Title:   ON THE SOUL

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Bookmarks





Page No 1


ON THE SOUL

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

ON THE SOUL...................................................................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

Book I.....................................................................................................................................................1

Book II..................................................................................................................................................13

Book III .................................................................................................................................................28


ON THE SOUL

i



Top




Page No 3


ON THE SOUL

by Aristotle

translated by J. A. Smith

Book I 

Book II 

Book III  

Book I

HOLDING as we do that, while knowledge of any kind is a thing to  be honoured and prized, one kind of it

may, either by reason of its  greater exactness or of a higher dignity and greater wonderfulness  in  its objects,

be more honourable and precious than another, on  both  accounts we should naturally be led to place in the

front rank  the  study of the soul. The knowledge of the soul admittedly  contributes  greatly to the advance of

truth in general, and, above  all, to our  understanding of Nature, for the soul is in some sense the  principle  of

animal life. Our aim is to grasp and understand, first  its  essential nature, and secondly its properties; of these

some are  taught to be affections proper to the soul itself, while others are  considered to attach to the animal

owing to the presence within it  of  soul. 

To attain any assured knowledge about the soul is one of the most  difficult things in the world. As the form of

question which here  presents itself, viz. the question 'What is it?', recurs in other  fields, it might be supposed

that there was some single method of  inquiry applicable to all objects whose essential nature (as we are

endeavouring to ascertain there is for derived properties the single  method of demonstration); in that case

what we should have to seek for  would be this unique method. But if there is no such single and  general

method for solving the question of essence, our task becomes  still more difficult; in the case of each different

subject we shall  have to determine the appropriate process of investigation. If to this  there be a clear answer,

e.g. that the process is demonstration or  division, or some known method, difficulties and hesitations still

beset uswith what facts shall we begin the inquiry? For the facts  which form the startingpoints in different

subjects must be  different, as e.g. in the case of numbers and surfaces. 

First, no doubt, it is necessary to determine in which of the  summa genera soul lies, what it is; is it 'a

thissomewhat, 'a  substance, or is it a quale or a quantum, or some other of the  remaining kinds of predicates

which we have distinguished? Further,  does soul belong to the class of potential existents, or is it not  rather

an actuality? Our answer to this question is of the greatest  importance. 

We must consider also whether soul is divisible or is without  parts,  and whether it is everywhere

homogeneous or not; and if not  homogeneous, whether its various forms are different specifically or

generically: up to the present time those who have discussed and  investigated soul seem to have confined

ON THE SOUL 1



Top




Page No 4


themselves to the human  soul.  We must be careful not to ignore the question whether soul can  be  defined in a

single unambiguous formula, as is the case with  animal,  or whether we must not give a separate formula for

each of it,  as we  do for horse, dog, man, god (in the latter case the  'universal'  animaland so too every other

'common predicate'being  treated either  as nothing at all or as a later product). Further, if  what exists is  not a

plurality of souls, but a plurality of parts of  one soul, which  ought we to investigate first, the whole soul or its

parts? (It is  also a difficult problem to decide which of these  parts are in nature  distinct from one another.)

Again, which ought  we to investigate  first, these parts or their functions, mind or  thinking, the faculty  or the

act of sensation, and so on? If the  investigation of the  functions precedes that of the parts, the further  question

suggests  itself: ought we not before either to consider the  correlative  objects, e.g. of sense or thought? It

seems not only  useful for the  discovery of the causes of the derived properties of  substances to be  acquainted

with the essential nature of those  substances (as in  mathematics it is useful for the understanding of  the

property of the  equality of the interior angles of a triangle to  two right angles to  know the essential nature of

the straight and  the curved or of the  line and the plane) but also conversely, for  the knowledge of the  essential

nature of a substance is largely  promoted by an acquaintance  with its properties: for, when we are able  to give

an account  conformable to experience of all or most of the  properties of a  substance, we shall be in the most

favourable position  to say  something worth saying about the essential nature of that  subject; in  all

demonstration a definition of the essence is  required as a  startingpoint, so that definitions which do not

enable us to discover  the derived properties, or which fail to  facilitate even a conjecture  about them, must

obviously, one and  all, be dialectical and futile. 

A further problem presented by the affections of soul is this: are  they all affections of the complex of body

and soul, or is there any  one among them peculiar to the soul by itself? To determine this is  indispensable but

difficult. If we consider the majority of them,  there seems to be no case in which the soul can act or be acted

upon  without involving the body; e.g. anger, courage, appetite, and  sensation generally. Thinking seems the

most probable exception; but  if this too proves to be a form of imagination or to be impossible  without

imagination, it too requires a body as a condition of its  existence. If there is any way of acting or being acted

upon proper to  soul, soul will be capable of separate existence; if there is none,  its separate existence is

impossible. In the latter case, it will be  like what is straight, which has many properties arising from the

straightness in it, e.g. that of touching a bronze sphere at a  point,  though straightness divorced from the other

constituents of the  straight thing cannot touch it in this way; it cannot be so divorced  at all, since it is always

found in a body. It therefore seems that  all the affections of soul involve a bodypassion, gentleness, fear,

pity, courage, joy, loving, and hating; in all these there is a  concurrent affection of the body. In support of this

we may point to  the fact that, while sometimes on the occasion of violent and striking  occurrences there is no

excitement or fear felt, on others faint and  feeble stimulations produce these emotions, viz. when the body is

already in a state of tension resembling its condition when we are  angry. Here is a still clearer case: in the

absence of any external  cause of terror we find ourselves experiencing the feelings of a man  in terror. From

all this it is obvious that the affections of soul are  enmattered formulable essences. 

Consequently their definitions ought to correspond, e.g. anger  should be defined as a certain mode of

movement of such and such a  body (or part or faculty of a body) by this or that cause and for this  or that end.

That is precisely why the study of the soul must fall  within the science of Nature, at least so far as in its

affections  it  manifests this double character. Hence a physicist would define  an  affection of soul differently

from a dialectician; the latter would  define e.g. anger as the appetite for returning pain for pain, or  something

like that, while the former would define it as a boiling  of  the blood or warm substance surround the heart. The

latter  assigns the  material conditions, the former the form or formulable  essence; for  what he states is the

formulable essence of the fact,  though for its  actual existence there must be embodiment of it in a  material

such as  is described by the other. Thus the essence of a  house is assigned in  such a formula as 'a shelter

against  destruction by wind, rain, and  heat'; the physicist would describe  it as 'stones, bricks, and  timbers'; but

there is a third possible  description which would say  that it was that form in that material  with that purpose or

end.  Which, then, among these is entitled to be  regarded as the genuine  physicist? The one who confines

himself to the  material, or the one  who restricts himself to the formulable essence  alone? Is it not  rather the


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 2



Top




Page No 5


one who combines both in a single formula?  If this is so,  how are we to characterize the other two? Must we

not  say that there  is no type of thinker who concerns himself with those  qualities or  attributes of the material

which are in fact  inseparable from the  material, and without attempting even in  thought to separate them? The

physicist is he who concerns himself  with all the properties active  and passive of bodies or materials thus  or

thus defined; attributes  not considered as being of this  character he leaves to others, in  certain cases it may be

to a  specialist, e.g. a carpenter or a  physician, in others (a) where  they are inseparable in fact, but are

separable from any particular  kind of body by an effort of  abstraction, to the mathematician, (b)  where they

are separate both in  fact and in thought from body  altogether, to the First Philosopher or  metaphysician. But

we must  return from this digression, and repeat  that the affections of soul  are inseparable from the material

substratum of animal life, to  which we have seen that such affections,  e.g. passion and fear,  attach, and have

not the same mode of being as  a line or a plane. 

For our study of soul it is necessary, while formulating the  problems of which in our further advance we are

to find the solutions,  to call into council the views of those of our predecessors who have  declared any

opinion on this subject, in order that we may profit by  whatever is sound in their suggestions and avoid their

errors. 

The startingpoint of our inquiry is an exposition of those  characteristics which have chiefly been held to

belong to soul in  its  very nature. Two characteristic marks have above all others been  recognized as

distinguishing that which has soul in it from that which  has notmovement and sensation. It may be said that

these two are what  our predecessors have fixed upon as characteristic of soul. 

Some say that what originates movement is both preeminently and  primarily soul; believing that what is not

itself moved cannot  originate movement in another, they arrived at the view that soul  belongs to the class of

things in movement. This is what led  Democritus to say that soul is a sort of fire or hot substance; his  'forms'

or atoms are infinite in number; those which are spherical  he  calls fire and soul, and compares them to the

motes in the air  which  we see in shafts of light coming through windows; the mixture of  seeds  of all sorts he

calls the elements of the whole of Nature  (Leucippus  gives a similar account); the spherical atoms are

identified with soul  because atoms of that shape are most adapted to  permeate everywhere,  and to set all the

others moving by being  themselves in movement. This  implies the view that soul is identical  with what

produces movement in  animals. That is why, further, they  regard respiration as the  characteristic mark of life;

as the  environment compresses the bodies  of animals, and tends to extrude  those atoms which impart

movement to  them, because they themselves are  never at rest, there must be a  reinforcement of these by

similar atoms  coming in from without in the  act of respiration; for they prevent the  extrusion of those which

are  already within by counteracting the  compressing and consolidating  force of the environment; and animals

continue to live only so long as  they are able to maintain this  resistance. 

The doctrine of the Pythagoreans seems to rest upon the same  ideas; some of them declared the motes in air,

others what moved them,  to be soul. These motes were referred to because they are seen  always  in

movement, even in a complete calm. 

The same tendency is shown by those who define soul as that which  moves itself; all seem to hold the view

that movement is what is  closest to the nature of soul, and that while all else is moved by  soul, it alone moves

itself. This belief arises from their never  seeing anything originating movement which is not first itself

moved. 

Similarly also Anaxagoras (and whoever agrees with him in saying  that mind set the whole in movement)

declares the moving cause of  things to be soul. His position must, however, be distinguished from  that of

Democritus. Democritus roundly identifies soul and mind, for  he identifies what appears with what is


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 3



Top




Page No 6


truethat is why he commends  Homer for the phrase 'Hector lay with thought distraught'; he does not  employ

mind as a special faculty dealing with truth, but identifies  soul and mind. What Anaxagoras says about them

is more obscure; in  many places he tells us that the cause of beauty and order is mind,  elsewhere that it is

soul; it is found, he says, in all animals, great  and small, high and low, but mind (in the sense of intelligence)

appears not to belong alike to all animals, and indeed not even to all  human beings. 

All those, then, who had special regard to the fact that what has  soul in it is moved, adopted the view that

soul is to be identified  with what is eminently originative of movement. All, on the other  hand, who looked to

the fact that what has soul in it knows or  perceives what is, identify soul with the principle or principles of

Nature, according as they admit several such principles or one only.  Thus Empedocles declares that it is

formed out of all his elements,  each of them also being soul; his words are: 

For 'tis by Earth we see Earth, by Water Water, 

By Ether Ether divine, by Fire destructive Fire, 

By Love Love, and Hate by cruel Hate. 

In the same way Plato in the Timaeus fashions soul out of his  elements; for like, he holds, is known by like,

and things are  formed  out of the principles or elements, so that soul must be so too.  Similarly also in his

lectures 'On Philosophy' it was set forth that  the Animalitself is compounded of the Idea itself of the One

together  with the primary length, breadth, and depth, everything else, the  objects of its perception, being

similarly constituted. Again he  puts  his view in yet other terms: Mind is the monad, science or  knowledge  the

dyad (because it goes undeviatingly from one point to  another),  opinion the number of the plane, sensation

the number of the  solid;  the numbers are by him expressly identified with the Forms  themselves  or principles,

and are formed out of the elements; now  things are  apprehended either by mind or science or opinion or

sensation, and  these same numbers are the Forms of things. 

Some thinkers, accepting both premisses, viz. that the soul is  both originative of movement and cognitive,

have compounded it of both  and declared the soul to be a selfmoving number. 

As to the nature and number of the first principles opinions  differ.  The difference is greatest between those

who regard them as  corporeal and those who regard them as incorporeal, and from both  dissent those who

make a blend and draw their principles from both  sources. The number of principles is also in dispute; some

admit one  only, others assert several. There is a consequent diversity in  their  several accounts of soul; they

assume, naturally enough, that  what is  in its own nature originative of movement must be among what  is

primordial. That has led some to regard it as fire, for fire is the  subtlest of the elements and nearest to

incorporeality; further, in  the most primary sense, fire both is moved and originates movement  in  all the

others. 

Democritus has expressed himself more ingeniously than the rest on  the grounds for ascribing each of these

two characters to soul; soul  and mind are, he says, one and the same thing, and this thing must  be  one of the

primary and indivisible bodies, and its power of  originating movement must be due to its fineness of grain

and the  shape of its atoms; he says that of all the shapes the spherical is  the most mobile, and that this is the

shape of the particles of fire  and mind. 

Anaxagoras, as we said above, seems to distinguish between soul  and mind, but in practice he treats them as a

single substance, except  that it is mind that he specially posits as the principle of all  things; at any rate what

he says is that mind alone of all that is  simple, unmixed, and pure. He assigns both characteristics, knowing

and origination of movement, to the same principle, when he says  that  it was mind that set the whole in

movement. 


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 4



Top




Page No 7


Thales, too, to judge from what is recorded about him, seems to  have  held soul to be a motive force, since he

said that the magnet has  a  soul in it because it moves the iron. 

Diogenes (and others) held the soul to be air because he believed  air to be finest in grain and a first principle;

therein lay the  grounds of the soul's powers of knowing and originating movement. As  the primordial

principle from which all other things are derived, it  is cognitive; as finest in grain, it has the power to

originate  movement. 

Heraclitus too says that the first principlethe 'warm exhalation'  of which, according to him, everything else

is composedis soul;  further, that this exhalation is most incorporeal and in ceaseless  flux; that what is in

movement requires that what knows it should be  in movement; and that all that is has its being essentially in

movement (herein agreeing with the majority). 

Alcmaeon also seems to have held a similar view about soul; he  says that it is immortal because it resembles

'the immortals,' and  that this immortality belongs to it in virtue of its ceaseless  movement; for all the 'things

divine,' moon, sun, the planets, and the  whole heavens, are in perpetual movement. 

of More superficial writers, some, e.g. Hippo, have pronounced it  to  be water; they seem to have argued from

the fact that the seed of  all animals is fluid, for Hippo tries to refute those who say that the  soul is blood, on

the ground that the seed, which is the primordial  soul, is not blood. 

Another group (Critias, for example) did hold it to be blood; they  take perception to be the most characteristic

attribute of soul, and  hold that perceptiveness is due to the nature of blood. 

Each of the elements has thus found its partisan, except  earthearth  has found no supporter unless we count

as such those who  have declared  soul to be, or to be compounded of, all the elements.  All, then, it  may be

said, characterize the soul by three marks,  Movement,  Sensation, Incorporeality, and each of these is traced

back  to the  first principles. That is why (with one exception) all those  who  define the soul by its power of

knowing make it either an element  or  constructed out of the elements. The language they all use is  similar;

like, they say, is known by like; as the soul knows  everything, they  construct it out of all the principles.

Hence all  those who admit  but one cause or element, make the soul also one (e.g.  fire or air),  while those who

admit a multiplicity of principles make  the soul  also multiple. The exception is Anaxagoras; he alone says

that mind is  impassible and has nothing in common with anything else.  But, if  this is so, how or in virtue of

what cause can it know? That  Anaxagoras has not explained, nor can any answer be inferred from  his  words.

All who acknowledge pairs of opposites among their  principles,  construct the soul also out of these

contraries, while  those who admit  as principles only one contrary of each pair, e.g.  either hot or cold,  likewise

make the soul some one of these. That  is why, also, they  allow themselves to be guided by the names; those

who identify soul  with the hot argue that sen (to live) is derived  from sein (to boil),  while those who identify

it with the cold say  that soul (psuche) is so  called from the process of respiration and  (katapsuxis). Such are

the  traditional opinions concerning soul,  together with the grounds on  which they are maintained. 

We must begin our examination with movement; for doubtless, not  only  is it false that the essence of soul is

correctly described by  those  who say that it is what moves (or is capable of moving) itself,  but it  is an

impossibility that movement should be even an attribute  of it. 

We have already pointed out that there is no necessity that what  originates movement should itself be moved.

There are two senses in  which anything may be movedeither (a) indirectly, owing to  something  other than

itself, or (b) directly, owing to itself.  Things are  'indirectly moved' which are moved as being contained in

something  which is moved, e.g. sailors in a ship, for they are moved  in a  different sense from that in which


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 5



Top




Page No 8


the ship is moved; the ship is  'directly moved', they are 'indirectly moved', because they are in a  moving

vessel. This is clear if we consider their limbs; the  movement  proper to the legs (and so to man) is walking,

and in this  case the  sailors tare not walking. Recognizing the double sense of  'being  moved', what we have to

consider now is whether the soul is  'directly  moved' and participates in such direct movement. 

There are four species of movementlocomotion, alteration,  diminution, growth; consequently if the soul is

moved, it must be  moved with one or several or all of these species of movement. Now  if  its movement is not

incidental, there must be a movement natural to  it, and, if so, as all the species enumerated involve place,

place  must be natural to it. But if the essence of soul be to move itself,  its being moved cannot be incidental

toas it is to what is white or  three cubits long; they too can be moved, but only incidentallywhat  is moved

is that of which 'white' and 'three cubits long' are the  attributes, the body in which they inhere; hence they

have no place:  but if the soul naturally partakes in movement, it follows that it  must have a place. 

Further, if there be a movement natural to the soul, there must be  a  countermovement unnatural to it, and

conversely. The same applies  to rest as well as to movement; for the terminus ad quem of a  thing's  natural

movement is the place of its natural rest, and  similarly the  terminus ad quem of its enforced movement is the

place  of its enforced  rest. But what meaning can be attached to enforced  movements or rests  of the soul, it is

difficult even to imagine. 

Further, if the natural movement of the soul be upward, the soul  must be fire; if downward, it must be earth;

for upward and downward  movements are the definitory characteristics of these bodies. The same  reasoning

applies to the intermediate movements, termini, and  bodies.  Further, since the soul is observed to originate

movement in  the body,  it is reasonable to suppose that it transmits to the body  the  movements by which it

itself is moved, and so, reversing the  order, we  may infer from the movements of the body back to similar

movements of  the soul. Now the body is moved from place to place  with movements of  locomotion. Hence it

would follow that the soul  too must in accordance  with the body change either its place as a  whole or the

relative  places of its parts. This carries with it the  possibility that the  soul might even quit its body and

reenter it,  and with this would be  involved the possibility of a resurrection of  animals from the dead.  But, it

may be contended, the soul can be moved  indirectly by  something else; for an animal can be pushed out of its

course. Yes,  but that to whose essence belongs the power of being  moved by itself,  cannot be moved by

something else except  incidentally, just as what is  good by or in itself cannot owe its  goodness to something

external to  it or to some end to which it is a  means. 

If the soul is moved, the most probable view is that what moves it  is sensible things. 

We must note also that, if the soul moves itself, it must be the  mover itself that is moved, so that it follows

that if movement is  in  every case a displacement of that which is in movement, in that  respect in which it is

said to be moved, the movement of the soul must  be a departure from its essential nature, at least if its

selfmovement is essential to it, not incidental. 

Some go so far as to hold that the movements which the soul  imparts to the body in which it is are the same

in kind as those  with  which it itself is moved. An example of this is Democritus, who  uses  language like that

of the comic dramatist Philippus, who accounts  for  the movements that Daedalus imparted to his wooden

Aphrodite by  saying  that he poured quicksilver into it; similarly Democritus says  that the  spherical atoms

which according to him constitute soul, owing  to their  own ceaseless movements draw the whole body after

them and so  produce  its movements. We must urge the question whether it is these  very same  atoms which

produce rest alsohow they could do so, it is  difficult  and even impossible to say. And, in general, we may

object  that it is  not in this way that the soul appears to originate movement  in  animalsit is through intention

or process of thinking. 


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 6



Top




Page No 9


It is in the same fashion that the Timaeus also tries to give a  physical account of how the soul moves its body;

the soul, it is there  said, is in movement, and so owing to their mutual implication moves  the body also. After

compounding the soulsubstance out of the  elements and dividing it in accordance with the harmonic

numbers, in  order that it may possess a connate sensibility for 'harmony' and that  the whole may move in

movements well attuned, the Demiurge bent the  straight line into a circle; this single circle he divided into

two  circles united at two common points; one of these he subdivided into  seven circles. All this implies that

the movements of the soul are  identified with the local movements of the heavens. 

Now, in the first place, it is a mistake to say that the soul is a  spatial magnitude. It is evident that Plato means

the soul of the  whole to be like the sort of soul which is called mind not like the  sensitive or the desiderative

soul, for the movements of neither of  these are circular. Now mind is one and continuous in the sense in

which the process of thinking is so, and thinking is identical with  the thoughts which are its parts; these have

a serial unity like  that  of number, not a unity like that of a spatial magnitude. Hence  mind  cannot have that

kind of unity either; mind is either without  parts or  is continuous in some other way than that which

characterizes  a  spatial magnitude. How, indeed, if it were a spatial magnitude,  could  mind possibly think?

Will it think with any one indifferently of  its  parts? In this case, the 'part' must be understood either in the

sense  of a spatial magnitude or in the sense of a point (if a point  can be  called a part of a spatial magnitude).

If we accept the  latter  alternative, the points being infinite in number, obviously the  mind  can never

exhaustively traverse them; if the former, the mind  must  think the same thing over and over again, indeed an

infinite  number of  times (whereas it is manifestly possible to think a thing  once only).  If contact of any part

whatsoever of itself with the  object is all  that is required, why need mind move in a circle, or  indeed possess

magnitude at all? On the other hand, if contact with  the whole circle  is necessary, what meaning can be given

to the  contact of the parts?  Further, how could what has no parts think  what has parts, or what has  parts think

what has none? We must  identify the circle referred to  with mind; for it is mind whose  movement is thinking,

and it is the  circle whose movement is  revolution, so that if thinking is a movement  of revolution, the  circle

which has this characteristic movement must  be mind. 

If the circular movement is eternal, there must be something which  mind is always thinkingwhat can this

be? For all practical  processes  of thinking have limitsthey all go on for the sake of  something  outside the

process, and all theoretical processes come to a  close in  the same way as the phrases in speech which express

processes  and  results of thinking. Every such linguistic phrase is either  definitory  or demonstrative.

Demonstration has both a startingpoint  and may be  said to end in a conclusion or inferred result; even if the

process  never reaches final completion, at any rate it never returns  upon  itself again to its startingpoint, it

goes on assuming a fresh  middle  term or a fresh extreme, and moves straight forward, but  circular  movement

returns to its startingpoint. Definitions, too, are  closed  groups of terms. 

Further, if the same revolution is repeated, mind must repeatedly  think the same object. 

Further, thinking has more resemblance to a coming to rest or  arrest  than to a movement; the same may be

said of inferring. 

It might also be urged that what is difficult and enforced is  incompatible with blessedness; if the movement

of the soul is not of  its essence, movement of the soul must be contrary to its nature. It  must also be painful

for the soul to be inextricably bound up with the  body; nay more, if, as is frequently said and widely

accepted, it is  better for mind not to be embodied, the union must be for it  undesirable. 

Further, the cause of the revolution of the heavens is left  obscure.  It is not the essence of soul which is the

cause of this  circular  movementthat movement is only incidental to soulnor is, a  fortiori, the body its

cause. Again, it is not even asserted that it  is better that soul should be so moved; and yet the reason for

which  God caused the soul to move in a circle can only have been that  movement was better for it than rest,

and movement of this kind better  than any other. But since this sort of consideration is more  appropriate to


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 7



Top




Page No 10


another field of speculation, let us dismiss it for the  present. 

The view we have just been examining, in company with most  theories about the soul, involves the following

absurdity: they all  join the soul to a body, or place it in a body, without adding any  specification of the reason

of their union, or of the bodily  conditions required for it. Yet such explanation can scarcely be  omitted; for

some community of nature is presupposed by the fact  that  the one acts and the other is acted upon, the one

moves and the  other  is moved; interaction always implies a special nature in the two  interagents. All,

however, that these thinkers do is to describe the  specific characteristics of the soul; they do not try to

determine  anything about the body which is to contain it, as if it were  possible, as in the Pythagorean myths,

that any soul could be  clothed  upon with any bodyan absurd view, for each body seems to have  a form  and

shape of its own. It is as absurd as to say that the art of  carpentry could embody itself in flutes; each art must

use its  tools,  each soul its body. 

There is yet another theory about soul, which has commended itself  to many as no less probable than any of

those we have hitherto  mentioned, and has rendered public account of itself in the court of  popular

discussion. Its supporters say that the soul is a kind of  harmony, for (a) harmony is a blend or composition of

contraries,  and  (b) the body is compounded out of contraries. Harmony, however, is  a  certain proportion or

composition of the constituents blended, and  soul can be neither the one nor the other of these. Further, the

power  of originating movement cannot belong to a harmony, while almost all  concur in regarding this as a

principal attribute of soul. It is  more  appropriate to call health (or generally one of the good states  of the

body) a harmony than to predicate it of the soul. The absurdity  becomes most apparent when we try to

attribute the active and  passive  affections of the soul to a harmony; the necessary  readjustment of  their

conceptions is difficult. Further, in using  the word 'harmony'  we have one or other of two cases in our mind;

the most proper sense  is in relation to spatial magnitudes which  have motion and position,  where harmony

means the disposition and  cohesion of their parts in  such a manner as to prevent the  introduction into the

whole of  anything homogeneous with it, and the  secondary sense, derived from  the former, is that in which it

means  the ratio between the  constituents so blended; in neither of these  senses is it plausible to  predicate it of

soul. That soul is a harmony  in the sense of the mode  of composition of the parts of the body is  a view easily

refutable;  for there are many composite parts and  those variously compounded; of  what bodily part is mind or

the  sensitive or the appetitive faculty  the mode of composition? And  what is the mode of composition which

constitutes each of them? It  is equally absurd to identify the soul  with the ratio of the  mixture; for the mixture

which makes flesh has a  different ratio  between the elements from that which makes bone. The  consequence

of  this view will therefore be that distributed throughout  the whole body  there will be many souls, since every

one of the bodily  parts is a  different mixture of the elements, and the ratio of mixture  is in each  case a

harmony, i.e. a soul. 

From Empedocles at any rate we might demand an answer to the  following question for he says that each of

the parts of the body is  what it is in virtue of a ratio between the elements: is the soul  identical with this ratio,

or is it not rather something over and  above this which is formed in the parts? Is love the cause of any  and

every mixture, or only of those that are in the right ratio? Is  love  this ratio itself, or is love something over

and above this? Such  are  the problems raised by this account. But, on the other hand, if  the  soul is different

from the mixture, why does it disappear at one  and  the same moment with that relation between the elements

which  constitutes flesh or the other parts of the animal body? Further, if  the soul is not identical with the ratio

of mixture, and it is  consequently not the case that each of the parts has a soul, what is  that which perishes

when the soul quits the body? 

That the soul cannot either be a harmony, or be moved in a circle,  is clear from what we have said. Yet that it

can be moved incidentally  is, as we said above, possible, and even that in a sense it can move  itself, i.e. in the

sense that the vehicle in which it is can be  moved, and moved by it; in no other sense can the soul be moved


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 8



Top




Page No 11


in  space. 

More legitimate doubts might remain as to its movement in view of  the following facts. We speak of the soul

as being pained or  pleased,  being bold or fearful, being angry, perceiving, thinking. All  these  are regarded as

modes of movement, and hence it might be  inferred that  the soul is moved. This, however, does not

necessarily  follow. We may  admit to the full that being pained or pleased, or  thinking, are  movements (each

of them a 'being moved'), and that the  movement is  originated by the soul. For example we may regard anger

or  fear as  such and such movements of the heart, and thinking as such and  such  another movement of that

organ, or of some other; these  modifications  may arise either from changes of place in certain  parts or from

qualitative alterations (the special nature of the parts  and the  special modes of their changes being for our

present purpose  irrelevant). Yet to say that it is the soul which is angry is as  inexact as it would be to say that

it is the soul that weaves webs  or  builds houses. It is doubtless better to avoid saying that the soul  pities or

learns or thinks and rather to say that it is the man who  does this with his soul. What we mean is not that the

movement is in  the soul, but that sometimes it terminates in the soul and sometimes  starts from it, sensation

e.g. coming from without inwards, and  reminiscence starting from the soul and terminating with the

movements, actual or residual, in the sense organs. 

The case of mind is different; it seems to be an independent  substance implanted within the soul and to be

incapable of being  destroyed. If it could be destroyed at all, it would be under the  blunting influence of old

age. What really happens in respect of  mind  in old age is, however, exactly parallel to what happens in the

case  of the sense organs; if the old man could recover the proper kind  of  eye, he would see just as well as the

young man. The incapacity  of old  age is due to an affection not of the soul but of its  vehicle, as  occurs in

drunkenness or disease. Thus it is that in old  age the  activity of mind or intellectual apprehension declines

only  through  the decay of some other inward part; mind itself is  impassible.  Thinking, loving, and hating are

affections not of mind,  but of that  which has mind, so far as it has it. That is why, when  this vehicle  decays,

memory and love cease; they were activities not  of mind, but  of the composite which has perished; mind is,

no doubt,  something more  divine and impassible. That the soul cannot be moved is  therefore  clear from what

we have said, and if it cannot be moved at  all,  manifestly it cannot be moved by itself. 

Of all the opinions we have enumerated, by far the most  unreasonable  is that which declares the soul to be a

selfmoving  number; it  involves in the first place all the impossibilities which  follow  from regarding the soul

as moved, and in the second special  absurdities which follow from calling it a number. How we to imagine a

unit being moved? By what agency? What sort of movement can be  attributed to what is without parts or

internal differences? If the  unit is both originative of movement and itself capable of being  moved, it must

contain difference. 

Further, since they say a moving line generates a surface and a  moving point a line, the movements of the

psychic units must be  lines  (for a point is a unit having position, and the number of the  soul is,  of course,

somewhere and has position). 

Again, if from a number a number or a unit is subtracted, the  remainder is another number; but plants and

many animals when  divided  continue to live, and each segment is thought to retain the  same kind  of soul. 

It must be all the same whether we speak of units or corpuscles;  for  if the spherical atoms of Democritus

became points, nothing being  retained but their being a quantum, there must remain in each a moving  and a

moved part, just as there is in what is continuous; what happens  has nothing to do with the size of the atoms,

it depends solely upon  their being a quantum. That is why there must be something to  originate movement in

the units. If in the animal what originates  movement is the soul, so also must it be in the case of the number,

so  that not the mover and the moved together, but the mover only, will be  the soul. But how is it possible for

one of the units to fulfil this  function of originating movement? There must be some difference  between such

a unit and all the other units, and what difference can  there be between one placed unit and another except a


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 9



Top




Page No 12


difference of  position? If then, on the other hand, these psychic units within the  body are different from the

points of the body, there will be two sets  of units both occupying the same place; for each unit will occupy a

point. And yet, if there can be two, why cannot there be an infinite  number? For if things can occupy an

indivisible lace, they must  themselves be indivisible. If, on the other hand, the points of the  body are identical

with the units whose number is the soul, or if  the  number of the points in the body is the soul, why have not

all  bodies  souls? For all bodies contain points or an infinity of points. 

Further, how is it possible for these points to be isolated or  separated from their bodies, seeing that lines

cannot be resolved into  points? 

The result is, as we have said, that this view, while on the one  side identical with that of those who maintain

that soul is a subtle  kind of body, is on the other entangled in the absurdity peculiar to  Democritus' way of

describing the manner in which movement is  originated by soul. For if the soul is present throughout the

whole  percipient body, there must, if the soul be a kind of body, be two  bodies in the same place; and for

those who call it a number, there  must be many points at one point, or every body must have a soul,  unless

the soul be a different sort of numberother, that is, than the  sum of the points existing in a body. Another

consequence that follows  is that the animal must be moved by its number precisely in the way  that

Democritus explained its being moved by his spherical psychic  atoms. What difference does it make whether

we speak of small  spheres  or of large units, or, quite simply, of units in movement? One  way or  another, the

movements of the animal must be due to their  movements.  Hence those who combine movement and number

in the same  subject lay  themselves open to these and many other similar  absurdities. It is  impossible not only

that these characters should  give the definition  of soulit is impossible that they should even  be attributes of

it.  The point is clear if the attempt be made to  start from this as the  account of soul and explain from it the

affections and actions of the  soul, e.g. reasoning, sensation,  pleasure, pain, For, to repeat what  we have said

earlier, movement  and number do not facilitate even  conjecture about the derivative  properties of soul. 

Such are the three ways in which soul has traditionally been  defined; one group of thinkers declared it to be

that which is most  originative of movement because it moves itself, another group to be  the subtlest and most

nearly incorporeal of all kinds of body. We have  now sufficiently set forth the difficulties and inconsistencies

to  which these theories are exposed. It remains now to examine the  doctrine that soul is composed of the

elements. 

The reason assigned for this doctrine is that thus the soul may  perceive or come to know everything that is,

but the theory  necessarily involves itself in many impossibilities. Its upholders  assume that like is known

only by like, and imagine that by  declaring  the soul to be composed of the elements they succeed in

identifying  the soul with all the things it is capable of  apprehending. But the  elements are not the only things

it knows; there  are many others, or,  more exactly, an infinite number of others,  formed out of the  elements.

Let us admit that the soul knows or  perceives the elements  out of which each of these composites is made  up;

but by what means  will it know or perceive the composite whole,  e.g. what God, man,  flesh, bone (or any

other compound) is? For each  is, not merely the  elements of which it is composed, but those  elements

combined in a  determinate mode or ratio, as Empedocles  himself says of bone, 

The kindly Earth in its broadbosomed moulds 

Won of clear Water two parts out of eight, 

And four of Fire; and so white bones were formed. 


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 10



Top




Page No 13


Nothing, therefore, will be gained by the presence of the elements  in the soul, unless there be also present

there the various formulae  of proportion and the various compositions in accordance with them.  Each element

will indeed know its fellow outside, but there will be no  knowledge of bone or man, unless they too are

present in the  constitution of the soul. The impossibility of this needs no  pointing  out; for who would suggest

that stone or man could enter into  the  constitution of the soul? The same applies to 'the good' and  'the

notgood', and so on. 

Further, the word 'is' has many meanings: it may be used of a  'this'  or substance, or of a quantum, or of a

quale, or of any other  of the  kinds of predicates we have distinguished. Does the soul  consist of  all of these or

not? It does not appear that all have  common elements.  Is the soul formed out of those elements alone which

enter into  substances? so how will it be able to know each of the  other kinds  of thing? Will it be said that each

kind of thing has  elements or  principles of its own, and that the soul is formed out of  the whole of  these? In

that case, the soul must be a quantum and a  quale and a  substance. But all that can be made out of the

elements of  a quantum  is a quantum, not a substance. These (and others like them)  are the  consequences of

the view that the soul is composed of all the  elements. 

It is absurd, also, to say both (a) that like is not capable of  being affected by like, and (b) that like is perceived

or known by  like, for perceiving, and also both thinking and knowing, are, on  their own assumption, ways of

being affected or moved. 

There are many puzzles and difficulties raised by saying, as  Empedocles does, that each set of things is

known by means of its  corporeal elements and by reference to something in soul which is like  them, and

additional testimony is furnished by this new consideration;  for all the parts of the animal body which consist

wholly of earth  such as bones, sinews, and hair seem to be wholly insensitive and  consequently not

perceptive even of objects earthy like themselves, as  they ought to have been. 

Further, each of the principles will have far more ignorance than  knowledge, for though each of them will

know one thing, there will  be  many of which it will be ignorant. Empedocles at any rate must  conclude that

his God is the least intelligent of all beings, for of  him alone is it true that there is one thing, Strife, which he

does  not know, while there is nothing which mortal beings do not know,  for  ere is nothing which does not

enter into their composition. 

In general, we may ask, Why has not everything a soul, since  everything either is an element, or is formed out

of one or several or  all of the elements? Each must certainly know one or several or all. 

The problem might also be raised, What is that which unifies the  elements into a soul? The elements

correspond, it would appear, to the  matter; what unites them, whatever it is, is the supremely important  factor.

But it is impossible that there should be something superior  to, and dominant over, the soul (and a fortiori

over the mind); it  is  reasonable to hold that mind is by nature most primordial and  dominant, while their

statement that it is the elements which are  first of all that is. 

All, both those who assert that the soul, because of its knowledge  or perception of what is compounded out of

the elements, and is  those  who assert that it is of all things the most originative of  movement,  fail to take into

consideration all kinds of soul. In fact  (1) not all  beings that perceive can originate movement; there  appear to

be  certain animals which stationary, and yet local  movement is the only  one, so it seems, which the soul

originates in  animals. And (2) the  same objecton holds against all those who  construct mind and the

perceptive faculty out of the elements; for  it appears that plants  live, and yet are not endowed with

locomotion  or perception, while a  large number of animals are without discourse  of reason. Even if these

points were waived and mind admitted to be  a part of the soul (and so  too the perceptive faculty), still, even

so, there would be kinds and  parts of soul of which they had failed to  give any account. 


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 11



Top




Page No 14


The same objection lies against the view expressed in the 'Orphic'  poems: there it is said that the soul comes

in from the whole when  breathing takes place, being borne in upon the winds. Now this  cannot  take place in

the case of plants, nor indeed in the case of  certain  classes of animal, for not all classes of animal breathe.

This  fact  has escaped the notice of the holders of this view. 

If we must construct the soul out of the elements, there is no  necessity to suppose that all the elements enter

into its  construction; one element in each pair of contraries will suffice to  enable it to know both that element

itself and its contrary. By  means  of the straight line we know both itself and the curvedthe  carpenter's rule

enables us to test bothbut what is curved does not  enable us to distinguish either itself or the straight.

Certain  thinkers say that soul is intermingled in the whole universe, and it  is perhaps for that reason that

Thales came to the opinion that all  things are full of gods. This presents some difficulties: Why does the  soul

when it resides in air or fire not form an animal, while it  does  so when it resides in mixtures of the elements,

and that although  it  is held to be of higher quality when contained in the former?  (One  might add the

question, why the soul in air is maintained to be  higher  and more immortal than that in animals.) Both

possible ways  of  replying to the former question lead to absurdity or paradox; for  it  is beyond paradox to say

that fire or air is an animal, and it is  absurd to refuse the name of animal to what has soul in it. The  opinion

that the elements have soul in them seems to have arisen  from  the doctrine that a whole must be

homogeneous with its parts.  If it is  true that animals become animate by drawing into themselves a  portion  of

what surrounds them, the partisans of this view are bound  to say  that the soul of the Whole too is

homogeneous with all its  parts. If  the air sucked in is homogeneous, but soul heterogeneous,  clearly  while

some part of soul will exist in the inbreathed air, some  other  part will not. The soul must either be

homogeneous, or such that  there  are some parts of the Whole in which it is not to be found. 

From what has been said it is now clear that knowing as an  attribute  of soul cannot be explained by soul's

being composed of the  elements, and that it is neither sound nor true to speak of soul as  moved. But since (a)

knowing, perceiving, opining, and further (b)  desiring, wishing, and generally all other modes of appetition,

belong  to soul, and (c) the local movements of animals, and (d) growth,  maturity, and decay are produced by

the soul, we must ask whether each  of these is an attribute of the soul as a whole, i.e. whether it is  with the

whole soul we think, perceive, move ourselves, act or are  acted upon, or whether each of them requires a

different part of the  soul? So too with regard to life. Does it depend on one of the parts  of soul? Or is it

dependent on more than one? Or on all? Or has it  some quite other cause? 

Some hold that the soul is divisible, and that one part thinks,  another desires. If, then, its nature admits of its

being divided,  what can it be that holds the parts together? Surely not the body;  on  the contrary it seems

rather to be the soul that holds the body  together; at any rate when the soul departs the body disintegrates and

decays. If, then, there is something else which makes the soul one,  this unifying agency would have the best

right to the name of soul,  and we shall have to repeat for it the question: Is it one or  multipartite? If it is one,

why not at once admit that 'the soul' is  one? If it has parts, once more the question must be put: What holds  its

parts together, and so ad infinitum? 

The question might also be raised about the parts of the soul:  What is the separate role of each in relation to

the body? For, if the  whole soul holds together the whole body, we should expect each part  of the soul to hold

together a part of the body. But this seems an  impossibility; it is difficult even to imagine what sort of bodily

part mind will hold together, or how it will do this. 

It is a fact of observation that plants and certain insects go on  living when divided into segments; this means

that each of the  segments has a soul in it identical in species, though not numerically  identical in the different

segments, for both of the segments for a  time possess the power of sensation and local movement. That this

does  not last is not surprising, for they no longer possess the organs  necessary for selfmaintenance. But, all

the same, in each of the  bodily parts there are present all the parts of soul, and the souls so  present are

homogeneous with one another and with the whole; this  means that the several parts of the soul are


ON THE SOUL

ON THE SOUL 12



Top




Page No 15


indisseverable from one  another, although the whole soul is divisible. It seems also that  the  principle found in

plants is also a kind of soul; for this is  the only  principle which is common to both animals and plants; and

this exists  in isolation from the principle of sensation, though there  nothing  which has the latter without the

former. 

Book II

LET the foregoing suffice as our account of the views concerning  the  soul which have been handed on by our

predecessors; let us now  dismiss  them and make as it were a completely fresh start,  endeavouring to  give a

precise answer to the question, What is soul?  i.e. to formulate  the most general possible definition of it. 

We are in the habit of recognizing, as one determinate kind of  what is, substance, and that in several senses,

(a) in the sense of  matter or that which in itself is not 'a this', and (b) in the sense  of form or essence, which is

that precisely in virtue of which a thing  is called 'a this', and thirdly (c) in the sense of that which is

compounded of both (a) and (b). Now matter is potentiality, form  actuality; of the latter there are two grades

related to one another  as e.g. knowledge to the exercise of knowledge. 

Among substances are by general consent reckoned bodies and  especially natural bodies; for they are the

principles of all other  bodies. Of natural bodies some have life in them, others not; by  life  we mean

selfnutrition and growth (with its correlative decay).  It  follows that every natural body which has life in it is

a substance  in  the sense of a composite. 

But since it is also a body of such and such a kind, viz. having  life, the body cannot be soul; the body is the

subject or matter,  not  what is attributed to it. Hence the soul must be a substance in  the  sense of the form of a

natural body having life potentially within  it.  But substance is actuality, and thus soul is the actuality of a

body  as above characterized. Now the word actuality has two senses  corresponding respectively to the

possession of knowledge and the  actual exercise of knowledge. It is obvious that the soul is actuality  in the

first sense, viz. that of knowledge as possessed, for both  sleeping and waking presuppose the existence of

soul, and of these  waking corresponds to actual knowing, sleeping to knowledge  possessed  but not employed,

and, in the history of the individual,  knowledge  comes before its employment or exercise. 

That is why the soul is the first grade of actuality of a natural  body having life potentially in it. The body so

described is a body  which is organized. The parts of plants in spite of their extreme  simplicity are 'organs';

e.g. the leaf serves to shelter the pericarp,  the pericarp to shelter the fruit, while the roots of plants are

analogous to the mouth of animals, both serving for the absorption  of  food. If, then, we have to give a general

formula applicable to all  kinds of soul, we must describe it as the first grade of actuality  of  a natural

organized body. That is why we can wholly dismiss as  unnecessary the question whether the soul and the

body are one: it  is  as meaningless as to ask whether the wax and the shape given to  it by  the stamp are one, or

generally the matter of a thing and that  of  which it is the matter. Unity has many senses (as many as 'is'  has),

but the most proper and fundamental sense of both is the  relation of  an actuality to that of which it is the

actuality. We have  now given  an answer to the question, What is soul?an answer which  applies to it  in its

full extent. It is substance in the sense which  corresponds to  the definitive formula of a thing's essence. That

means  that it is  'the essential whatness' of a body of the character just  assigned.  Suppose that what is literally

an 'organ', like an axe, were  a natural  body, its 'essential whatness', would have been its essence,  and so  its

soul; if this disappeared from it, it would have ceased  to be an  axe, except in name. As it is, it is just an axe; it

wants  the  character which is required to make its whatness or formulable  essence  a soul; for that, it would

have had to be a natural body of  a  particular kind, viz. one having in itself the power of setting  itself  in

movement and arresting itself. Next, apply this doctrine  in the  case of the 'parts' of the living body. Suppose


ON THE SOUL

Book II 13



Top




Page No 16


that the eye  were an  animalsight would have been its soul, for sight is the  substance or  essence of the eye

which corresponds to the formula,  the eye being  merely the matter of seeing; when seeing is removed  the eye

is no  longer an eye, except in nameit is no more a real eye  than the eye of  a statue or of a painted figure. We

must now extend  our consideration  from the 'parts' to the whole living body; for  what the departmental  sense

is to the bodily part which is its  organ, that the whole faculty  of sense is to the whole sensitive  body as such. 

We must not understand by that which is 'potentially capable of  living' what has lost the soul it had, but only

what still retains it;  but seeds and fruits are bodies which possess the qualification.  Consequently, while

waking is actuality in a sense corresponding to  the cutting and the seeing, the soul is actuality in the sense

corresponding to the power of sight and the power in the tool; the  body corresponds to what exists in

potentiality; as the pupil plus the  power of sight constitutes the eye, so the soul plus the body  constitutes the

animal. 

From this it indubitably follows that the soul is inseparable from  its body, or at any rate that certain parts of it

are (if it has  parts) for the actuality of some of them is nothing but the  actualities of their bodily parts. Yet

some may be separable because  they are not the actualities of any body at all. Further, we have no  light on the

problem whether the soul may not be the actuality of  its  body in the sense in which the sailor is the actuality

of the  ship. 

This must suffice as our sketch or outline determination of the  nature of soul. 

Since what is clear or logically more evident emerges from what in  itself is confused but more observable by

us, we must reconsider our  results from this point of view. For it is not enough for a definitive  formula to

express as most now do the mere fact; it must include and  exhibit the ground also. At present definitions are

given in a form  analogous to the conclusion of a syllogism; e.g. What is squaring? The  construction of an

equilateral rectangle equal to a given oblong  rectangle. Such a definition is in form equivalent to a

conclusion.  One that tells us that squaring is the discovery of a line which is  a  mean proportional between the

two unequal sides of the given  rectangle  discloses the ground of what is defined. 

We resume our inquiry from a fresh startingpoint by calling  attention to the fact that what has soul in it

differs from what has  not, in that the former displays life. Now this word has more than one  sense, and

provided any one alone of these is found in a thing we  say  that thing is living. Living, that is, may mean

thinking or  perception  or local movement and rest, or movement in the sense of  nutrition,  decay and growth.

Hence we think of plants also as  living, for they  are observed to possess in themselves an  originative power

through  which they increase or decrease in all  spatial directions; they grow  up and down, and everything that

grows  increases its bulk alike in  both directions or indeed in all, and  continues to live so long as it  can absorb

nutriment. 

This power of selfnutrition can be isolated from the other powers  mentioned, but not they from itin mortal

beings at least. The fact is  obvious in plants; for it is the only psychic power they possess. 

This is the originative power the possession of which leads us to  speak of things as living at all, but it is the

possession of  sensation that leads us for the first time to speak of living things  as animals; for even those

beings which possess no power of local  movement but do possess the power of sensation we call animals and

not  merely living things. 

The primary form of sense is touch, which belongs to all animals.  just as the power of selfnutrition can be

isolated from touch and  sensation generally, so touch can be isolated from all other forms  of  sense. (By the

power of selfnutrition we mean that departmental  power  of the soul which is common to plants and animals:


ON THE SOUL

Book II 14



Top




Page No 17


all animals  whatsoever are observed to have the sense of touch.) What the  explanation of these two facts is,

we must discuss later. At present  we must confine ourselves to saying that soul is the source of these

phenomena and is characterized by them, viz. by the powers of  selfnutrition, sensation, thinking, and

motivity. 

Is each of these a soul or a part of a soul? And if a part, a part  in what sense? A part merely distinguishable

by definition or a part  distinct in local situation as well? In the case of certain of these  powers, the answers to

these questions are easy, in the case of others  we are puzzled what to say. just as in the case of plants which

when  divided are observed to continue to live though removed to a  distance  from one another (thus showing

that in their case the soul of  each  individual plant before division was actually one, potentially  many),  so we

notice a similar result in other varieties of soul,  i.e. in  insects which have been cut in two; each of the

segments  possesses  both sensation and local movement; and if sensation,  necessarily also  imagination and

appetition; for, where there is  sensation, there is  also pleasure and pain, and, where these,  necessarily also

desire. 

We have no evidence as yet about mind or the power to think; it  seems to be a widely different kind of soul,

differing as what is  eternal from what is perishable; it alone is capable of existence in  isolation from all other

psychic powers. All the other parts of  soul,  it is evident from what we have said, are, in spite of certain

statements to the contrary, incapable of separate existence though, of  course, distinguishable by definition. If

opining is distinct from  perceiving, to be capable of opining and to be capable of perceiving  must be distinct,

and so with all the other forms of living above  enumerated. Further, some animals possess all these parts of

soul,  some certain of them only, others one only (this is what enables us to  classify animals); the cause must

be considered later.' A similar  arrangement is found also within the field of the senses; some classes  of

animals have all the senses, some only certain of them, others only  one, the most indispensable, touch. 

Since the expression 'that whereby we live and perceive' has two  meanings, just like the expression 'that

whereby we know'that may  mean either (a) knowledge or (b) the soul, for we can speak of knowing  by or

with either, and similarly that whereby we are in health may  be  either (a) health or (b) the body or some part

of the body; and  since  of the two terms thus contrasted knowledge or health is the name  of a  form, essence, or

ratio, or if we so express it an actuality of a  recipient matterknowledge of what is capable of knowing,

health of  what is capable of being made healthy (for the operation of that which  is capable of originating

change terminates and has its seat in what  is changed or altered); further, since it is the soul by or with which

primarily we live, perceive, and think:it follows that the soul  must  be a ratio or formulable essence, not a

matter or subject. For,  as we  said, word substance has three meanings form, matter, and the  complex  of both

and of these three what is called matter is  potentiality, what  is called form actuality. Since then the complex

here is the living  thing, the body cannot be the actuality of the  soul; it is the soul  which is the actuality of a

certain kind of body.  Hence the rightness  of the view that the soul cannot be without a  body, while it csnnot

he  a body; it is not a body but something  relative to a body. That is why  it is in a body, and a body of a

definite kind. It was a mistake,  therefore, to do as former thinkers  did, merely to fit it into a body  without

adding a definite  specification of the kind or character of  that body. Reflection  confirms the observed fact;

the actuality of any  given thing can  only be realized in what is already potentially that  thing, i.e. in  a matter of

its own appropriate to it. From all this it  follows that  soul is an actuality or formulable essence of something

that possesses  a potentiality of being besouled. 

Of the psychic powers above enumerated some kinds of living  things, as we have said, possess all, some less

than all, others one  only. Those we have mentioned are the nutritive, the appetitive, the  sensory, the

locomotive, and the power of thinking. Plants have none  but the first, the nutritive, while another order of

living things has  this plus the sensory. If any order of living things has the  sensory,  it must also have the

appetitive; for appetite is the genus  of which  desire, passion, and wish are the species; now all animals  have


ON THE SOUL

Book II 15



Top




Page No 18


one  sense at least, viz. touch, and whatever has a sense has  the capacity  for pleasure and pain and therefore

has pleasant and  painful objects  present to it, and wherever these are present, there  is desire, for  desire is just

appetition of what is pleasant. Further,  all animals  have the sense for food (for touch is the sense for food);

the food of  all living things consists of what is dry, moist, hot,  cold, and these  are the qualities apprehended

by touch; all other  sensible qualities  are apprehended by touch only indirectly. Sounds,  colours, and odours

contribute nothing to nutriment; flavours fall  within the field of  tangible qualities. Hunger and thirst are

forms of  desire, hunger a  desire for what is dry and hot, thirst a desire for  what is cold and  moist; flavour is a

sort of seasoning added to  both. We must later  clear up these points, but at present it may be  enough to say

that all  animals that possess the sense of touch have  also appetition. The case  of imagination is obscure; we

must examine  it later. Certain kinds of  animals possess in addition the power of  locomotion, and still another

order of animate beings, i.e. man and  possibly another order like man  or superior to him, the power of

thinking, i.e. mind. It is now  evident that a single definition can be  given of soul only in the same  sense as

one can be given of figure.  For, as in that case there is no  figure distinguishable and apart from  triangle, so

here there is no  soul apart from the forms of soul  just enumerated. It is true that a  highly general definition

can be  given for figure which will fit all  figures without expressing the  peculiar nature of any figure. So here

in the case of soul and its  specific forms. Hence it is absurd in this  and similar cases to demand  an absolutely

general definition which  will fail to express the  peculiar nature of anything that is, or  again, omitting this, to

look for separate definitions corresponding  to each infima species.  The cases of figure and soul are exactly

parallel; for the particulars  subsumed under the common name in both  casesfigures and living

beingsconstitute a series, each successive  term of which  potentially contains its predecessor, e.g. the square

the triangle,  the sensory power the selfnutritive. Hence we must ask  in the case of  each order of living

things, What is its soul, i.e.  What is the soul  of plant, animal, man? Why the terms are related in  this serial

way  must form the subject of later examination. But the  facts are that the  power of perception is never found

apart from the  power of  selfnutrition, whilein plantsthe latter is found isolated  from  the former. Again, no

sense is found apart from that of touch,  while  touch is found by itself; many animals have neither sight,

hearing,  nor smell. Again, among living things that possess sense some  have the  power of locomotion, some

not. Lastly, certain living  beingsa small  minoritypossess calculation and thought, for (among  mortal

beings)  those which possess calculation have all the other  powers above  mentioned, while the converse does

not holdindeed some  live by  imagination alone, while others have not even imagination. The  mind  that

knows with immediate intuition presents a different problem. 

It is evident that the way to give the most adequate definition of  soul is to seek in the case of each of its forms

for the most  appropriate definition. 

It is necessary for the student of these forms of soul first to  find  a definition of each, expressive of what it is,

and then to  investigate its derivative properties, But if we are to express  what  each is, viz. what the thinking

power is, or the perceptive, or  the  nutritive, we must go farther back and first give an account of  thinking or

perceiving, for in the order of investigation the question  of what an agent does precedes the question, what

enables it to do  what it does. If this is correct, we must on the same ground go yet  another step farther back

and have some clear view of the objects of  each; thus we must start with these objects, e.g. with food, with

what  is perceptible, or with what is intelligible. 

It follows that first of all we must treat of nutrition and  reproduction, for the nutritive soul is found along with

all the  others and is the most primitive and widely distributed power of soul,  being indeed that one in virtue

of which all are said to have life.  The acts in which it manifests itself are reproduction and the use  of

foodreproduction, I say, because for any living thing that has  reached its normal development and which is

unmutilated, and whose  mode of generation is not spontaneous, the most natural act is the  production of

another like itself, an animal producing an animal, a  plant a plant, in order that, as far as its nature allows, it

may  partake in the eternal and divine. That is the goal towards which  all  things strive, that for the sake of


ON THE SOUL

Book II 16



Top




Page No 19


which they do whatsoever their  nature renders possible. The phrase 'for the sake of which' is  ambiguous; it

may mean either (a) the end to achieve which, or (b) the  being in whose interest, the act is done. Since then

no living thing  is able to partake in what is eternal and divine by uninterrupted  continuance (for nothing

perishable can for ever remain one and the  same), it tries to achieve that end in the only way possible to it,

and success is possible in varying degrees; so it remains not indeed  as the selfsame individual but continues

its existence in something  like itselfnot numerically but specifically one. 

The soul is the cause or source of the living body. The terms  cause and source have many senses. But the soul

is the cause of its  body alike in all three senses which we explicitly recognize. It is  (a) the source or origin of

movement, it is (b) the end, it is (c) the  essence of the whole living body. 

That it is the last, is clear; for in everything the essence is  identical with the ground of its being, and here, in

the case of  living things, their being is to live, and of their being and their  living the soul in them is the cause

or source. Further, the actuality  of whatever is potential is identical with its formulable essence. 

It is manifest that the soul is also the final cause of its body.  For Nature, like mind, always does whatever it

does for the sake of  something, which something is its end. To that something corresponds  in the case of

animals the soul and in this it follows the order of  nature; all natural bodies are organs of the soul. This is true

of  those that enter into the constitution of plants as well as of those  which enter into that of animals. This

shows that that the sake of  which they are is soul. We must here recall the two senses of 'that  for the sake of

which', viz. (a) the end to achieve which, and (b) the  being in whose interest, anything is or is done. 

We must maintain, further, that the soul is also the cause of the  living body as the original source of local

movement. The power of  locomotion is not found, however, in all living things. But change  of  quality and

change of quantity are also due to the soul.  Sensation is  held to be a qualitative alteration, and nothing except

what has soul  in it is capable of sensation. The same holds of the  quantitative  changes which constitute

growth and decay; nothing  grows or decays  naturally except what feeds itself, and nothing  feeds itself except

what has a share of soul in it. 

Empedocles is wrong in adding that growth in plants is to be  explained, the downward rooting by the natural

tendency of earth to  travel downwards, and the upward branching by the similar natural  tendency of fire to

travel upwards. For he misinterprets up and  down;  up and down are not for all things what they are for the

whole  Cosmos:  if we are to distinguish and identify organs according to  their  functions, the roots of plants

are analogous to the head in  animals.  Further, we must ask what is the force that holds together  the earth  and

the fire which tend to travel in contrary directions; if  there is  no counteracting force, they will be torn

asunder; if there  is, this  must be the soul and the cause of nutrition and growth. By  some the  element of fire is

held to be the cause of nutrition and  growth, for  it alone of the primary bodies or elements is observed  to feed

and  increase itself. Hence the suggestion that in both  plants and animals  it is it which is the operative force. A

concurrent  cause in a sense  it certainly is, but not the principal cause, that is  rather the soul;  for while the

growth of fire goes on without limit so  long as there is  a supply of fuel, in the case of all complex wholes

formed in the  course of nature there is a limit or ratio which  determines their size  and increase, and limit and

ratio are marks of  soul but not of fire,  and belong to the side of formulable essence  rather than that of  matter. 

Nutrition and reproduction are due to one and the same psychic  power. It is necessary first to give precision

to our account of food,  for it is by this function of absorbing food that this psychic power  is distinguished

from all the others. The current view is that what  serves as food to a living thing is what is contrary to itnot

that in  every pair of contraries each is food to the other: to be food a  contrary must not only be transformable

into the other and vice versa,  it must also in so doing increase the bulk of the other. Many a  contrary is

transformed into its other and vice versa, where neither  is even a quantum and so cannot increase in bulk, e.g.

an invalid into  a healthy subject. It is clear that not even those contraries which  satisfy both the conditions

mentioned above are food to one another in  precisely the same sense; water may be said to feed fire, but not


ON THE SOUL

Book II 17



Top




Page No 20


fire  water. Where the members of the pair are elementary bodies only one of  the contraries, it would appear,

can be said to feed the other. But  there is a difficulty here. One set of thinkers assert that like  fed,  as well as

increased in amount, by like. Another set, as we  have said,  maintain the very reverse, viz. that what feeds and

what is  fed are  contrary to one another; like, they argue, is incapable of  being  affected by like; but food is

changed in the process of  digestion, and  change is always to what is opposite or to what is  intermediate.

Further, food is acted upon by what is nourished by  it, not the other  way round, as timber is worked by a

carpenter and  not conversely;  there is a change in the carpenter but it is merely  a change from  notworking to

working. In answering this problem it  makes all the  difference whether we mean by 'the food' the  'finished' or

the 'raw'  product. If we use the word food of both, viz.  of the completely  undigested and the completely

digested matter, we  can justify both the  rival accounts of it; taking food in the sense of  undigested matter,  it is

the contrary of what is fed by it, taking  it as digested it is  like what is fed by it. Consequently it is  clear that in

a certain  sense we may say that both parties are  right, both wrong. 

Since nothing except what is alive can be fed, what is fed is the  besouled body and just because it has soul in

it. Hence food is  essentially related to what has soul in it. Food has a power which  is  other than the power to

increase the bulk of what is fed by it;  so far  forth as what has soul in it is a quantum, food may increase  its

quantity, but it is only so far as what has soul in it is a  'thissomewhat' or substance that food acts as food; in

that case it  maintains the being of what is fed, and that continues to be what it  is so long as the process of

nutrition continues. Further, it is the  agent in generation, i.e. not the generation of the individual fed but  the

reproduction of another like it; the substance of the individual  fed is already in existence; the existence of no

substance is a  selfgeneration but only a selfmaintenance. 

Hence the psychic power which we are now studying may be described  as that which tends to maintain

whatever has this power in it of  continuing such as it was, and food helps it to do its work. That is  why, if

deprived of food, it must cease to be. 

The process of nutrition involves three factors, (a) what is fed,  (b) that wherewith it is fed, (c) what does the

feeding; of these  (c)  is the first soul, (a) the body which has that soul in it, (b) the  food. But since it is right to

call things after the ends they  realize, and the end of this soul is to generate another being like  that in which it

is, the first soul ought to be named the reproductive  soul. The expression (b) 'wherewith it is fed' is

ambiguous just as is  the expression 'wherewith the ship is steered'; that may mean either  (i) the hand or (ii)

the rudder, i.e. either (i) what is moved and  sets in movement, or (ii) what is merely moved. We can apply

this  analogy here if we recall that all food must be capable of being  digested, and that what produces

digestion is warmth; that is why  everything that has soul in it possesses warmth. 

We have now given an outline account of the nature of food;  further details must be given in the appropriate

place. 

Having made these distinctions let us now speak of sensation in  the widest sense. Sensation depends, as we

have said, on a process  of  movement or affection from without, for it is held to be some  sort of  change of

quality. Now some thinkers assert that like is  affected only  by like; in what sense this is possible and in what

sense impossible,  we have explained in our general discussion of  acting and being acted  upon. 

Here arises a problem: why do we not perceive the senses  themselves as well as the external objects of sense,

or why without  the stimulation of external objects do they not produce sensation,  seeing that they contain in

themselves fire, earth, and all the  other  elements, which are the direct or indirect objects is so of  sense? It  is

clear that what is sensitive is only potentially, not  actually. The  power of sense is parallel to what is

combustible, for  that never  ignites itself spontaneously, but requires an agent which  has the  power of starting

ignition; otherwise it could have set itself  on  fire, and would not have needed actual fire to set it ablaze. 


ON THE SOUL

Book II 18



Top




Page No 21


In reply we must recall that we use the word 'perceive' in two  ways,  for we say (a) that what has the power to

hear or see, 'sees' or  'hears', even though it is at the moment asleep, and also (b) that  what is actually seeing or

hearing, 'sees' or 'hears'. Hence 'sense'  too must have two meanings, sense potential, and sense actual.

Similarly 'to be a sentient' means either (a) to have a certain  power  or (b) to manifest a certain activity. To

begin with, for a  time, let  us speak as if there were no difference between (i) being  moved or  affected, and (ii)

being active, for movement is a kind of  activityan  imperfect kind, as has elsewhere been explained.

Everything that is  acted upon or moved is acted upon by an agent which  is actually at  work. Hence it is that in

one sense, as has already  been stated, what  acts and what is acted upon are like, in another  unlike, i.e. prior to

and during the change the two factors are  unlike, after it like. 

But we must now distinguish not only between what is potential and  what is actual but also different senses

in which things can be said  to be potential or actual; up to now we have been speaking as if  each  of these

phrases had only one sense. We can speak of something as  'a  knower' either (a) as when we say that man is a

knower, meaning  that  man falls within the class of beings that know or have knowledge,  or  (b) as when we

are speaking of a man who possesses a knowledge of  grammar; each of these is so called as having in him a

certain  potentiality, but there is a difference between their respective  potentialities, the one (a) being a

potential knower, because his kind  or matter is such and such, the other (b), because he can in the  absence of

any external counteracting cause realize his knowledge in  actual knowing at will. This implies a third

meaning of 'a knower'  (c), one who is already realizing his knowledgehe is a knower in  actuality and in the

most proper sense is knowing, e.g. this A. Both  the former are potential knowers, who realize their respective

potentialities, the one (a) by change of quality, i.e. repeated  transitions from one state to its opposite under

instruction, the  other (b) by the transition from the inactive possession of sense or  grammar to their active

exercise. The two kinds of transition are  distinct. 

Also the expression 'to be acted upon' has more than one meaning;  it  may mean either (a) the extinction of

one of two contraries by the  other, or (b) the maintenance of what is potential by the agency of  what is actual

and already like what is acted upon, with such likeness  as is compatible with one's being actual and the other

potential.  For  what possesses knowledge becomes an actual knower by a  transition  which is either not an

alteration of it at all (being in  reality a  development into its true self or actuality) or at least  an alteration  in a

quite different sense from the usual meaning. 

Hence it is wrong to speak of a wise man as being 'altered' when  he uses his wisdom, just as it would be

absurd to speak of a builder  as being altered when he is using his skill in building a house. 

What in the case of knowing or understanding leads from  potentiality  to actuality ought not to be called

teaching but  something else.  That which starting with the power to know learns or  acquires  knowledge

through the agency of one who actually knows and  has the  power of teaching either (a) ought not to be said

'to be acted  upon'  at all or (b) we must recognize two senses of alteration, viz.  (i) the  substitution of one

quality for another, the first being the  contrary of the second, or (ii) the development of an existent quality

from potentiality in the direction of fixity or nature. 

In the case of what is to possess sense, the first transition is  due  to the action of the male parent and takes

place before birth so  that at birth the living thing is, in respect of sensation, at the  stage which corresponds to

the possession of knowledge. Actual  sensation corresponds to the stage of the exercise of knowledge. But

between the two cases compared there is a difference; the objects that  excite the sensory powers to activity,

the seen, the heard, are  outside. The ground of this difference is that what actual sensation  apprehends is

individuals, while what knowledge apprehends is  universals, and these are in a sense within the soul. That is

why a  man can exercise his knowledge when he wishes, but his sensation  does  not depend upon himself a

sensible object must be there. A  similar  statement must be made about our knowledge of what is  sensibleon

the  same ground, viz. that the sensible objects are  individual and  external. 


ON THE SOUL

Book II 19



Top




Page No 22


A later more appropriate occasion may be found thoroughly to clear  up all this. At present it must be enough

to recognize the  distinctions already drawn; a thing may be said to be potential in  either of two senses, (a) in

the sense in which we might say of a  boy  that he may become a general or (b) in the sense in which we might

say  the same of an adult, and there are two corresponding senses of  the  term 'a potential sentient'. There are

no separate names for the  two  stages of potentiality; we have pointed out that they are  different  and how they

are different. We cannot help using the  incorrect terms  'being acted upon or altered' of the two transitions

involved. As we  have said, has the power of sensation is potentially  like what the  perceived object is actually;

that is, while at the  beginning of the  process of its being acted upon the two interacting  factors are  dissimilar,

at the end the one acted upon is assimilated  to the other  and is identical in quality with it. 

In dealing with each of the senses we shall have first to speak of  the objects which are perceptible by each.

The term 'object of  sense'  covers three kinds of objects, two kinds of which are, in our  language, directly

perceptible, while the remaining one is only  incidentally perceptible. Of the first two kinds one (a) consists of

what is perceptible by a single sense, the other (b) of what is  perceptible by any and all of the senses. I call by

the name of  special object of this or that sense that which cannot be perceived by  any other sense than that

one and in respect of which no error is  possible; in this sense colour is the special object of sight, sound  of

hearing, flavour of taste. Touch, indeed, discriminates more than  one set of different qualities. Each sense has

one kind of object  which it discerns, and never errs in reporting that what is before  it  is colour or sound

(though it may err as to what it is that is  coloured or where that is, or what it is that is sounding or where  that

is.) Such objects are what we propose to call the special objects  of this or that sense. 

'Common sensibles' are movement, rest, number, figure, magnitude;  these are not peculiar to any one sense,

but are common to all.  There  are at any rate certain kinds of movement which are  perceptible both  by touch

and by sight. 

We speak of an incidental object of sense where e.g. the white  object which we see is the son of Diares; here

because 'being the  son  of Diares' is incidental to the directly visible white patch we  speak  of the son of Diares

as being (incidentally) perceived or seen  by us.  Because this is only incidentally an object of sense, it in  no

way as  such affects the senses. Of the two former kinds, both of  which are in  their own nature perceptible by

sense, the first  kindthat of special  objects of the several sensesconstitute the  objects of sense in the  strictest

sense of the term and it is to  them that in the nature of  things the structure of each several  sense is adapted. 

The object of sight is the visible, and what is visible is (a)  colour and (b) a certain kind of object which can be

described in  words but which has no single name; what we mean by (b) will be  abundantly clear as we

proceed. Whatever is visible is colour and  colour is what lies upon what is in its own nature visible; 'in its

own nature' here means not that visibility is involved in the  definition of what thus underlies colour, but that

that substratum  contains in itself the cause of visibility. Every colour has in it the  power to set in movement

what is actually transparent; that power  constitutes its very nature. That is why it is not visible except with  the

help of light; it is only in light that the colour of a thing is  seen. Hence our first task is to explain what light

is. 

Now there clearly is something which is transparent, and by  'transparent' I mean what is visible, and yet not

visible in itself,  but rather owing its visibility to the colour of something else; of  this character are air, water,

and many solid bodies. Neither air  nor  water is transparent because it is air or water; they are  transparent

because each of them has contained in it a certain  substance which is  the same in both and is also found in the

eternal  body which  constitutes the uppermost shell of the physical Cosmos.  Of this  substance light is the

activitythe activity of what is  transparent so  far forth as it has in it the determinate power of  becoming


ON THE SOUL

Book II 20



Top




Page No 23


transparent; where this power is present, there is also the  potentiality of the contrary, viz. darkness. Light is as

it were the  proper colour of what is transparent, and exists whenever the  potentially transparent is excited to

actuality by the influence of  fire or something resembling 'the uppermost body'; for fire too  contains

something which is one and the same with the substance in  question. 

We have now explained what the transparent is and what light is;  light is neither fire nor any kind whatsoever

of body nor an efflux  from any kind of body (if it were, it would again itself be a kind  of  body)it is the

presence of fire or something resembling fire in  what  is transparent. It is certainly not a body, for two bodies

cannot  be  present in the same place. The opposite of light is darkness;  darkness  is the absence from what is

transparent of the  corresponding positive  state above characterized; clearly therefore,  light is just the  presence

of that. 

Empedocles (and with him all others who used the same forms of  expression) was wrong in speaking of light

as 'travelling' or being at  a given moment between the earth and its envelope, its movement  being

unobservable by us; that view is contrary both to the clear  evidence  of argument and to the observed facts; if

the distance  traversed were  short, the movement might have been unobservable, but  where the  distance is

from extreme East to extreme West, the draught  upon our  powers of belief is too great. 

What is capable of taking on colour is what in itself is  colourless,  as what can take on sound is what is

soundless; what is  colourless  includes (a) what is transparent and (b) what is invisible  or scarcely  visible, i.e.

what is 'dark'. The latter (b) is the same  as what is  transparent, when it is potentially, not of course when it  is

actually  transparent; it is the same substance which is now  darkness, now  light. 

Not everything that is visible depends upon light for its  visibility. This is only true of the 'proper' colour of

things. Some  objects of sight which in light are invisible, in darkness stimulate  the sense; that is, things that

appear fiery or shining. This class of  objects has no simple common name, but instances of it are fungi,  flesh,

heads, scales, and eyes of fish. In none of these is what is  seen their own proper' colour. Why we see these at

all is another  question. At present what is obvious is that what is seen in light  is  always colour. That is why

without the help of light colour remains  invisible. Its being colour at all means precisely its having in it  the

power to set in movement what is already actually transparent,  and, as we have seen, the actuality of what is

transparent is just  light. 

The following experiment makes the necessity of a medium clear. If  what has colour is placed in immediate

contact with the eye, it cannot  be seen. Colour sets in movement not the sense organ but what is  transparent,

e.g. the air, and that, extending continuously from the  object to the organ, sets the latter in movement.

Democritus  misrepresents the facts when he expresses the opinion that if the  interspace were empty one could

distinctly see an ant on the vault  of  the sky; that is an impossibility. Seeing is due to an affection or  change of

what has the perceptive faculty, and it cannot be affected  by the seen colour itself; it remains that it must be

affected by what  comes between. Hence it is indispensable that there be something in  betweenif there were

nothing, so far from seeing with greater  distinctness, we should see nothing at all. 

We have now explained the cause why colour cannot be seen  otherwise than in light. Fire on the other hand is

seen both in  darkness and in light; this double possibility follows necessarily  from our theory, for it is just fire

that makes what is potentially  transparent actually transparent. 

The same account holds also of sound and smell; if the object of  either of these senses is in immediate contact

with the organ no  sensation is produced. In both cases the object sets in movement  only  what lies between,

and this in turn sets the organ in movement:  if  what sounds or smells is brought into immediate contact with

the  organ, no sensation will be produced. The same, in spite of all  appearances, applies also to touch and

taste; why there is this  apparent difference will be clear later. What comes between in the  case of sounds is

air; the corresponding medium in the case of smell  has no name. But, corresponding to what is transparent in


ON THE SOUL

Book II 21



Top




Page No 24


the case  of  colour, there is a quality found both in air and water, which  serves  as a medium for what has

smellI say 'in water' because animals  that  live in water as well as those that live on land seem to  possess the

sense of smell, and 'in air' because man and all other  land animals  that breathe, perceive smells only when

they breathe  air in. The  explanation of this too will be given later. 

Now let us, to begin with, make certain distinctions about sound  and  hearing. 

Sound may mean either of two things (a) actual, and (b) potential,  sound. There are certain things which, as

we say, 'have no sound',  e.g. sponges or wool, others which have, e.g. bronze and in general  all things which

are smooth and solidthe latter are said to have a  sound because they can make a sound, i.e. can generate

actual sound  between themselves and the organ of hearing. 

Actual sound requires for its occurrence (i, ii) two such bodies  and  (iii) a space between them; for it is

generated by an impact.  Hence it  is impossible for one body only to generate a soundthere  must be a  body

impinging and a body impinged upon; what sounds does so  by  striking against something else, and this is

impossible without a  movement from place to place. 

As we have said, not all bodies can by impact on one another  produce  sound; impact on wool makes no

sound, while the impact on  bronze or  any body which is smooth and hollow does. Bronze gives out a  sound

when struck because it is smooth; bodies which are hollow owing  to  reflection repeat the original impact over

and over again, the body  originally set in movement being unable to escape from the concavity. 

Further, we must remark that sound is heard both in air and in  water, though less distinctly in the latter. Yet

neither air nor water  is the principal cause of sound. What is required for the production  of sound is an impact

of two solids against one another and against  the air. The latter condition is satisfied when the air impinged

upon  does not retreat before the blow, i.e. is not dissipated by it. 

That is why it must be struck with a sudden sharp blow, if it is  to soundthe movement of the whip must

outrun the dispersion of the  air, just as one might get in a stroke at a heap or whirl of sand as  it was traveling

rapidly past. 

An echo occurs, when, a mass of air having been unified, bounded,  and prevented from dissipation by the

containing walls of a vessel,  the air originally struck by the impinging body and set in movement by  it

rebounds from this mass of air like a ball from a wall. It is  probable that in all generation of sound echo takes

place, though it  is frequently only indistinctly heard. What happens here must be  analogous to what happens

in the case of light; light is always  reflectedotherwise it would not be diffused and outside what was  directly

illuminated by the sun there would be blank darkness; but  this reflected light is not always strong enough, as

it is when it  is  reflected from water, bronze, and other smooth bodies, to cast a  shadow, which is the

distinguishing mark by which we recognize light. 

It is rightly said that an empty space plays the chief part in the  production of hearing, for what people mean

by 'the vacuum' is the  air, which is what causes hearing, when that air is set in movement as  one continuous

mass; but owing to its friability it emits no sound,  being dissipated by impinging upon any surface which is

not smooth.  When the surface on which it impinges is quite smooth, what is  produced by the original impact

is a united mass, a result due to  the  smoothness of the surface with which the air is in contact at  the  other end. 

What has the power of producing sound is what has the power of  setting in movement a single mass of air

which is continuous from  the  impinging body up to the organ of hearing. The organ of hearing is  physically

united with air, and because it is in air, the air inside  is moved concurrently with the air outside. Hence


ON THE SOUL

Book II 22



Top




Page No 25


animals do not  hear  with all parts of their bodies, nor do all parts admit of the  entrance  of air; for even the

part which can be moved and can sound  has not air  everywhere in it. Air in itself is, owing to its  friability,

quite  soundless; only when its dissipation is prevented is  its movement  sound. The air in the ear is built into a

chamber just to  prevent this  dissipating movement, in order that the animal may  accurately  apprehend all

varieties of the movements of the air  outside. That is  why we hear also in water, viz. because the water  cannot

get into the  air chamber or even, owing to the spirals, into  the outer ear. If this  does happen, hearing ceases,

as it also does if  the tympanic membrane  is damaged, just as sight ceases if the membrane  covering the pupil

is  damaged. It is also a test of deafness whether  the ear does or does  not reverberate like a horn; the air inside

the  ear has always a  movement of its own, but the sound we hear is  always the sounding of  something else,

not of the organ itself. That  is why we say that we  hear with what is empty and echoes, viz. because  what we

hear with is  a chamber which contains a bounded mass of air. 

Which is it that 'sounds', the striking body or the struck? Is not  the answer 'it is both, but each in a different

way'? Sound is a  movement of what can rebound from a smooth surface when struck against  it. As we have

explained' not everything sounds when it strikes or  is  struck, e.g. if one needle is struck against another,

neither emits  any sound. In order, therefore, that sound may be generated, what is  struck must be smooth, to

enable the air to rebound and be shaken  off  from it in one piece. 

The distinctions between different sounding bodies show themselves  only in actual sound; as without the help

of light colours remain  invisible, so without the help of actual sound the distinctions  between acute and grave

sounds remain inaudible. Acute and grave are  here metaphors, transferred from their proper sphere, viz. that

of  touch, where they mean respectively (a) what moves the sense much in a  short time, (b) what moves the

sense little in a long time. Not that  what is sharp really moves fast, and what is grave, slowly, but that  the

difference in the qualities of the one and the other movement is  due to their respective speeds. There seems to

be a sort of  parallelism between what is acute or grave to hearing and what is  sharp or blunt to touch; what is

sharp as it were stabs, while what is  blunt pushes, the one producing its effect in a short, the other in  a  long

time, so that the one is quick, the other slow. 

Let the foregoing suffice as an analysis of sound. Voice is a kind  of sound characteristic of what has soul in

it; nothing that is  without soul utters voice, it being only by a metaphor that we speak  of the voice of the flute

or the lyre or generally of what (being  without soul) possesses the power of producing a succession of notes

which differ in length and pitch and timbre. The metaphor is based  on  the fact that all these differences are

found also in voice. Many  animals are voiceless, e.g. all nonsanuineous animals and among  sanguineous

animals fish. This is just what we should expect, since  voice is a certain movement of air. The fish, like those

in the  Achelous, which are said to have voice, really make the sounds with  their gills or some similar organ.

Voice is the sound made by an  animal, and that with a special organ. As we saw, everything that  makes a

sound does so by the impact of something (a) against something  else, (b) across a space, (c) filled with air;

hence it is only to  be  expected that no animals utter voice except those which take in  air.  Once air is

inbreathed, Nature uses it for two different  purposes, as  the tongue is used both for tasting and for

articulating;  in that case  of the two functions tasting is necessary for the  animal's existence  (hence it is found

more widely distributed),  while articulate speech  is a luxury subserving its possessor's  wellbeing; similarly

in the  former case Nature employs the breath  both as an indispensable means  to the regulation of the inner

temperature of the living body and also  as the matter of articulate  voice, in the interests of its possessor's

wellbeing. Why its  former use is indispensable must be discussed  elsewhere. 

The organ of respiration is the windpipe, and the organ to which  this is related as means to end is the lungs.

The latter is the part  of the body by which the temperature of land animals is raised above  that of all others.

But what primarily requires the air drawn in by  respiration is not only this but the region surrounding the

heart.  That is why when animals breathe the air must penetrate inwards. 


ON THE SOUL

Book II 23



Top




Page No 26


Voice then is the impact of the inbreathed air against the  'windpipe', and the agent that produces the impact is

the soul  resident in these parts of the body. Not every sound, as we said, made  by an animal is voice (even

with the tongue we may merely make a sound  which is not voice, or without the tongue as in coughing); what

produces the impact must have soul in it and must be accompanied by an  act of imagination, for voice is a

sound with a meaning, and is not  merely the result of any impact of the breath as in coughing; in voice  the

breath in the windpipe is used as an instrument to knock with  against the walls of the windpipe. This is

confirmed by our  inability  to speak when we are breathing either out or inwe can  only do so by  holding our

breath; we make the movements with the  breath so checked.  It is clear also why fish are voiceless; they  have

no windpipe. And  they have no windpipe because they do not  breathe or take in air. Why  they do not is a

question belonging to  another inquiry. 

Smell and its object are much less easy to determine than what we  have hitherto discussed; the distinguishing

characteristic of the  object of smell is less obvious than those of sound or colour. The  ground of this is that

our power of smell is less discriminating and  in general inferior to that of many species of animals; men have

a  poor sense of smell and our apprehension of its proper objects is  inseparably bound up with and so confused

by pleasure and pain,  which  shows that in us the organ is inaccurate. It is probable that  there is  a parallel

failure in the perception of colour by animals  that have  hard eyes: probably they discriminate differences of

colour only by  the presence or absence of what excites fear, and  that it is thus that  human beings distinguish

smells. It seems that  there is an analogy  between smell and taste, and that the species of  tastes run parallel  to

those of smellsthe only difference being  that our sense of taste  is more discriminating than our sense of

smell, because the former is  a modification of touch, which reaches in  man the maximum of  discriminative

accuracy. While in respect of all  the other senses we  fall below many species of animals, in respect  of touch

we far excel  all other species in exactness of  discrimination. That is why man is  the most intelligent of all

animals. This is confirmed by the fact  that it is to differences in  the organ of touch and to nothing else  that the

differences between  man and man in respect of natural  endowment are due; men whose flesh  is hard are

illendowed by nature,  men whose flesh is soft,  wellendowed. 

As flavours may be divided into (a) sweet, (b) bitter, so with  smells. In some things the flavour and the smell

have the same  quality, i.e. both are sweet or both bitter, in others they diverge.  Similarly a smell, like a

flavour, may be pungent, astringent, acid,  or succulent. But, as we said, because smells are much less easy to

discriminate than flavours, the names of these varieties are applied  to smells only metaphorically; for

example 'sweet' is extended from  the taste to the smell of saffron or honey, 'pungent' to that of  thyme, and so

on. 

In the same sense in which hearing has for its object both the  audible and the inaudible, sight both the visible

and the invisible,  smell has for its object both the odorous and the inodorous.  'Inodorous' may be either (a)

what has no smell at all, or (b) what  has a small or feeble smell. The same ambiguity lurks in the word

'tasteless'. 

Smelling, like the operation of the senses previously examined,  takes place through a medium, i.e. through air

or waterI add water,  because wateranimals too (both sanguineous and nonsanguineous)  seem  to smell just

as much as landanimals; at any rate some of them  make  directly for their food from a distance if it has any

scent. That  is  why the following facts constitute a problem for us. All animals  smell  in the same way, but

man smells only when he inhales; if he  exhales or  holds his breath, he ceases to smell, no difference being

made whether  the odorous object is distant or near, or even placed  inside the nose  and actually on the wall of

the nostril; it is a  disability common to  all the senses not to perceive what is in  immediate contact with the

organ of sense, but our failure to  apprehend what is odorous without  the help of inhalation is peculiar  (the

fact is obvious on making the  experiment). Now since bloodless  animals do not breathe, they must, it  might

be argued, have some novel  sense not reckoned among the usual  five. Our reply must be that this  is


ON THE SOUL

Book II 24



Top




Page No 27


impossible, since it is scent  that is perceived; a sense that  apprehends what is odorous and what  has a good or

bad odour cannot  be anything but smell. Further, they  are observed to be  deleteriously effected by the same

strong odours as  man is, e.g.  bitumen, sulphur, and the like. These animals must be  able to smell  without

being able to breathe. The probable explanation  is that in man  the organ of smell has a certain superiority

over that  in all other  animals just as his eyes have over those of hardeyed  animals. Man's  eyes have in the

eyelids a kind of shelter or envelope,  which must  be shifted or drawn back in order that we may see, while

hardeyed  animals have nothing of the kind, but at once see whatever  presents  itself in the transparent

medium. Similarly in certain  species of  animals the organ of smell is like the eye of hardeyed  animals,

uncurtained, while in others which take in air it probably  has a  curtain over it, which is drawn back in

inhalation, owing to the  dilating of the veins or pores. That explains also why such animals  cannot smell

under water; to smell they must first inhale, and that  they cannot do under water. 

Smells come from what is dry as flavours from what is moist.  Consequently the organ of smell is potentially

dry. 

10 

What can be tasted is always something that can be touched, and  just  for that reason it cannot be perceived

through an interposed  foreign  body, for touch means the absence of any intervening body.  Further,  the

flavoured and tasteable body is suspended in a liquid  matter,  and this is tangible. Hence, if we lived in water,

we should  perceive a sweet object introduced into the water, but the water would  not be the medium through

which we perceived; our perception would  be  due to the solution of the sweet substance in what we imbibed,

just  as  if it were mixed with some drink. There is no parallel here to  the  perception of colour, which is due

neither to any blending of  anything  with anything, nor to any efflux of anything from anything.  In the  case of

taste, there is nothing corresponding to the medium  in the  case of the senses previously discussed; but as the

object of  sight is  colour, so the object of taste is flavour. But nothing  excites a  perception of flavour without

the help of liquid; what  acts upon the  sense of taste must be either actually or potentially  liquid like what  is

saline; it must be both (a) itself easily  dissolved, and (b)  capable of dissolving along with itself the tongue.

Taste apprehends  both (a) what has taste and (b) what has no taste, if  we mean by (b)  what has only a slight

or feeble flavour or what  tends to destroy the  sense of taste. In this it is exactly parallel to  sight, which

apprehends both what is visible and what is invisible  (for darkness is  invisible and yet is discriminated by

sight; so is,  in a different  way, what is over brilliant), and to hearing, which  apprehends both  sound and

silence, of which the one is audible and the  other  inaudible, and also overloud sound. This corresponds in

the  case of  hearing to overbright light in the case of sight. As a  faint sound is  'inaudible', so in a sense is a

loud or violent  sound. The word  'invisible' and similar privative terms cover not only  (a) what is  simply

without some power, but also (b) what is adapted by  nature to  have it but has not it or has it only in a very

low  degree, as when we  say that a species of swallow is 'footless' or that  a variety of fruit  is 'stoneless'. So too

taste has as its object both  what can be tasted  and the tastelessthe latter in the sense of what  has little flavour

or a bad flavour or one destructive of taste. The  difference between  what is tasteless and what is not seems to

rest  ultimately on that  between what is drinkable and what is undrinkable  both are tasteable,  but the latter is

bad and tends to destroy  taste, while the former is  the normal stimulus of taste. What is  drinkable is the

common object  of both touch and taste. 

Since what can be tasted is liquid, the organ for its perception  cannot be either (a) actually liquid or (b)

incapable of becoming  liquid. Tasting means a being affected by what can be tasted as  such;  hence the organ

of taste must be liquefied, and so to start with  must  be nonliquid but capable of liquefaction without loss of

its  distinctive nature. This is confirmed by the fact that the tongue  cannot taste either when it is too dry or

when it is too moist; in the  latter case what occurs is due to a contact with the preexistent  moisture in the

tongue itself, when after a foretaste of some strong  flavour we try to taste another flavour; it is in this way

that sick  persons find everything they taste bitter, viz. because, when they  taste, their tongues are overflowing

with bitter moisture. 


ON THE SOUL

Book II 25



Top




Page No 28


The species of flavour are, as in the case of colour, (a) simple,  i.e. the two contraries, the sweet and the bitter,

(b) secondary, viz.  (i) on the side of the sweet, the succulent, (ii) on the side of the  bitter, the saline, (iii)

between these come the pungent, the harsh,  the astringent, and the acid; these pretty well exhaust the  varieties

of flavour. It follows that what has the power of tasting is  what is  potentially of that kind, and that what is

tasteable is what  has the  power of making it actually what it itself already is. 

11 

Whatever can be said of what is tangible, can be said of touch,  and vice versa; if touch is not a single sense

but a group of  senses,  there must be several kinds of what is tangible. It is a  problem  whether touch is a single

sense or a group of senses. It is  also a  problem, what is the organ of touch; is it or is it not the  flesh  (including

what in certain animals is homologous with flesh)? On  the  second view, flesh is 'the medium' of touch, the

real organ  being  situated farther inward. The problem arises because the field of  each  sense is according to

the accepted view determined as the range  between a single pair of contraries, white and black for sight,  acute

and grave for hearing, bitter and sweet for taste; but in the  field of  what is tangible we find several such pairs,

hot cold, dry  moist, hard  soft, This problem finds a partial solution, when it  is recalled that  in the case of the

other senses more than one pair of  contraries are  to be met with, e.g. in sound not only acute and  grave but

loud and  soft, smooth and rough,  there are similar  contrasts in the field of  colour. Nevertheless we are unable

clearly  to detect in the case of  touch what the single subject is which  underlies the contrasted  qualities and

corresponds to sound in the  case of hearing. 

To the question whether the organ of touch lies inward or not  (i.e. whether we need look any farther than the

flesh), no  indication  in favour of the second answer can be drawn from the fact  that if the  object comes into

contact with the flesh it is at once  perceived. For  even under present conditions if the experiment is made  of

making a  web and stretching it tight over the flesh, as soon as  this web is  touched the sensation is reported in

the same manner as  before, yet it  is clear that the or is gan is not in this membrane. If  the membrane  could be

grown on to the flesh, the report would travel  still quicker.  The flesh plays in touch very much the same part

as  would be played in  the other senses by an airenvelope growing round  our body; had we  such an envelope

attached to us we should have  supposed that it was by  a single organ that we perceived sounds,  colours, and

smells, and we  should have taken sight, hearing, and  smell to be a single sense. But  as it is, because that

through which  the different movements are  transmitted is not naturally attached to  our bodies, the difference

of  the various senseorgans is too plain to  miss. But in the case of  touch the obscurity remains. 

There must be such a naturally attached 'medium' as flesh, for no  living body could be constructed of air or

water; it must be something  solid. Consequently it must be composed of earth along with these,  which is just

what flesh and its analogue in animals which have no  true flesh tend to be. Hence of necessity the medium

through which are  transmitted the manifoldly contrasted tactual qualities must be a body  naturally attached to

the organism. That they are manifold is clear  when we consider touching with the tongue; we apprehend at

the  tongue  all tangible qualities as well as flavour. Suppose all the rest  of our  flesh was, like the tongue,

sensitive to flavour, we should  have  identified the sense of taste and the sense of touch; what  saves us  from

this identification is the fact that touch and taste are  not  always found together in the same part of the body.

The  following  problem might be raised. Let us assume that every body has  depth, i.e.  has three dimensions,

and that if two bodies have a  third body between  them they cannot be in contact with one another;  let us

remember that  what is liquid is a body and must be or contain  water, and that if two  bodies touch one another

under water, their  touching surfaces cannot  be dry, but must have water between, viz. the  water which wets

their  bounding surfaces; from all this it follows  that in water two bodies  cannot be in contact with one

another. The  same holds of two bodies in  airair being to bodies in air precisely  what water is to bodies in

waterbut the facts are not so evident to  our observation, because we  live in air, just as animals that live  in

water would not notice that  the things which touch one another in  water have wet surfaces. The  problem,

then, is: does the perception of  all objects of sense take  place in the same way, or does it not,  e.g. taste and

touch requiring  contact (as they are commonly thought  to do), while all other senses  perceive over a distance?


ON THE SOUL

Book II 26



Top




Page No 29


The  distinction is unsound; we perceive what  is hard or soft, as well as  the objects of hearing, sight, and

smell,  through a 'medium', only  that the latter are perceived over a greater  distance than the former;  that is

why the facts escape our notice. For  we do perceive everything  through a medium; but in these cases the  fact

escapes us. Yet, to  repeat what we said before, if the medium for  touch were a membrane  separating us from

the object without our  observing its existence,  we should be relatively to it in the same  condition as we are

now to  air or water in which we are immersed; in  their case we fancy we can  touch objects, nothing coming

in between us  and them. But there  remains this difference between what can be  touched and what can be  seen

or can sound; in the latter two cases we  perceive because the  medium produces a certain effect upon us,

whereas  in the perception of  objects of touch we are affected not by but along  with the medium;  it is as if a

man were struck through his shield,  where the shock is  not first given to the shield and passed on to the  man,

but the  concussion of both is simultaneous. 

In general, flesh and the tongue are related to the real organs of  touch and taste, as air and water are to those

of sight, hearing,  and  smell. Hence in neither the one case nor the other can there be  any  perception of an

object if it is placed immediately upon the  organ,  e.g. if a white object is placed on the surface of the eye.

This again  shows that what has the power of perceiving the tangible is  seated  inside. Only so would there be a

complete analogy with all  the other  senses. In their case if you place the object on the organ  it is not

perceived, here if you place it on the flesh it is  perceived;  therefore flesh is not the organ but the medium of

touch. 

What can be touched are distinctive qualities of body as body; by  such differences I mean those which

characterize the elements, viz,  hot cold, dry moist, of which we have spoken earlier in our treatise  on the

elements. The organ for the perception of these is that of  touchthat part of the body in which primarily the

sense of touch  resides. This is that part which is potentially such as its object  is  actually: for all

senseperception is a process of being so  affected;  so that that which makes something such as it itself

actually is makes  the other such because the other is already  potentially such. That is  why when an object of

touch is equally hot  and cold or hard and soft  we cannot perceive; what we perceive must  have a degree of

the  sensible quality lying beyond the neutral  point. This implies that the  sense itself is a 'mean' between any

two opposite qualities which  determine the field of that sense. It  is to this that it owes its  power of discerning

the objects in that  field. What is 'in the middle'  is fitted to discern; relatively to  either extreme it can put itself

in the place of the other. As what is  to perceive both white and black  must, to begin with, be actually  neither

but potentially either (and  so with all the other  senseorgans), so the organ of touch must be  neither hot nor

cold. 

Further, as in a sense sight had for its object both what was  visible and what was invisible (and there was a

parallel truth about  all the other senses discussed), so touch has for its object both what  is tangible and what

is intangible. Here by 'intangible' is meant  (a)  what like air possesses some quality of tangible things in a  very

slight degree and (b) what possesses it in an excessive degree,  as  destructive things do. 

We have now given an outline account of each of the several senses. 

12 

The following results applying to any and every sense may now be  formulated. 

(A) By a 'sense' is meant what has the power of receiving into  itself the sensible forms of things without the

matter. This must be  conceived of as taking place in the way in which a piece of wax  takes  on the impress of

a signetring without the iron or gold; we say  that  what produces the impression is a signet of bronze or gold,

but  its  particular metallic constitution makes no difference: in a similar  way  the sense is affected by what is

coloured or flavoured or  sounding,  but it is indifferent what in each case the substance is;  what alone  matters

is what quality it has, i.e. in what ratio its  constituents  are combined. 


ON THE SOUL

Book II 27



Top




Page No 30


(B) By 'an organ of sense' is meant that in which ultimately such  a power is seated. 

The sense and its organ are the same in fact, but their essence is  not the same. What perceives is, of course, a

spatial magnitude, but  we must not admit that either the having the power to perceive or  the  sense itself is a

magnitude; what they are is a certain ratio or  power  in a magnitude. This enables us to explain why objects of

sense which  possess one of two opposite sensible qualities in a degree  largely in  excess of the other opposite

destroy the organs of sense;  if the  movement set up by an object is too strong for the organ, the  equipoise of

contrary qualities in the organ, which just is its  sensory power, is disturbed; it is precisely as concord and

tone are  destroyed by too violently twanging the strings of a lyre. This  explains also why plants cannot

perceive. in spite of their having a  portion of soul in them and obviously being affected by tangible  objects

themselves; for undoubtedly their temperature can be lowered  or raised. The explanation is that they have no

mean of contrary  qualities, and so no principle in them capable of taking on the  forms  of sensible objects

without their matter; in the case of  plants the  affection is an affection by formandmatter together.  The

problem  might be raised: Can what cannot smell be said to be  affected by  smells or what cannot see by

colours, and so on? It  might be said that  a smell is just what can be smelt, and if it  produces any effect it  can

only be so as to make something smell it,  and it might be argued  that what cannot smell cannot be affected by

smells and further that  what can smell can be affected by it only in  so far as it has in it  the power to smell

(similarly with the proper  objects of all the other  senses). Indeed that this is so is made quite  evident as

follows.  Light or darkness, sounds and smells leave  bodies quite unaffected;  what does affect bodies is not

these but  the bodies which are their  vehicles, e.g. what splits the trunk of a  tree is not the sound of the  thunder

but the air which accompanies  thunder. Yes, but, it may be  objected, bodies are affected by what  is tangible

and by flavours. If  not, by what are things that are  without soul affected, i.e. altered  in quality? Must we not,

then,  admit that the objects of the other  senses also may affect them? Is  not the true account this, that all

bodies are capable of being  affected by smells and sounds, but that  some on being acted upon,  having no

boundaries of their own,  disintegrate, as in the instance of  air, which does become odorous,  showing that

some effect is produced  on it by what is odorous? But  smelling is more than such an  affection by what is

odorouswhat more?  Is not the answer that,  while the air owing to the momentary duration  of the action upon

it of  what is odorous does itself become  perceptible to the sense of  smell, smelling is an observing of the

result produced? 

Book III

THAT there is no sixth sense in addition to the five  enumeratedsight, hearing, smell, taste, touchmay be

established by  the following considerations: 

If we have actually sensation of everything of which touch can  give us sensation (for all the qualities of the

tangible qua  tangible  are perceived by us through touch); and if absence of a sense  necessarily involves

absence of a senseorgan; and if (1) all  objects  that we perceive by immediate contact with them are

perceptible by  touch, which sense we actually possess, and (2) all  objects that we  perceive through media, i.e.

without immediate  contact, are  perceptible by or through the simple elements, e.g. air  and water (and  this is

so arranged that (a) if more than one kind of  sensible object  is perceivable through a single medium, the

possessor of a senseorgan  homogeneous with that medium has the  power of perceiving both kinds of

objects; for example, if the  senseorgan is made of air, and air is a  medium both for sound and for  colour;

and that (b) if more than one  medium can transmit the same  kind of sensible objects, as e.g. water  as well as

air can transmit  colour, both being transparent, then the  possessor of either alone  will be able to perceive the

kind of objects  transmissible through  both); and if of the simple elements two only,  air and water, go to  form

senseorgans (for the pupil is made of  water, the organ of  hearing is made of air, and the organ of smell of

one or other of  these two, while fire is found either in none or in  allwarmth being  an essential condition of


ON THE SOUL

Book III 28



Top




Page No 31


all sensibilityand earth  either in none or,  if anywhere, specially mingled with the components  of the organ

of  touch; wherefore it would remain that there can be no  senseorgan  formed of anything except water and

air); and if these  senseorgans  are actually found in certain animals;then all the  possible senses  are

possessed by those animals that are not imperfect  or mutilated  (for even the mole is observed to have eyes

beneath its  skin); so  that, if there is no fifth element and no property other  than those  which belong to the four

elements of our world, no sense  can be  wanting to such animals. 

Further, there cannot be a special senseorgan for the common  sensibles either, i.e. the objects which we

perceive incidentally  through this or that special sense, e.g. movement, rest, figure,  magnitude, number,

unity; for all these we perceive by movement,  e.g.  magnitude by movement, and therefore also figure (for

figure is a  species of magnitude), what is at rest by the absence of movement:  number is perceived by the

negation of continuity, and by the  special  sensibles; for each sense perceives one class of sensible  objects. So

that it is clearly impossible that there should be a  special sense for  any one of the common sensibles, e.g.

movement; for,  if that were so,  our perception of it would be exactly parallel to our  present  perception of

what is sweet by vision. That is so because we  have a  sense for each of the two qualities, in virtue of which

when  they  happen to meet in one sensible object we are aware of both  contemporaneously. If it were not like

this our perception of the  common qualities would always be incidental, i.e. as is the perception  of Cleon's

son, where we perceive him not as Cleon's son but as white,  and the white thing which we really perceive

happens to be Cleon's  son. 

But in the case of the common sensibles there is already in us a  general sensibility which enables us to

perceive them directly;  there  is therefore no special sense required for their perception:  if there  were, our

perception of them would have been exactly like  what has  been above described. 

The senses perceive each other's special objects incidentally; not  because the percipient sense is this or that

special sense, but  because all form a unity: this incidental perception takes place  whenever sense is directed

at one and the same moment to two disparate  qualities in one and the same object, e.g. to the bitterness and

the  yellowness of bile, the assertion of the identity of both cannot be  the act of either of the senses; hence the

illusion of sense, e.g. the  belief that if a thing is yellow it is bile. 

It might be asked why we have more senses than one. Is it to  prevent  a failure to apprehend the common

sensibles, e.g. movement,  magnitude,  and number, which go along with the special sensibles? Had  we no

sense  but sight, and that sense no object but white, they would  have  tended to escape our notice and

everything would have merged for  us  into an indistinguishable identity because of the concomitance of  colour

and magnitude. As it is, the fact that the common sensibles are  given in the objects of more than one sense

reveals their  distinction  from each and all of the special sensibles. 

Since it is through sense that we are aware that we are seeing or  hearing, it must be either by sight that we are

aware of seeing, or by  some sense other than sight. But the sense that gives us this new  sensation must

perceive both sight and its object, viz. colour: so  that either (1) there will be two senses both percipient of the

same  sensible object, or (2) the sense must be percipient of itself.  Further, even if the sense which perceives

sight were different from  sight, we must either fall into an infinite regress, or we must  somewhere assume a

sense which is aware of itself. If so, we ought  to  do this in the first case. 

This presents a difficulty: if to perceive by sight is just to  see, and what is seen is colour (or the coloured),

then if we are to  see that which sees, that which sees originally must be coloured. It  is clear therefore that 'to

perceive by sight' has more than one  meaning; for even when we are not seeing, it is by sight that we

discriminate darkness from light, though not in the same way as we  distinguish one colour from another.

Further, in a sense even that  which sees is coloured; for in each case the senseorgan is capable of  receiving


ON THE SOUL

Book III 29



Top




Page No 32


the sensible object without its matter. That is why even  when the sensible objects are gone the sensings and

imaginings  continue to exist in the senseorgans. 

The activity of the sensible object and that of the percipient  sense  is one and the same activity, and yet the

distinction between  their  being remains. Take as illustration actual sound and actual  hearing: a  man may have

hearing and yet not be hearing, and that which  has a  sound is not always sounding. But when that which can

hear is  actively  hearing and which can sound is sounding, then the actual  hearing and  the actual sound are

merged in one (these one might call  respectively hearkening and sounding). 

If it is true that the movement, both the acting and the being  acted  upon, is to be found in that which is acted

upon, both the sound  and  the hearing so far as it is actual must be found in that which has  the  faculty of

hearing; for it is in the passive factor that the  actuality  of the active or motive factor is realized; that is why

that  which  causes movement may be at rest. Now the actuality of that which  can  sound is just sound or

sounding, and the actuality of that which  can  hear is hearing or hearkening; 'sound' and 'hearing' are both

ambiguous. The same account applies to the other senses and their  objects. For as

theactingandbeingactedupon is to be found in  the  passive, not in the active factor, so also the actuality

of the  sensible object and that of the sensitive subject are both realized in  the latter. But while in some cases

each aspect of the total actuality  has a distinct name, e.g. sounding and hearkening, in some one or  other is

nameless, e.g. the actuality of sight is called seeing, but  the actuality of colour has no name: the actuality of

the faculty of  taste is called tasting, but the actuality of flavour has no name.  Since the actualities of the

sensible object and of the sensitive  faculty are one actuality in spite of the difference between their  modes of

being, actual hearing and actual sounding appear and  disappear from existence at one and the same moment,

and so actual  savour and actual tasting, while as potentialities one of them  may  exist without the other. The

earlier students of nature were  mistaken  in their view that without sight there was no white or black,  without

taste no savour. This statement of theirs is partly true,  partly  false: 'sense' and 'the sensible object' are

ambiguous terms,  i.e. may  denote either potentialities or actualities: the statement is  true of  the latter, false of

the former. This ambiguity they wholly  failed to  notice. 

If voice always implies a concord, and if the voice and the  hearing of it are in one sense one and the same,

and if concord always  implies a ratio, hearing as well as what is heard must be a ratio.  That is why the excess

of either the sharp or the flat destroys the  hearing. (So also in the case of savours excess destroys the sense  of

taste, and in the case of colours excessive brightness or  darkness  destroys the sight, and in the case of smell

excess of  strength  whether in the direction of sweetness or bitterness is  destructive.)  This shows that the sense

is a ratio. 

That is also why the objects of sense are (1) pleasant when the  sensible extremes such as acid or sweet or salt

being pure and unmixed  are brought into the proper ratio; then they are pleasant: and in  general what is

blended is more pleasant than the sharp or the flat  alone; or, to touch, that which is capable of being either

warmed or  chilled: the sense and the ratio are identical: while (2) in excess  the sensible extremes are painful

or destructive. 

Each sense then is relative to its particular group of sensible  qualities: it is found in a senseorgan as such

and discriminates  the  differences which exist within that group; e.g. sight  discriminates  white and black, taste

sweet and bitter, and so in all  cases. Since we  also discriminate white from sweet, and indeed each  sensible

quality  from every other, with what do we perceive that  they are different? It  must be by sense; for what is

before us is  sensible objects. (Hence it  is also obvious that the flesh cannot be  the ultimate senseorgan: if  it

were, the discriminating power could  not do its work without  immediate contact with the object.) 

Therefore (1) discrimination between white and sweet cannot be  effected by two agencies which remain

separate; both the qualities  discriminated must be present to something that is one and single.  On  any other

supposition even if I perceived sweet and you perceived  white, the difference between them would be


ON THE SOUL

Book III 30



Top




Page No 33


apparent. What says that  two things are different must be one; for sweet is different from  white. Therefore

what asserts this difference must be  selfidentical,  and as what asserts, so also what thinks or perceives.  That

it is not  possible by means of two agencies which remain separate  to  discriminate two objects which are

separate, is therefore  obvious; and  that (it is not possible to do this in separate movements  of time may  be

seen' if we look at it as follows. For as what  asserts the  difference between the good and the bad is one and

the  same, so also  the time at which it asserts the one to be different and  the other to  be different is not

accidental to the assertion (as it is  for instance  when I now assert a difference but do not assert that  there is

now a  difference); it asserts thusboth now and that the  objects are  different now; the objects therefore must

be present at  one and the  same moment. Both the discriminating power and the time of  its  exercise must be

one and undivided. 

But, it may be objected, it is impossible that what is  selfidentical should be moved at me and the same time

with contrary  movements in so far as it is undivided, and in an undivided moment  of  time. For if what is

sweet be the quality perceived, it moves the  sense or thought in this determinate way, while what is bitter

moves  it in a contrary way, and what is white in a different way. Is it  the  case then that what discriminates,

though both numerically one and  indivisible, is at the same time divided in its being? In one sense,  it is what

is divided that perceives two separate objects at once, but  in another sense it does so qua undivided; for it is

divisible in  its  being but spatially and numerically undivided. is not this  impossible?  For while it is true that

what is selfidentical and  undivided may be  both contraries at once potentially, it cannot be  selfidentical in

its beingit must lose its unity by being put into  activity. It is not  possible to be at once white and black, and

therefore it must also be  impossible for a thing to be affected at one  and the same moment by  the forms of

both, assuming it to be the case  that sensation and  thinking are properly so described. 

The answer is that just as what is called a 'point' is, as being  at once one and two, properly said to be

divisible, so here, that  which discriminates is qua undivided one, and active in a single  moment of time, while

so far forth as it is divisible it twice over  uses the same dot at one and the same time. So far forth then as it

takes the limit as two' it discriminates two separate objects with  what in a sense is divided: while so far as it

takes it as one, it  does so with what is one and occupies in its activity a single  moment  of time. 

About the principle in virtue of which we say that animals are  percipient, let this discussion suffice. 

There are two distinctive peculiarities by reference to which we  characterize the soul (1) local movement and

(2) thinking,  discriminating, and perceiving. Thinking both speculative and  practical is regarded as akin to a

form of perceiving; for in the  one  as well as the other the soul discriminates and is cognizant of  something

which is. Indeed the ancients go so far as to identify  thinking and perceiving; e.g. Empedocles says 'For 'tis in

respect  of  what is present that man's wit is increased', and again 'Whence  it  befalls them from time to time to

think diverse thoughts', and  Homer's  phrase 'For suchlike is man's mind' means the same. They all  look upon

thinking as a bodily process like perceiving, and hold  that like is  known as well as perceived by like, as I

explained at the  beginning of  our discussion. Yet they ought at the same time to have  accounted for  error

also; for it is more intimately connected with  animal existence  and the soul continues longer in the state of

error  than in that of  truth. They cannot escape the dilemma: either (1)  whatever seems is  true (and there are

some who accept this) or (2)  error is contact with  the unlike; for that is the opposite of the  knowing of like by

like. 

But it is a received principle that error as well as knowledge in  respect to contraries is one and the same. 

That perceiving and practical thinking are not identical is  therefore obvious; for the former is universal in the

animal world,  the latter is found in only a small division of it. Further,  speculative thinking is also distinct

from perceivingI mean that in  which we find rightness and wrongnessrightness in prudence,  knowledge,


ON THE SOUL

Book III 31



Top




Page No 34


true opinion, wrongness in their opposites; for  perception  of the special objects of sense is always free from

error, and is  found in all animals, while it is possible to think  falsely as well as  truly, and thought is found

only where there is  discourse of reason as  well as sensibility. For imagination is  different from either

perceiving or discursive thinking, though it  is not found without  sensation, or judgement without it. That this

activity is not the same  kind of thinking as judgement is obvious. For  imagining lies within  our own power

whenever we wish (e.g. we can call  up a picture, as in  the practice of mnemonics by the use of mental

images), but in forming  opinions we are not free: we cannot escape the  alternative of  falsehood or truth.

Further, when we think something to  be fearful or  threatening, emotion is immediately produced, and so too

with what is  encouraging; but when we merely imagine we remain as  unaffected as  persons who are looking

at a painting of some dreadful  or encouraging  scene. Again within the field of judgement itself we  find

varieties,  knowledge, opinion, prudence, and their opposites;  of the differences  between these I must speak

elsewhere. 

Thinking is different from perceiving and is held to be in part  imagination, in part judgement: we must

therefore first mark off the  sphere of imagination and then speak of judgement. If then imagination  is that in

virtue of which an image arises for us, excluding  metaphorical uses of the term, is it a single faculty or

disposition  relative to images, in virtue of which we discriminate and are  either  in error or not? The faculties

in virtue of which we do this  are  sense, opinion, science, intelligence. 

That imagination is not sense is clear from the following  considerations: Sense is either a faculty or an

activity, e.g. sight  or seeing: imagination takes place in the absence of both, as e.g.  in  dreams. (Again, sense

is always present, imagination not. If actual  imagination and actual sensation were the same, imagination

would be  found in all the brutes: this is held not to be the case; e.g. it is  not found in ants or bees or grubs.

(Again, sensations are always  true, imaginations are for the most part false. (Once more, even in  ordinary

speech, we do not, when sense functions precisely with regard  to its object, say that we imagine it to be a

man, but rather when  there is some failure of accuracy in its exercise. And as we were  saying before, visions

appear to us even when our eyes are shut.  Neither is imagination any of the things that are never in error: e.g.

knowledge or intelligence; for imagination may be false. 

It remains therefore to see if it is opinion, for opinion may be  either true or false. 

But opinion involves belief (for without belief in what we opine  we cannot have an opinion), and in the

brutes though we often find  imagination we never find belief. Further, every opinion is  accompanied by

belief, belief by conviction, and conviction by  discourse of reason: while there are some of the brutes in

which we  find imagination, without discourse of reason. It is clear then that  imagination cannot, again, be (1)

opinion plus sensation, or (2)  opinion mediated by sensation, or (3) a blend of opinion and  sensation; this is

impossible both for these reasons and because the  content of the supposed opinion cannot be different from

that of the  sensation (I mean that imagination must be the blending of the  perception of white with the

opinion that it is white: it could  scarcely be a blend of the opinion that it is good with the perception  that it is

white): to imagine is therefore (on this view) identical  with the thinking of exactly the same as what one in

the strictest  sense perceives. But what we imagine is sometimes false though our  contemporaneous judgement

about it is true; e.g. we imagine the sun to  be a foot in diameter though we are convinced that it is larger than

the inhabited part of the earth, and the following dilemma presents  itself. Either (a while the fact has not

changed and the (observer has  neither forgotten nor lost belief in the true opinion which he had,  that opinion

has disappeared, or (b) if he retains it then his opinion  is at once true and false. A true opinion, however,

becomes false only  when the fact alters without being noticed. 

Imagination is therefore neither any one of the states enumerated,  nor compounded out of them. 

But since when one thing has been set in motion another thing may  be  moved by it, and imagination is held to

be a movement and to be  impossible without sensation, i.e. to occur in beings that are  percipient and to have


ON THE SOUL

Book III 32



Top




Page No 35


for its content what can be perceived, and  since movement may be produced by actual sensation and that

movement  is necessarily similar in character to the sensation itself, this  movement must be (1) necessarily (a)

incapable of existing apart  from  sensation, (b) incapable of existing except when we perceive,  (such  that in

virtue of its possession that in which it is found may  present  various phenomena both active and passive, and

(such that it  may be  either true or false. 

The reason of the last characteristic is as follows. Perception  (1) of the special objects of sense is never in

error or admits the  least possible amount of falsehood. (2) That of the concomitance of  the objects

concomitant with the sensible qualities comes next: in  this case certainly we may be deceived; for while the

perception  that  there is white before us cannot be false, the perception that  what is  white is this or that may be

false. (3) Third comes the  perception of  the universal attributes which accompany the concomitant  objects to

which the special sensibles attach (I mean e.g. of movement  and  magnitude); it is in respect of these that the

greatest amount  of  senseillusion is possible. 

The motion which is due to the activity of sense in these three  modes of its exercise will differ from the

activity of sense; (1)  the  first kind of derived motion is free from error while the  sensation is  present; (2) and

(3) the others may be erroneous  whether it is present  or absent, especially when the object of  perception is far

off. If  then imagination presents no other  features than those enumerated and  is what we have described, then

imagination must be a movement  resulting from an actual exercise of  a power of sense. 

As sight is the most highly developed sense, the name Phantasia  (imagination) has been formed from Phaos

(light) because it is not  possible to see without light. 

And because imaginations remain in the organs of sense and  resemble sensations, animals in their actions are

largely guided by  them, some (i.e. the brutes) because of the nonexistence in them of  mind, others (i.e. men)

because of the temporary eclipse in them of  mind by feeling or disease or sleep. 

About imagination, what it is and why it exists, let so much  suffice. 

Turning now to the part of the soul with which the soul knows and  thinks (whether this is separable from the

others in definition  only,  or spatially as well) we have to inquire (1) what differentiates  this  part, and (2) how

thinking can take place. 

If thinking is like perceiving, it must be either a process in  which  the soul is acted upon by what is capable of

being thought, or a  process different from but analogous to that. The thinking part of the  soul must therefore

be, while impassible, capable of receiving the  form of an object; that is, must be potentially identical in

character  with its object without being the object. Mind must be related to what  is thinkable, as sense is to

what is sensible. 

Therefore, since everything is a possible object of thought, mind  in  order, as Anaxagoras says, to dominate,

that is, to know, must be  pure  from all admixture; for the copresence of what is alien to its  nature  is a

hindrance and a block: it follows that it too, like the  sensitive  part, can have no nature of its own, other than

that of  having a  certain capacity. Thus that in the soul which is called mind  (by  mind I mean that whereby the

soul thinks and judges) is, before it  thinks, not actually any real thing. For this reason it cannot  reasonably be

regarded as blended with the body: if so, it would  acquire some quality, e.g. warmth or cold, or even have an

organ  like  the sensitive faculty: as it is, it has none. It was a good  idea to  call the soul 'the place of forms',

though (1) this  description holds  only of the intellective soul, and (2) even this  is the forms only  potentially,

not actually. 


ON THE SOUL

Book III 33



Top




Page No 36


Observation of the senseorgans and their employment reveals a  distinction between the impassibility of the

sensitive and that of the  intellective faculty. After strong stimulation of a sense we are  less  able to exercise it

than before, as e.g. in the case of a loud  sound  we cannot hear easily immediately after, or in the case of a

bright  colour or a powerful odour we cannot see or smell, but in the  case of  mind thought about an object that

is highly intelligible  renders it  more and not less able afterwards to think objects that are  less  intelligible: the

reason is that while the faculty of sensation  is  dependent upon the body, mind is separable from it. 

Once the mind has become each set of its possible objects, as a  man of science has, when this phrase is used

of one who is actually  a  man of science (this happens when he is now able to exercise the  power  on his own

initiative), its condition is still one of  potentiality,  but in a different sense from the potentiality which

preceded the  acquisition of knowledge by learning or discovery: the  mind too is  then able to think itself. 

Since we can distinguish between a spatial magnitude and what it  is to be such, and between water and what

it is to be water, and so in  many other cases (though not in all; for in certain cases the thing  and its form are

identical), flesh and what it is to be flesh are  discriminated either by different faculties, or by the same faculty

in  two different states: for flesh necessarily involves matter and is  like what is snubnosed, a this in a this.

Now it is by means of the  sensitive faculty that we discriminate the hot and the cold, i.e.  the  factors which

combined in a certain ratio constitute flesh: the  essential character of flesh is apprehended by something

different  either wholly separate from the sensitive faculty or related to it  as  a bent line to the same line when

it has been straightened out. 

Again in the case of abstract objects what is straight is  analogous to what is snubnosed; for it necessarily

implies a  continuum as its matter: its constitutive essence is different, if  we  may distinguish between

straightness and what is straight: let us  take  it to be twoness. It must be apprehended, therefore, by a

different  power or by the same power in a different state. To sum  up, in so far  as the realities it knows are

capable of being separated  from their  matter, so it is also with the powers of mind. 

The problem might be suggested: if thinking is a passive  affection, then if mind is simple and impassible and

has nothing in  common with anything else, as Anaxagoras says, how can it come to  think at all? For

interaction between two factors is held to require a  precedent community of nature between the factors. Again

it might be  asked, is mind a possible object of thought to itself? For if mind  is  thinkable per se and what is

thinkable is in kind one and the same,  then either (a) mind will belong to everything, or (b) mind will  contain

some element common to it with all other realities which makes  them all thinkable. 

(1) Have not we already disposed of the difficulty about  interaction  involving a common element, when we

said that mind is in a  sense  potentially whatever is thinkable, though actually it is nothing  until  it has thought?

What it thinks must be in it just as characters  may be  said to be on a writingtablet on which as yet nothing

actually  stands written: this is exactly what happens with mind. 

(Mind is itself thinkable in exactly the same way as its objects  are. For (a) in the case of objects which

involve no matter, what  thinks and what is thought are identical; for speculative knowledge  and its object are

identical. (Why mind is not always thinking we must  consider later.) (b) In the case of those which contain

matter each of  the objects of thought is only potentially present. It follows that  while they will not have mind

in them (for mind is a potentiality of  them only in so far as they are capable of being disengaged from  matter)

mind may yet be thinkable. 

Since in every class of things, as in nature as a whole, we find  two  factors involved, (1) a matter which is

potentially all the  particulars included in the class, (2) a cause which is productive  in  the sense that it makes

them all (the latter standing to the  former,  as e.g. an art to its material), these distinct elements  must likewise


ON THE SOUL

Book III 34



Top




Page No 37


be found within the soul. 

And in fact mind as we have described it is what it is what it is  by  virtue of becoming all things, while there

is another which is what  it  is by virtue of making all things: this is a sort of positive state  like light; for in a

sense light makes potential colours into actual  colours. 

Mind in this sense of it is separable, impassible, unmixed, since  it  is in its essential nature activity (for always

the active is  superior  to the passive factor, the originating force to the matter  which it  forms). 

Actual knowledge is identical with its object: in the individual,  potential knowledge is in time prior to actual

knowledge, but in the  universe as a whole it is not prior even in time. Mind is not at one  time knowing and at

another not. When mind is set free from its  present conditions it appears as just what it is and nothing more:

this alone is immortal and eternal (we do not, however, remember its  former activity because, while mind in

this sense is impassible,  mind  as passive is destructible), and without it nothing thinks. 

The thinking then of the simple objects of thought is found in  those  cases where falsehood is impossible:

where the alternative of  true  or false applies, there we always find a putting together of  objects  of thought in a

quasiunity. As Empedocles said that 'where  heads of  many a creature sprouted without necks' they

afterwards by  Love's  power were combined, so here too objects of thought which were  given  separate are

combined, e.g. 'incommensurate' and 'diagonal': if  the  combination be of objects past or future the

combination of  thought  includes in its content the date. For falsehood always  involves a  synthesis; for even if

you assert that what is white is not  white  you have included not white in a synthesis. It is possible also  to  call

all these cases division as well as combination. However that  may  be, there is not only the true or false

assertion that Cleon is  white but also the true or false assertion that he was or will he  white. In each and every

case that which unifies is mind. 

Since the word 'simple' has two senses, i.e. may mean either (a)  'not capable of being divided' or (b) 'not

actually divided', there is  nothing to prevent mind from knowing what is undivided, e.g. when it  apprehends a

length (which is actually undivided) and that in an  undivided time; for the time is divided or undivided in the

same  manner as the line. It is not possible, then, to tell what part of the  line it was apprehending in each half

of the time: the object has no  actual parts until it has been divided: if in thought you think each  half

separately, then by the same act you divide the time also, the  halflines becoming as it were new wholes of

length. But if you  think  it as a whole consisting of these two possible parts, then  also you  think it in a time

which corresponds to both parts  together. (But what  is not quantitatively but qualitatively simple  is thought in

a simple  time and by a simple act of the soul.) 

But that which mind thinks and the time in which it thinks are in  this case divisible only incidentally and not

as such. For in them too  there is something indivisible (though, it may be, not isolable) which  gives unity to

the time and the whole of length; and this is found  equally in every continuum whether temporal or spatial. 

Points and similar instances of things that divide, themselves  being  indivisible, are realized in consciousness

in the same manner as  privations. 

A similar account may be given of all other cases, e.g. how evil  or black is cognized; they are cognized, in a

sense, by means of their  contraries. That which cognizes must have an element of potentiality  in its being,

and one of the contraries must be in it. But if there is  anything that has no contrary, then it knows itself and is

actually  and possesses independent existence. 


ON THE SOUL

Book III 35



Top




Page No 38


Assertion is the saying of something concerning something, e.g.  affirmation, and is in every case either true

or false: this is not  always the case with mind: the thinking of the definition in the sense  of the constitutive

essence is never in error nor is it the  assertion  of something concerning something, but, just as while the

seeing of  the special object of sight can never be in error, the  belief that the  white object seen is a man may

be mistaken, so too  in the case of  objects which are without matter. 

Actual knowledge is identical with its object: potential knowledge  in the individual is in time prior to actual

knowledge but in the  universe it has no priority even in time; for all things that come  into being arise from

what actually is. In the case of sense clearly  the sensitive faculty already was potentially what the object

makes it  to be actually; the faculty is not affected or altered. This must  therefore be a different kind from

movement; for movement is, as we  saw, an activity of what is imperfect, activity in the unqualified  sense, i.e.

that of what has been perfected, is different from  movement. 

To perceive then is like bare asserting or knowing; but when the  object is pleasant or painful, the soul makes

a quasiaffirmation or  negation, and pursues or avoids the object. To feel pleasure or pain  is to act with the

sensitive mean towards what is good or bad as such.  Both avoidance and appetite when actual are identical

with this: the  faculty of appetite and avoidance are not different, either from one  another or from the faculty

of senseperception; but their being is  different. 

To the thinking soul images serve as if they were contents of  perception (and when it asserts or denies them

to be good or bad it  avoids or pursues them). That is why the soul never thinks without  an  image. The process

is like that in which the air modifies the pupil  in  this or that way and the pupil transmits the modification to

some  third thing (and similarly in hearing), while the ultimate point of  arrival is one, a single mean, with

different manners of being. 

With what part of itself the soul discriminates sweet from hot I  have explained before and must now describe

again as follows: That  with which it does so is a sort of unity, but in the way just  mentioned, i.e. as a

connecting term. And the two faculties it  connects, being one by analogy and numerically, are each to each as

the qualities discerned are to one another (for what difference does  it make whether we raise the problem of

discrimination between  disparates or between contraries, e.g. white and black?). Let then C  be to D as is to B:

it follows alternando that C: A:: D: B. If then  C  and D belong to one subject, the case will be the same with

them  as  with and B; and B form a single identity with different modes of  being; so too will the former pair.

The same reasoning holds if be  sweet and B white. 

The faculty of thinking then thinks the forms in the images, and  as in the former case what is to be pursued or

avoided is marked out  for it, so where there is no sensation and it is engaged upon the  images it is moved to

pursuit or avoidance. E.g.. perceiving by  sense  that the beacon is fire, it recognizes in virtue of the  general

faculty of sense that it signifies an enemy, because it sees  it  moving; but sometimes by means of the images

or thoughts which  are  within the soul, just as if it were seeing, it calculates and  deliberates what is to come by

reference to what is present; and  when  it makes a pronouncement, as in the case of sensation it  pronounces

the object to be pleasant or painful, in this case it  avoids or  persues and so generally in cases of action. 

That too which involves no action, i.e. that which is true or  false,  is in the same province with what is good or

bad: yet they  differ in  this, that the one set imply and the other do not a  reference to a  particular person. 

The socalled abstract objects the mind thinks just as, if one had  thought of the snubnosed not as snubnosed

but as hollow, one would  have thought of an actuality without the flesh in which it is  embodied: it is thus that

the mind when it is thinking the objects  of  Mathematics thinks as separate elements which do not exist

separate.  In every case the mind which is actively thinking is the  objects which  it thinks. Whether it is


ON THE SOUL

Book III 36



Top




Page No 39


possible for it while not  existing separate  from spatial conditions to think anything that is  separate, or not, we

must consider later. 

Let us now summarize our results about soul, and repeat that the  soul is in a way all existing things; for

existing things are either  sensible or thinkable, and knowledge is in a way what is knowable, and  sensation is

in a way what is sensible: in what way we must inquire. 

Knowledge and sensation are divided to correspond with the  realities, potential knowledge and sensation

answering to  potentialities, actual knowledge and sensation to actualities.  Within  the soul the faculties of

knowledge and sensation are  potentially  these objects, the one what is knowable, the other what is  sensible.

They must be either the things themselves or their forms.  The former  alternative is of course impossible: it is

not the stone  which is  present in the soul but its form. 

It follows that the soul is analogous to the hand; for as the hand  is a tool of tools, so the mind is the form of

forms and sense the  form of sensible things. 

Since according to common agreement there is nothing outside and  separate in existence from sensible spatial

magnitudes, the objects of  thought are in the sensible forms, viz. both the abstract objects  and  all the states

and affections of sensible things. Hence (1) no one  can  learn or understand anything in the absence of sense,

and (when  the  mind is actively aware of anything it is necessarily aware of it  along  with an image; for images

are like sensuous contents except in  that  they contain no matter. 

Imagination is different from assertion and denial; for what is  true  or false involves a synthesis of concepts.

In what will the  primary  concepts differ from images? Must we not say that neither  these nor  even our other

concepts are images, though they necessarily  involve  them? 

The soul of animals is characterized by two faculties, (a) the  faculty of discrimination which is the work of

thought and sense,  and  (b) the faculty of originating local movement. Sense and mind we  have  now

sufficiently examined. Let us next consider what it is in the  soul  which originates movement. Is it a single

part of the soul  separate  either spatially or in definition? Or is it the soul as a  whole? If it  is a part, is that part

different from those usually  distinguished or  already mentioned by us, or is it one of them? The  problem at

once  presents itself, in what sense we are to speak of  parts of the soul,  or how many we should distinguish.

For in a sense  there is an infinity  of parts: it is not enough to distinguish, with  some thinkers, the  calculative,

the passionate, and the  desiderative, or with others the  rational and the irrational; for if  we take the dividing

lines  followed by these thinkers we shall find  parts far more distinctly  separated from one another than these,

namely those we have just  mentioned: (1) the nutritive, which  belongs both to plants and to all  animals, and

(2) the sensitive,  which cannot easily be classed as  either irrational or rational;  further (3) the imaginative,

which is,  in its being, different from  all, while it is very hard to say with  which of the others it is the  same or

not the same, supposing we  determine to posit separate parts  in the soul; and lastly (4) the  appetitive, which

would seem to be  distinct both in definition and in  power from all hitherto enumerated. 

It is absurd to break up the lastmentioned faculty: as these  thinkers do, for wish is found in the calculative

part and desire  and  passion in the irrational; and if the soul is tripartite  appetite will  be found in all three

parts. Turning our attention to  the present  object of discussion, let us ask what that is which  originates local

movement of the animal. 


ON THE SOUL

Book III 37



Top




Page No 40


The movement of growth and decay, being found in all living  things, must be attributed to the faculty of

reproduction and  nutrition, which is common to all: inspiration and expiration, sleep  and waking, we must

consider later: these too present much difficulty:  at present we must consider local movement, asking what it

is that  originates forward movement in the animal. 

That it is not the nutritive faculty is obvious; for this kind of  movement is always for an end and is

accompanied either by imagination  or by appetite; for no animal moves except by compulsion unless it has  an

impulse towards or away from an object. Further, if it were the  nutritive faculty, even plants would have been

capable of  originating  such movement and would have possessed the organs  necessary to carry  it out.

Similarly it cannot be the sensitive  faculty either; for there  are many animals which have sensibility  but

remain fast and immovable  throughout their lives. 

If then Nature never makes anything without a purpose and never  leaves out what is necessary (except in the

case of mutilated or  imperfect growths; and that here we have neither mutilation nor  imperfection may be

argued from the facts that such animals (a) can  reproduce their species and (b) rise to completeness of nature

and  decay to an end), it follows that, had they been capable of  originating forward movement, they would

have possessed the organs  necessary for that purpose. Further, neither can the calculative  faculty or what is

called 'mind' be the cause of such movement; for  mind as speculative never thinks what is practicable, it

never says  anything about an object to be avoided or pursued, while this movement  is always in something

which is avoiding or pursuing an object. No,  not even when it is aware of such an object does it at once

enjoin  pursuit or avoidance of it; e.g. the mind often thinks of something  terrifying or pleasant without

enjoining the emotion of fear. It is  the heart that is moved (or in the case of a pleasant object some  other part).

Further, even when the mind does command and thought bids  us pursue or avoid something, sometimes no

movement is produced; we  act in accordance with desire, as in the case of moral weakness.  And,  generally,

we observe that the possessor of medical knowledge  is not  necessarily healing, which shows that something

else is  required to  produce action in accordance with knowledge; the knowledge  alone is  not the cause.

Lastly, appetite too is incompetent to account  fully  for movement; for those who successfully resist

temptation  have  appetite and desire and yet follow mind and refuse to enact  that for  which they have appetite. 

10 

These two at all events appear to be sources of movement: appetite  and mind (if one may venture to regard

imagination as a kind of  thinking; for many men follow their imaginations contrary to  knowledge, and in all

animals other than man there is no thinking or  calculation but only imagination). 

Both of these then are capable of originating local movement, mind  and appetite: (1) mind, that is, which

calculates means to an end,  i.e. mind practical (it differs from mind speculative in the character  of its end);

while (2) appetite is in every form of it relative to  an  end: for that which is the object of appetite is the

stimulant of  mind  practical; and that which is last in the process of thinking is  the  beginning of the action. It

follows that there is a  justification for  regarding these two as the sources of movement, i.e.  appetite and

practical thought; for the object of appetite starts a  movement and as  a result of that thought gives rise to

movement, the  object of  appetite being it a source of stimulation. So too when  imagination  originates

movement, it necessarily involves appetite. 

That which moves therefore is a single faculty and the faculty of  appetite; for if there had been two sources of

movementmind and  appetitethey would have produced movement in virtue of some common  character. As

it is, mind is never found producing movement without  appetite (for wish is a form of appetite; and when

movement is  produced according to calculation it is also according to wish), but  appetite can originate

movement contrary to calculation, for desire is  a form of appetite. Now mind is always right, but appetite and

imagination may be either right or wrong. That is why, though in any  case it is the object of appetite which

originates movement, this  object may be either the real or the apparent good. To produce  movement the


ON THE SOUL

Book III 38



Top




Page No 41


object must be more than this: it must be good that can  be brought into being by action; and only what can be

otherwise than  as it is can thus be brought into being. That then such a power in the  soul as has been

described, i.e. that called appetite, originates  movement is clear. Those who distinguish parts in the soul, if

they  distinguish and divide in accordance with differences of power, find  themselves with a very large

number of parts, a nutritive, a  sensitive, an intellective, a deliberative, and now an appetitive  part; for these

are more different from one another than the faculties  of desire and passion. 

Since appetites run counter to one another, which happens when a  principle of reason and a desire are

contrary and is possible only  in  beings with a sense of time (for while mind bids us hold back  because  of

what is future, desire is influenced by what is just at  hand: a  pleasant object which is just at hand presents

itself as  both pleasant  and good, without condition in either case, because of  want of  foresight into what is

farther away in time), it follows  that while  that which originates movement must be specifically one,  viz. the

faculty of appetite as such (or rather farthest back of all  the object  of that faculty; for it is it that itself

remaining unmoved  originates  the movement by being apprehended in thought or  imagination), the  things

that originate movement are numerically many. 

All movement involves three factors, (1) that which originates the  movement, (2) that by means of which it

originates it, and (3) that  which is moved. The expression 'that which originates the movement' is  ambiguous:

it may mean either (a) something which itself is unmoved or  (b) that which at once moves and is moved. Here

that which moves  without itself being moved is the realizable good, that which at  once  moves and is moved is

the faculty of appetite (for that which  is  influenced by appetite so far as it is actually so influenced is  set  in

movement, and appetite in the sense of actual appetite is a  kind of  movement), while that which is in motion

is the animal. The  instrument  which appetite employs to produce movement is no longer  psychical but

bodily: hence the examination of it falls within the  province of the  functions common to body and soul. To

state the matter  summarily at  present, that which is the instrument in the production  of movement is  to be

found where a beginning and an end coincide as  e.g. in a ball  and socket joint; for there the convex and the

concave sides are  respectively an end and a beginning (that is why  while the one remains  at rest, the other is

moved): they are  separate in definition but not  separable spatially. For everything  is moved by pushing and

pulling.  Hence just as in the case of a wheel,  so here there must be a point  which remains at rest, and from

that  point the movement must  originate. 

To sum up, then, and repeat what I have said, inasmuch as an  animal is capable of appetite it is capable of

selfmovement; it is  not capable of appetite without possessing imagination; and all  imagination is either (1)

calculative or (2) sensitive. In the  latter  an animals, and not only man, partake. 

11 

We must consider also in the case of imperfect animals, sc. those  which have no sense but touch, what it is

that in them originates  movement. Can they have imagination or not? or desire? Clearly they  have feelings of

pleasure and pain, and if they have these they must  have desire. But how can they have imagination? Must

not we say  that,  as their movements are indefinite, they have imagination and  desire,  but indefinitely? 

Sensitive imagination, as we have said, is found in all animals,  deliberative imagination only in those that are

calculative: for  whether this or that shall be enacted is already a task requiring  calculation; and there must be

a single standard to measure by, for  that is pursued which is greater. It follows that what acts in this  way must

be able to make a unity out of several images. 

This is the reason why imagination is held not to involve opinion,  in that it does not involve opinion based on

inference, though opinion  involves imagination. Hence appetite contains no deliberative element.  Sometimes

it overpowers wish and sets it in movement: at times wish  acts thus upon appetite, like one sphere imparting

its movement to  another, or appetite acts thus upon appetite, i.e. in the condition of  moral weakness (though


ON THE SOUL

Book III 39



Top




Page No 42


by nature the higher faculty is always more  authoritative and gives rise to movement). Thus three modes of

movement are possible. 

The faculty of knowing is never moved but remains at rest. Since  the  one premiss or judgement is universal

and the other deals with the  particular (for the first tells us that such and such a kind of man  should do such

and such a kind of act, and the second that this is  an  act of the kind meant, and I a person of the type

intended), it  is the  latter opinion that really originates movement, not the  universal; or  rather it is both, but the

one does so while it  remains in a state  more like rest, while the other partakes in  movement. 

12 

The nutritive soul then must be possessed by everything that is  alive, and every such thing is endowed with

soul from its birth to its  death. For what has been born must grow, reach maturity, and decayall  of which are

impossible without nutrition. Therefore the nutritive  faculty must be found in everything that grows and

decays. 

But sensation need not be found in all things that live. For it is  impossible for touch to belong either (1) to

those whose body is  uncompounded or (2) to those which are incapable of taking in the  forms without their

matter. 

But animals must be endowed with sensation, since Nature does  nothing in vain. For all things that exist by

Nature are means to an  end, or will be concomitants of means to an end. Every body capable of  forward

movement would, if unendowed with sensation, perish and fail  to reach its end, which is the aim of Nature;

for how could it  obtain  nutriment? Stationary living things, it is true, have as  their  nutriment that from which

they have arisen; but it is not  possible  that a body which is not stationary but produced by  generation should

have a soul and a discerning mind without also  having sensation. (Nor  yet even if it were not produced by

generation.  Why should it not have  sensation? Because it were better so either for  the body or for the  soul?

But clearly it would not be better for  either: the absence of  sensation will not enable the one to think  better or

the other to  exist better.) Therefore no body which is not  stationary has soul  without sensation. 

But if a body has sensation, it must be either simple or compound.  And simple it cannot be; for then it could

not have touch, which is  indispensable. This is clear from what follows. An animal is a body  with soul in it:

every body is tangible, i.e. perceptible by touch;  hence necessarily, if an animal is to survive, its body must

have  tactual sensation. All the other senses, e.g. smell, sight, hearing,  apprehend through media; but where

there is immediate contact the  animal, if it has no sensation, will be unable to avoid some things  and take

others, and so will find it impossible to survive. That is  why taste also is a sort of touch; it is relative to

nutriment,  which  is just tangible body; whereas sound, colour, and odour are  innutritious, and further neither

grow nor decay. Hence it is that  taste also must be a sort of touch, because it is the sense for what  is tangible

and nutritious. 

Both these senses, then, are indispensable to the animal, and it  is clear that without touch it is impossible for

an animal to be.  All  the other senses subserve wellbeing and for that very reason  belong  not to any and

every kind of animal, but only to some, e.g.  those  capable of forward movement must have them; for, if they

are  to  survive, they must perceive not only by immediate contact but  also at  a distance from the object. This

will be possible if they  can perceive  through a medium, the medium being affected and moved  by the

perceptible object, and the animal by the medium. just as  that which  produces local movement causes a

change extending to a  certain point,  and that which gave an impulse causes another to  produce a new impulse

so that the movement traverses a medium the  first mover impelling  without being impelled, the last moved

being  impelled without  impelling, while the medium (or media, for there  are many) is bothso  is it also in the

case of alteration, except that  the agent produces  produces it without the patient's changing its  place. Thus if

an  object is dipped into wax, the movement goes on  until submersion has  taken place, and in stone it goes no


ON THE SOUL

Book III 40



Top




Page No 43


distance  at all, while in water  the disturbance goes far beyond the object  dipped: in air the  disturbance is

propagated farthest of all, the  air acting and being  acted upon, so long as it maintains an unbroken  unity. That

is why in  the case of reflection it is better, instead  of saying that the sight  issues from the eye and is reflected,

to  say that the air, so long as  it remains one, is affected by the  shape and colour. On a smooth  surface the air

possesses unity; hence  it is that it in turn sets the  sight in motion, just as if the  impression on the wax were

transmitted  as far as the wax extends. 

13 

It is clear that the body of an animal cannot be simple, i.e.  consist of one element such as fire or air. For

without touch it is  impossible to have any other sense; for every body that has soul in it  must, as we have

said, be capable of touch. All the other elements  with the exception of earth can constitute organs of sense,

but all of  them bring about perception only through something else, viz.  through  the media. Touch takes place

by direct contact with its  objects,  whence also its name. All the other organs of sense, no  doubt,  perceive by

contact, only the contact is mediate: touch alone  perceives by immediate contact. Consequently no animal

body can  consist of these other elements. 

Nor can it consist solely of earth. For touch is as it were a mean  between all tangible qualities, and its organ is

capable of  receiving  not only all the specific qualities which characterize  earth, but also  the hot and the cold

and all other tangible  qualities whatsoever. That  is why we have no sensation by means of  bones, hair,

because they  consist of earth. So too plants,  because they consist of earth, have  no sensation. Without touch

there can be no other sense, and the organ  of touch cannot consist  of earth or of any other single element. 

It is evident, therefore, that the loss of this one sense alone  must  bring about the death of an animal. For as on

the one hand  nothing  which is not an animal can have this sense, so on the other it  is  the only one which is

indispensably necessary to what is an animal.  This explains, further, the following difference between the

other  senses and touch. In the case of all the others excess of intensity in  the qualities which they apprehend,

i.e. excess of intensity in  colour, sound, and smell, destroys not the but only the organs of  the  sense (except

incidentally, as when the sound is accompanied by an  impact or shock, or where through the objects of sight

or of smell  certain other things are set in motion, which destroy by contact);  flavour also destroys only in so

far as it is at the same time  tangible. But excess of intensity in tangible qualities, e.g. heat,  cold, or hardness,

destroys the animal itself. As in the case of every  sensible quality excess destroys the organ, so here what is

tangible  destroys touch, which is the essential mark of life; for it has been  shown that without touch it is

impossible for an animal to be. That is  why excess in intensity of tangible qualities destroys not merely  the

organ, but the animal itself, because this is the only sense which  it  must have. 

All the other senses are necessary to animals, as we have said,  not for their being, but for their wellbeing.

Such, e.g. is sight,  which, since it lives in air or water, or generally in what is  pellucid, it must have in order

to see, and taste because of what is  pleasant or painful to it, in order that it may perceive these  qualities in its

nutriment and so may desire to be set in motion,  and  hearing that it may have communication made to it, and

a tongue  that  it may communicate with its fellows. 

THE END 


ON THE SOUL

Book III 41



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. ON THE SOUL, page = 4

   3. by Aristotle, page = 4

   4.  Book I, page = 4

   5.  Book II, page = 16

   6.  Book III, page = 31