Title:   ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Bookmarks





Page No 1


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE...................................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

1..............................................................................................................................................................1

2..............................................................................................................................................................2

3..............................................................................................................................................................4

4..............................................................................................................................................................7

5..............................................................................................................................................................9

6............................................................................................................................................................12

7............................................................................................................................................................15


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

i



Top




Page No 3


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

by Aristotle

translated by J. I. Beare

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7  

1

HAVING now definitely considered the soul, by itself, and its  several faculties, we must next make a survey

of animals and all  living things, in order to ascertain what functions are peculiar,  and  what functions are

common, to them. What has been already  determined  respecting the soul  [sc. by itself]  must be assumed

throughout. The  remaining parts  [sc. the attributes of soul and  body conjointly]  of  our subject must be now

dealt with, and we may  begin with those that  come first. 

The most important attributes of animals, whether common to all or  peculiar to some, are, manifestly,

attributes of soul and body in  conjunction, e.g. sensation, memory, passion, appetite and desire in  general,

and, in addition pleasure and pain. For these may, in fact,  be said to belong to all animals. But there are,

besides these,  certain other attributes, of which some are common to all living  things, while others are

peculiar to certain species of animals. The  most important of these may be summed up in four pairs, viz.

waking  and sleeping, youth and old age, inhalation and exhalation, life and  death. We must endeavour to

arrive at a scientific conception of  these, determining their respective natures, and the causes of their

occurrence. 

But it behoves the Physical Philosopher to obtain also a clear  view of the first principles of health and

disease, inasmuch as  neither health nor disease can exist in lifeless things. Indeed we may  say of most

physical inquirers, and of those physicians who study  their art philosophically, that while the former

complete their  works  with a disquisition on medicine, the latter usually base their  medical  theories on

principles derived from Physics. 

That all the attributes above enumerated belong to soul and body  in conjunction, is obvious; for they all either

imply sensation as a  concomitant, or have it as their medium. Some are either affections or  states of

sensation, others, means of defending and safeguarding  it,  while others, again, involve its destruction or

negation. Now it  is  clear, alike by reasoning and observation, that sensation is  generated  in the soul through

the medium of the body. 

ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE 1



Top




Page No 4


We have already, in our treatise On the Soul, explained the nature  of sensation and the act of perceiving by

sense, and the reason why  this affection belongs to animals. Sensation must, indeed, be  attributed to all

animals as such, for by its presence or absence we  distinguish essentially between what is and what is not an

animal. 

But coming now to the special senses severally, we may say that  touch and taste necessarily appertain to all

animals, touch, for the  reason given in On the Soul, and taste, because of nutrition. It is by  taste that one

distinguishes in food the pleasant from the unpleasant,  so as to flee from the latter and pursue the former: and

savour in  general is an affection of nutrient matter. 

The senses which operate through external media, viz. smelling,  hearing, seeing, are found in all animals

which possess the faculty of  locomotion. To all that possess them they are a means of preservation;  their final

cause being that such creatures may, guided by  antecedent  perception, both pursue their food, and shun things

that  are bad or  destructive. But in animals which have also intelligence  they serve  for the attainment of a

higher perfection. They bring in  tidings of  many distinctive qualities of things, from which the  knowledge of

truth, speculative and practical, is generated in the  soul. 

Of the two last mentioned, seeing, regarded as a supply for the  primary wants of life, and in its direct effects,

is the superior  sense; but for developing intelligence, and in its indirect  consequences, hearing takes the

precedence. The faculty of seeing,  thanks to the fact that all bodies are coloured, brings tidings of  multitudes

of distinctive qualities of all sorts; whence it is through  this sense especially that we perceive the common

sensibles, viz.  figure, magnitude, motion, number: while hearing announces only the  distinctive qualities of

sound, and, to some few animals, those also  of voice. indirectly, however, it is hearing that contributes most

to  the growth of intelligence. For rational discourse is a cause of  instruction in virtue of its being audible,

which it is, not directly,  but indirectly; since it is composed of words, and each word is a  thoughtsymbol.

Accordingly, of persons destitute from birth of either  sense, the blind are more intelligent than the deaf and

dumb. 

2

Of the distinctive potency of each of the faculties of sense  enough has been said already. 

But as to the nature of the sensory organs, or parts of the body  in which each of the senses is naturally

implanted, inquirers now  usually take as their guide the fundamental elements of bodies. Not,  however,

finding it easy to coordinate five senses with four elements,  they are at a loss respecting the fifth sense. But

they hold the organ  of sight to consist of fire, being prompted to this view by a  certain  sensory affection of

whose true cause they are ignorant.  This is that,  when the eye is pressed or moved, fire appears to  flash from

it. This  naturally takes place in darkness, or when the  eyelids are closed, for  then, too, darkness is produced. 

This theory, however, solves one question only to raise another;  for, unless on the hypothesis that a person

who is in his full  senses  can see an object of vision without being aware of it, the  eye must on  this theory see

itself. But then why does the above  affection not  occur also when the eye is at rest? The true explanation  of

this  affection, which will contain the answer to our question,  and account  for the current notion that the eye

consists of fire, must  be  determined in the following way: Things which are smooth have the  natural property

of shining in darkness, without, however, producing  light. Now, the part of the eye called 'the black', i.e. its

central  part, is manifestly smooth. The phenomenon of the flash occurs only  when the eye is moved, because

only then could it possibly occur  that  the same one object should become as it were two. The rapidity of  the

movement has the effect of making that which sees and that which  is  seen seem different from one another.

Hence the phenomenon does not  occur unless the motion is rapid and takes place in darkness. For it  is in the

dark that that which is smooth, e.g. the heads of certain  fishes, and the sepia of the cuttlefish, naturally


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

2 2



Top




Page No 5


shines, and,  when  the movement of the eye is slow, it is impossible that that which  sees  and that which is

seen should appear to be simultaneously two and  one.  But, in fact, the eye sees itself in the above

phenomenon  merely as it  does so in ordinary optical reflexion. 

If the visual organ proper really were fire, which is the doctrine  of Empedocles, a doctrine taught also in the

Timaeus, and if vision  were the result of light issuing from the eye as from a lantern, why  should the eye not

have had the power of seeing even in the dark? It  is totally idle to say, as the Timaeus does, that the visual ray

coming forth in the darkness is quenched. What is the meaning of  this  'quenching' of light? That which, like a

fire of coals or an  ordinary  flame, is hot and dry is, indeed, quenched by the moist or  cold; but  heat and

dryness are evidently not attributes of light. Or  if they are  attributes of it, but belong to it in a degree so slight

as to be  imperceptible to us, we should have expected that in the  daytime the  light of the sun should be

quenched when rain falls, and  that darkness  should prevail in frosty weather. Flame, for example,  and ignited

bodies are subject to such extinction, but experience  shows that  nothing of this sort happens to the sunlight. 

Empedocles at times seems to hold that vision is to be explained  as above stated by light issuing forth from

the eye, e.g. in the  following passage: 

As when one who purposes going abroad prepares a lantern,

A gleam of fire blazing through the stormy night,

Adjusting thereto, to screen it from all sorts of winds,

        transparent sides,

Which scatter the breath of the winds as they blow,

While, out through them leaping, the fire,

        i.e. all the more subtile part of this,

Shines along his threshold old incessant beams:

So [Divine love] embedded the round "lens", [viz.]

        the primaeval fire fenced within the membranes,

In [its own] delicate tissues;

And these fended off the deep surrounding flood,

While leaping forth the fire, i.e. all its more subtile part.

Sometimes he accounts for vision thus, but at other times he  explains  it by emanations from the visible

objects. 

Democritus, on the other hand, is right in his opinion that the  eye is of water; not, however, when he goes on

to explain seeing as  mere mirroring. The mirroring that takes place in an eye is due to the  fact that the eye is

smooth, and it really has its seat not in the eye  which is seen, but in that which sees. For the case is merely

one of  reflexion. But it would seem that even in his time there was no  scientific knowledge of the general

subject of the formation of images  and the phenomena of reflexion. It is strange too, that it never  occurred to

him to ask why, if his theory be true, the eye alone sees,  while none of the other things in which images are

reflected do so. 

True, then, the visual organ proper is composed of water, yet  vision  appertains to it not because it is so

composed, but because it  is  translucent a property common alike to water and to air. But water  is more

easily confined and more easily condensed than air;  wherefore  it is that the pupil, i.e. the eye proper, consists

of  water. That it  does so is proved by facts of actual experience. The  substance which  flows from eyes when

decomposing is seen to be  water, and this in  undeveloped embryos is remarkably cold and  glistening. In

sanguineous  animals the white of the eye is fat and  oily, in order that the  moisture of the eye may be proof

against  freezing. Wherefore the eye  is of all parts of the body the least  sensitive to cold: no one ever  feels

cold in the part sheltered by the  eyelids. The eyes of bloodless  animals are covered with a hard scale  which

gives them similar  protection. 


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

2 3



Top




Page No 6


It is, to state the matter generally, an irrational notion that  the eye should see in virtue of something issuing

from it; that the  visual ray should extend itself all the way to the stars, or else go  out merely to a certain point,

and there coalesce, as some say, with  rays which proceed from the object. It would be better to suppose this

coalescence to take place in the fundament of the eye itself. But even  this would be mere trifling. For what is

meant by the 'coalescence' of  light with light? Or how is it possible? Coalescence does not occur  between any

two things taken at random. And how could the light within  the eye coalesce with that outside it? For the

environing membrane  comes between them. 

That without light vision is impossible has been stated elsewhere;  but, whether the medium between the eye

and its objects is air or  light, vision is caused by a process through this medium. 

Accordingly, that the inner part of the eye consists of water is  easily intelligible, water being translucent. 

Now, as vision outwardly is impossible without [extraorganic]  light, so also it is impossible inwardly

[without light within the  organ]. There must, therefore, be some translucent medium within the  eye, and, as

this is not air, it must be water. The soul or its  perceptive part is not situated at the external surface of the eye,

but obviously somewhere within: whence the necessity of the interior  of the eye being translucent, i.e.

capable of admitting light. And  that it is so is plain from actual occurrences. It is matter of  experience that

soldiers wounded in battle by a sword slash on the  temple, so inflicted as to sever the passages of [i.e. inward

from]  the eye, feel a sudden onset of darkness, as if a lamp had gone out;  because what is called the pupil, i.e.

the translucent, which is a  sort of inner lamp, is then cut off [from its connexion with the  soul]. 

Hence, if the facts be at all as here stated, it is clear that if  one should explain the nature of the sensory

organs in this way,  i.e.  by correlating each of them with one of the four elements, we  must  conceive that the

part of the eye immediately concerned in vision  consists of water, that the part immediately concerned in the

perception of sound consists of air, and that the sense of smell  consists of fire. (I say the sense of smell, not

the organ.) For the  organ of smell is only potentially that which the sense of smell, as  realized, is actually;

since the object of sense is what causes the  actualization of each sense, so that it (the sense) must (at the

instant of actualization) be (actually) that which before (the  moment  of actualization) it was potentially. Now,

odour is a  smokelike  evaporation, and smokelike evaporation arises from fire.  This also  helps us to

understand why the olfactory organ has its  proper seat in  the environment of the brain, for cold matter is

potentially hot. In  the same way must the genesis of the eye be  explained. Its structure  is an offshoot from the

brain, because the  latter is the moistest and  coldest of all the bodily parts. 

The organ of touch proper consists of earth, and the faculty of  taste is a particular form of touch. This

explains why the sensory  organ of both touch and taste is closely related to the heart. For the  heart as being

the hottest of all the bodily parts, is the  counterpoise of the brain. 

This then is the way in which the characteristics of the bodily  organs of sense must be determined. 

3

Of the sensibles corresponding to each sensory organ, viz. colour,  sound, odour, savour, touch, we have

treated in On the Soul in general  terms, having there determined what their function is, and what is  implied in

their becoming actualized in relation to their respective  organs. We must next consider what account we are

to give of any one  of them; what, for example, we should say colour is, or sound, or  odour, or savour; and so

also respecting [the object of] touch. We  begin with colour. 

Now, each of them may be spoken of from two points of view, i.e.  either as actual or as potential. We have in

On the Soul explained  in  what sense the colour, or sound, regarded as actualized [for  sensation] is the same


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

3 4



Top




Page No 7


as, and in what sense it is different from, the  correlative sensation, the actual seeing or hearing. The point of

our  present discussion is, therefore, to determine what each  sensible  object must be in itself, in order to be

perceived as it is  in actual  consciousness. 

We have already in On the Soul stated of Light that it is the  colour  of the Translucent, [being so related to it]

incidentally; for  whenever a fiery element is in a translucent medium presence there  is  Light; while the

privation of it is Darkness. But the  'Translucent',  as we call it, is not something peculiar to air, or  water, or

any  other of the bodies usually called translucent, but is a  common  'nature' and power, capable of no separate

existence of its  own, but  residing in these, and subsisting likewise in all other  bodies in a  greater or less

degree. As the bodies in which it subsists  must have  some extreme bounding surface, so too must this. Here,

then,  we may  say that Light is a 'nature' inhering in the Translucent when  the  latter is without determinate

boundary. But it is manifest that,  when  the Translucent is in determinate bodies, its bounding extreme  must

be  something real; and that colour is just this 'something' we  are  plainly taught by factscolour being actually

either at the  external  limit, or being itself that limit, in bodies. Hence it was  that the  Pythagoreans named the

superficies of a body its 'hue', for  'hue',  indeed, lies at the limit of the body; but the limit of the  body; is  not a

real thing; rather we must suppose that the same  natural  substance which, externally, is the vehicle of colour

exists  [as such  a possible vehicle] also in the interior of the body. 

Air and water, too [i.e. as well as determinately bounded bodies]  are seen to possess colour; for their

brightness is of the nature of  colour. But the colour which air or sea presents, since the body in  which it

resides is not determinately bounded, is not the same when  one approaches and views it close by as it is when

one regards it from  a distance; whereas in determinate bodies the colour presented is  definitely fixed, unless,

indeed, when the atmospheric environment  causes it to change. Hence it is clear that that in them which is

susceptible of colour is in both cases the same. It is therefore the  Translucent, according to the degree to

which it subsists in bodies  (and it does so in all more or less), that causes them to partake of  colour. But since

the colour is at the extremity of the body, it  must  be at the extremity of the Translucent in the body. Whence

it  follows  that we may define colour as the limit of the Translucent in  determinately bounded body. For

whether we consider the special  class  of bodies called translucent, as water and such others, or  determinate

bodies, which appear to possess a fixed colour of their  own, it is at  the exterior bounding surface that all alike

exhibit  their colour. 

Now, that which when present in air produces light may be present  also in the Translucent which pervades

determinate bodies; or again,  it may not be present, but there may be a privation of it.  Accordingly, as in the

case of air the one condition is light, the  other darkness, in the same way the colours White and Black are

generated in determinate bodies. 

We must now treat of the other colours, reviewing the several  hypotheses invented to explain their genesis. 

(1) It is conceivable that the White and the Black should be  juxtaposed in quantities so minute that [a particle

of] either  separately would be invisible, though the joint product [of two  particles, a black and a white] would

be visible; and that they should  thus have the other colours for resultants. Their product could, at  all events,

appear neither white nor black; and, as it must have  some  colour, and can have neither of these, this colour

must be of a  mixed  character in fact, a species of colour different from either. Such,  then, is a possible way

of conceiving the existence of a plurality  of  colours besides the White and Black; and we may suppose that

[of  this  'plurality'] many are the result of a [numerical] ratio; for  the  blacks and whites may be juxtaposed in

the ratio of 3 to 2 or of 3  to  4, or in ratios expressible by other numbers; while some may be  juxtaposed

according to no numerically expressible ratio, but  according to some relation of excess or defect in which the

blacks and  whites involved would be incommensurable quantities; and, accordingly,  we may regard all these

colours [viz. all those based on numerical  ratios] as analogous to the sounds that enter into music, and

suppose  that those involving simple numerical ratios, like the  concords in  music, may be those generally

regarded as most  agreeable; as, for  example, purple, crimson, and some few such  colours, their fewness  being


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

3 5



Top




Page No 8


due to the same causes which render the  concords few. The other  compound colours may be those which are

not  based on numbers. Or it  may be that, while all colours whatever  [except black and white] are  based on

numbers, some are regular in  this respect, others irregular;  and that the latter [though now  supposed to be all

based on numbers],  whenever they are not pure,  owe this character to a corresponding  impurity in [the

arrangement of]  their numerical ratios. This then is  one conceivable hypothesis to  explain the genesis of

intermediate  colours. 

(2) Another is that the Black and White appear the one through the  medium of the other, giving an effect like

that sometimes produced  by  painters overlaying a less vivid upon a more vivid colour, as  when  they desire to

represent an object appearing under water or  enveloped  in a haze, and like that produced by the sun, which in

itself appears  white, but takes a crimson hue when beheld through a  fog or a cloud of  smoke. On this

hypothesis, too, a variety of colours  may be conceived  to arise in the same way as that already described;  for

between those  at the surface and those underneath a definite ratio  might sometimes  exist; in other cases they

might stand in no  determinate ratio. To  [introduce a theory of colour which would set  all these hypotheses

aside, and] say with the ancients that colours  are emanations, and  that the visibility of objects is due to such a

cause, is absurd. For  they must, in any case, explain senseperception  through Touch; so  that it were better to

say at once that visual  perception is due to a  process set up by the perceived object in the  medium between

this  object and the sensory organ; due, that is, to  contact [with the  medium affected,] not to emanations. 

If we accept the hypothesis of juxtaposition, we must assume not  only invisible magnitude, but also

imperceptible time, in order that  the succession in the arrival of the stimulatory movements may be

unperceived, and that the compound colour seen may appear to be one,  owing to its successive parts seeming

to present themselves at once.  On the hypothesis of superposition, however, no such assumption is  needful:

the stimulatory process produced in the medium by the upper  colour, when this is itself unaffected, will be

different in kind from  that produced by it when affected by the underlying colour. Hence it  presents itself as a

different colour, i.e. as one which is neither  white nor black. So that, if it is impossible to suppose any

magnitude  to be invisible, and we must assume that there is some distance from  which every magnitude is

visible, this superposition theory, too [i.e.  as well as No. 3 infra], might pass as a real theory of

colourmixture. Indeed, in the previous case also there is no reason  why, to persons at a distance from the

juxtaposed blacks and whites,  some one colour should not appear to present itself as a blend of  both. [But it

would not be so on a nearer view], for it will be shown,  in a discussion to be undertaken later on, that there is

no  magnitude  absolutely invisible. 

(3) There is a mixture of bodies, however, not merely such as some  suppose, i.e. by juxtaposition of their

minimal parts, which, owing to  [the weakness of our] sense, are imperceptible by us, but a mixture by  which

they [i.e. the 'matter' of which they consist] are wholly  blent  together by interpenetration, as we have

described it in the  treatise  on Mixture, where we dealt with this subject generally in its  most  comprehensive

aspect. For, on the supposition we are criticizing,  the  only totals capable of being mixed are those which are

divisible  into  minimal parts, [e.g. genera into individuals] as men, horses,  or the  [various kinds of] seeds. For

of mankind as a whole the  individual man  is such a least part; of horses [as an aggregate] the  individual

horse. Hence by the juxtaposition of these we obtain a  mixed total,  consisting [like a troop of cavalry] of both

together;  but we do not  say that by such a process any individual man has been  mixed with any  individual

horse. Not in this way, but by complete  interpenetration  [of their matter], must we conceive those things to  be

mixed which are  not divisible into minima; and it is in the case of  these that natural  mixture exhibits itself in

its most perfect form.  We have explained  already in our discourse 'On Mixture' how such  mixture is possible.

This being the true nature of mixture, it is  plain that when bodies  are mixed their colours also are necessarily

mixed at the same time;  and [it is no less plain] that this is the  real cause determining the  existence of a

plurality of colours not  superposition or  juxtaposition. For when bodies are thus mixed,  their resultant

colour  presents itself as one and the same at all  distances alike; not  varying as it is seen nearer or farther

away. 


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

3 6



Top




Page No 9


Colours will thus, too [as well as on the former hypotheses], be  many in number on account of the fact that

the ingredients may be  combined with one another in a multitude of ratios; some will be based  on determinate

numerical ratios, while others again will have as their  basis a relation of quantitative excess or defect not

expressible in  integers. And all else that was said in reference to the colours,  considered as juxtaposed or

superposed, may be said of them likewise  when regarded as mixed in the way just described. 

Why colours, as well as savours and sounds, consist of species  determinate [in themselves] and not infinite

[in number] is a question  which we shall discuss hereafter. 

4

We have now explained what colour is, and the reason why there are  many colours; while before, in our work

On the Soul, we explained  the  nature of sound and voice. We have next to speak of Odour and  Savour,  both

of which are almost the same physical affection, although  they  each have their being in different things.

Savours, as a class,  display their nature more clearly to us than Odours, the cause of  which is that the

olfactory sense of man is inferior in acuteness to  that of the lower animals, and is, when compared with our

other  senses, the least perfect of Man's sense of Touch, on the contrary,  excels that of all other animals in

fineness, and Taste is a  modification of Touch. 

Now the natural substance water per se tends to be tasteless. But  [since without water tasting is impossible]

either (a) we must suppose  that water contains in itself [uniformly diffused through it] the  various kinds of

savour, already formed, though in amounts so small as  to be imperceptible, which is the doctrine of

Empedocles; or (b) the  water must be a sort of matter, qualified, as it were, to produce  germs of savours of all

kinds, so that all kinds of savour are  generated from the water, though different kinds from its different  parts,

or else (c) the water is in itself quite undifferentiated in  respect of savour [whether developed or

undeveloped], but some  agent,  such for example as one might conceive Heat or the Sun to be,  is the  efficient

cause of savour. 

(a) Of these three hypotheses, the falsity of that held by  Empedocles is only too evident. For we see that when

pericarpal fruits  are plucked [from the tree] and exposed in the sun, or subjected to  the action of fire, their

sapid juices are changed by the heat,  which  shows that their qualities are not due to their drawing anything

from  the water in the ground, but to a change which they undergo  within the  pericarp itself; and we see,

moreover, that these juices,  when  extracted and allowed to lie, instead of sweet become by lapse of  time

harsh or bitter, or acquire savours of any and every sort; and  that,  again, by the process of boiling or

fermentation they are made  to  assume almost all kinds of new savours. 

(b) It is likewise impossible that water should be a material  qualified to generate all kinds of Savour germs

[so that different  savours should arise out of different parts of the water]; for we  see  different kinds of taste

generated from the same water, having  it as  their nutriment. 

(C) It remains, therefore, to suppose that the water is changed by  passively receiving some affection from an

external agent. Now, it  is  manifest that water does not contract the quality of sapidity  from the  agency of Heat

alone. For water is of all liquids the  thinnest,  thinner even than oil itself, though oil, owing to its  viscosity, is

more ductile than water, the latter being uncohesive  in its particles;  whence water is more difficult than oil to

hold in  the hand without  spilling. But since perfectly pure water does not,  when subjected to  the action of

Heat, show any tendency to acquire  consistency, we must  infer that some other agency than heat is the  cause

of sapidity. For  all savours [i.e. sapid liquors] exhibit a  comparative consistency.  Heat is, however, a coagent

in the matter. 

Now the sapid juices found in pericarpal fruits evidently exist  also  in the earth. Hence many of the old natural


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

4 7



Top




Page No 10


philosophers assert  that  water has qualities like those of the earth through which it  flows,  a fact especially

manifest in the case of saline springs, for  salt  is a form of earth. Hence also when liquids are filtered through

ashes, a bitter substance, the taste they yield is bitter. There are  many wells, too, of which some are bitter,

others acid, while others  exhibit other tastes of all kinds. 

As was to be anticipated, therefore, it is in the vegetable  kingdom that tastes occur in richest variety. For, like

all things  else, the Moist, by nature's law, is affected only by its contrary;  and this contrary is the Dry. Thus

we see why the Moist is affected by  Fire, which as a natural substance, is dry. Heat is, however, the  essential

property of Fire, as Dryness is of Earth, according to  what  has been said in our treatise on the elements. Fire

and Earth,  therefore, taken absolutely as such, have no natural power to  affect,  or be affected by, one another;

nor have any other pair of  substances.  Any two things can affect, or be affected by, one  another only so far  as

contrariety to the other resides in either of  them. 

As, therefore, persons washing Colours or Savours in a liquid  cause the water in which they wash to acquire

such a quality [as  that  of the colour or savour], so nature, too, by washing the Dry  and  Earthy in the Moist,

and by filtering the latter, that is,  moving it  on by the agency of heat through the dry and earthy, imparts  to it

a  certain quality. This affection, wrought by the aforesaid  Dry in the  Moist, capable of transforming the sense

of Taste from  potentiality to  actuality, is Savour. Savour brings into actual  exercise the  perceptive faculty

which preexisted only in potency. The  activity of  senseperception in general is analogous, not to the

process of  acquiring knowledge, but to that of exercising knowledge  already  acquired. 

That Savours, either as a quality or as the privation of a  quality, belong not to every form of the Dry but to the

Nutrient, we  shall see by considering that neither the Dry without the Moist, nor  the Moist without the Dry, is

nutrient. For no single element, but  only composite substance, constitutes nutriment for animals. Now,  among

the perceptible elements of the food which animals assimilate,  the tangible are the efficient causes of growth

and decay; it is qua  hot or cold that the food assimilated causes these; for the heat or  cold is the direct cause

of growth or decay. It is qua gustable,  however, that the assimilated food supplies nutrition. For all  organisms

are nourished by the Sweet [i.e. the 'gustable' proper],  either by itself or in combination with other savours.

Of this we must  speak with more precise detail in our work on Generation: for the  present we need touch

upon it only so far as our subject here  requires. Heat causes growth, and fits the foodstuff for  alimentation;

it attracts [into the organic system] that which is  light [viz. the sweet], while the salt and bitter it rejects

because  of their heaviness. In fact, whatever effects external heat produces  in external bodies, the same are

produced by their internal heat in  animal and vegetable organisms. Hence it is [i.e. by the agency of  heat as

described] that nourishment is effected by the sweet. The  other savours are introduced into and blended in

food [naturally] on a  principle analogous to that on which the saline or the acid is used  artificially, i.e. for

seasoning. These latter are used because they  counteract the tendency of the sweet to be too nutrient, and to

float  on the stomach. 

As the intermediate colours arise from the mixture of white and  black, so the intermediate savours arise from

the Sweet and Bitter;  and these savours, too, severally involve either a definite ratio,  or  else an indefinite

relation of degree, between their components,  either having certain integral numbers at the basis of their

mixture,  and, consequently, of their stimulative effect, or else being  mixed in  proportions not arithmetically

expressible. The tastes  which give  pleasure in their combination are those which have their  components

joined in a definite ratio. 

The sweet taste alone is Rich, [therefore the latter may be  regarded  as a variety of the former], while [so far

as both imply  privation  of the Sweet] the Saline is fairly identical with the  Bitter.  Between the extremes of

sweet and bitter come the Harsh, the  Pungent, the Astringent, and the Acid. Savours and Colours, it will be

observed, contain respectively about the same number of species. For  there are seven species of each, if, as is

reasonable, we regard Dun  [or Grey] as a variety of Black (for the alternative is that Yellow  should be classed

with White, as Rich with Sweet); while [the  irreducible colours, viz.] Crimson, Violet, leekGreen, and deep


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

4 8



Top




Page No 11


Blue,  come between White and Black, and from these all others are derived by  mixture. 

Again, as Black is a privation of White in the Translucent, so  Saline or Bitter is a privation of Sweet in the

Nutrient Moist. This  explains why the ash of all burnt things is bitter; for the potable  [sc. the sweet] moisture

has been exuded from them. 

Democritus and most of the natural philosophers who treat of  senseperception proceed quite irrationally, for

they represent all  objects of sense as objects of Touch. Yet, if this is really so, it  clearly follows that each of

the other senses is a mode of Touch;  but  one can see at a glance that this is impossible. 

Again, they treat the percepts common to all senses as proper to  one. For [the qualities by which they explain

taste viz.] Magnitude  and Figure, Roughness and Smoothness, and, moreover, the Sharpness and  Bluntness

found in solid bodies, are percepts common to all the  senses, or if not to all, at least to Sight and Touch. This

explains  why it is that the senses are liable to err regarding them, while no  such error arises respecting their

proper sensibles; e.g. the sense of  Seeing is not deceived as to Colour, nor is that of Hearing as to  Sound. 

On the other hand, they reduce the proper to common sensibles, as  Democritus does with White and Black;

for he asserts that the latter  is [a mode of the] rough, and the former [a mode of the] smooth, while  he reduces

Savours to the atomic figures. Yet surely no one sense, or,  if any, the sense of Sight rather than any other, can

discern the  common sensibles. But if we suppose that the sense of Taste is  better  able to do so, then since to

discern the smallest objects in  each  kind is what marks the acutest senseTaste should have been the  sense

which best perceived the common sensibles generally, and  showed the  most perfect power of discerning

figures in general. 

Again, all the sensibles involve contrariety; e.g. in Colour White  is contrary to Black, and in Savours Bitter is

contrary to Sweet;  but  no one figure is reckoned as contrary to any other figure. Else,  to  which of the possible

polygonal figures [to which Democritus  reduces  Bitter] is the spherical figure [to which he reduces Sweet]

contrary? 

Again, since figures are infinite in number, savours also should  be infinite; [the possible rejoinder 'that they

are so, only that  some are not perceived' cannot be sustained] for why should one  savour be perceived, and

another not? 

This completes our discussion of the object of Taste, i.e. Savour;  for the other affections of Savours are

examined in their proper place  in connection with the natural history of Plants. 

5

Our conception of the nature of Odours must be analogous to that  of Savours; inasmuch as the Sapid Dry

effects in air and water  alike,  but in a different province of sense, precisely what the Dry  effects  in the Moist

of water only. We customarily predicate  Translucency of  both air and water in common; but it is not qua

translucent that  either is a vehicle of odour, but qua possessed of  a power of washing  or rinsing [and so

imbibing] the Sapid Dryness. 

For the object of Smell exists not in air only: it also exists in  water. This is proved by the case of fishes and

testacea, which are  seen to possess the faculty of smell, although water contains no air  (for whenever air is

generated within water it rises to the  surface),  and these creatures do not respire. Hence, if one were to

assume that  air and water are both moist, it would follow that Odour  is the  natural substance consisting of the

Sapid Dry diffused in the  Moist,  and whatever is of this kind would be an object of Smell. 


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

5 9



Top




Page No 12


That the property of odorousness is based upon the Sapid may be  seen  by comparing the things which possess

with those which do not  possess odour. The elements, viz. Fire, Air, Earth, Water, are  inodorous, because

both the dry and the moist among them are without  sapidity, unless some added ingredient produces it. This

explains  why  seawater possesses odour, for [unlike 'elemental' water] it  contains  savour and dryness. Salt,

too, is more odorous than natron,  as the oil  which exudes from the former proves, for natron is allied  to

['elemental'] earth more nearly than salt. Again, a stone is  inodorous, just because it is tasteless, while, on the

contrary,  wood  is odorous, because it is sapid. The kinds of wood, too, which  contain  more ['elemental']

water are less odorous than others.  Moreover, to  take the case of metals, gold is inodorous because it  is

without  taste, but bronze and iron are odorous; and when the  [sapid] moisture  has been burnt out of them,

their slag is, in all  cases, less odorous  the metals [than the metals themselves]. Silver  and tin are more

odorous than the one class of metals, less so than  the other, inasmuch  as they are water [to a greater degree

than the  former, to a less  degree than the latter]. 

Some writers look upon Fumid exhalation, which is a compound of  Earth and Air, as the essence of Odour.

[Indeed all are inclined to  rush to this theory of Odour.] Heraclitus implied his adherence to  it  when he

declared that if all existing things were turned into  Smoke,  the nose would be the organ to discern them with.

All writers  incline  to refer odour to this cause [sc. exhalation of some sort],  but some  regard it as aqueous,

others as fumid, exhalation; while  others,  again, hold it to be either. Aqueous exhalation is merely a  form of

moisture, but fumid exhalation is, as already remarked,  composed of  Air and Earth. The former when

condensed turns into water;  the latter,  in a particular species of earth. Now, it is unlikely that  odour is  either

of these. For vaporous exhalation consists of mere  water  [which, being tasteless, is inodorous]; and fumid

exhalation  cannot  occur in water at all, though, as has been before stated,  aquatic  creatures also have the

sense of smell. 

Again, the exhalation theory of odour is analogous to the theory  of emanations. If, therefore, the latter is

untenable, so, too, is the  former. 

It is clearly conceivable that the Moist, whether in air (for air,  too, is essentially moist) or in water, should

imbibe the influence  of, and have effects wrought in it by, the Sapid Dryness. Moreover, if  the Dry produces

in moist media, i.e. water and air, an effect as of  something washed out in them, it is manifest that odours

must be  something analogous to savours. Nay, indeed, this analogy is, in  some  instances, a fact [registered in

language]; for odours as well as  savours are spoken of as pungent, sweet, harsh, astringent rich  [='savoury'];

and one might regard fetid smells as analogous to bitter  tastes; which explains why the former are offensive

to inhalation as  the latter are to deglutition. It is clear, therefore, that Odour is  in both water and air what

Savour is in water alone. This explains why  coldness and freezing render Savours dull, and abolish odours

altogether; for cooling and freezing tend to annul the kinetic heat  which helps to fabricate sapidity. 

There are two species of the Odorous. For the statement of certain  writers that the odorous is not divisible

into species is false; it is  so divisible. We must here define the sense in which these species are  to be admitted

or denied. 

One class of odours, then, is that which runs parallel, as has  been observed, to savours: to odours of this class

their  pleasantness  or unpleasantness belongs incidentally. For owing to  the fact that  Savours are qualities of

nutrient matter, the odours  connected with  these [e.g. those of a certain food] are agreeable as  long as animals

have an appetite for the food, but they are not  agreeable to them when  sated and no longer in want of it; nor

are they  agreeable, either, to  those animals that do not like the food itself  which yields the  odours. Hence, as

we observed, these odours are  pleasant or unpleasant  incidentally, and the same reasoning explains  why it is

that they are  perceptible to all animals in common. 

The other class of odours consists of those agreeable in their  essential nature, e.g. those of flowers. For these

do not in any  degree stimulate animals to food, nor do they contribute in any way to  appetite; their effect


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

5 10



Top




Page No 13


upon it, if any, is rather the opposite. For  the verse of Strattis ridiculing Euripides 

        Use not perfumery to flavour soup,

contains a truth. 

Those who nowadays introduce such flavours into beverages deforce  our sense of pleasure by habituating us

to them, until, from two  distinct kinds of sensations combined, pleasure arises as it might  from one simple

kind. 

Of this species of odour man alone is sensible; the other, viz.  that  correlated with Tastes, is, as has been said

before, perceptible  also to the lower animals. And odours of the latter sort, since  their  pleasureableness

depends upon taste, are divided into as many  species  as there are different tastes; but we cannot go on to say

this  of the  former kind of odour, since its nature is agreeable or  disagreeable  per se. The reason why the

perception of such odours is  peculiar to  man is found in the characteristic state of man's brain.  For his brain  is

naturally cold, and the blood which it contains in  its vessels is  thin and pure but easily cooled (whence it

happens that  the exhalation  arising from food, being cooled by the coldness of this  region,  produces

unhealthy rheums); therefore it is that odours of  such a  species have been generated for human beings, as a

safeguard to  health. This is their sole function, and that they perform it is  evident. For food, whether dry or

moist, though sweet to taste, is  often unwholesome; whereas the odour arising from what is fragrant,  that

odour which is pleasant in its own right, is, so to say, always  beneficial to persons in any state of bodily

health whatever. 

For this reason, too, the perception of odour [in general]  effected through respiration, not in all animals, but

in man and  certain other sanguineous animals, e.g. quadrupeds, and all that  participate freely in the natural

substance air; because when  odours,  on account of the lightness of the heat in them, mount to  the brain,  the

health of this region is thereby promoted. For odour,  as a power,  is naturally heatgiving. Thus Nature has

employed  respiration for two  purposes: primarily for the relief thereby brought  to the thorax,  secondarily for

the inhalation of odour. For while an  animal is  inhaling, odour moves in through its nostrils, as it were  'from

a  sideentrance.' 

But the perception of the second class of odours above described  [does not belong to all animal, but] is

confined to human beings,  because man's brain is, in proportion to his whole bulk, larger and  moister than the

brain of any other animal. This is the reason of  the  further fact that man alone, so to speak, among animals

perceives and  takes pleasure in the odours of flowers and such things.  For the heat  and stimulation set up by

these odours are commensurate  with the  excess of moisture and coldness in his cerebral region. On  all the

other animals which have lungs, Nature has bestowed their  due  perception of one of the two kinds of odour

[i.e. that connected  with  nutrition] through the act of respiration, guarding against the  needless creation of

two organs of sense; for in the fact that they  respire the other animals have already sufficient provision for

their  perception of the one species of odour only, as human beings  have for  their perception of both. 

But that creatures which do not respire have the olfactory sense  is evident. For fishes, and all insects as a

class, have, thanks to  the species of odour correlated with nutrition, a keen olfactory sense  of their proper

food from a distance, even when they are very far away  from it; such is the case with bees, and also with the

class of  small  ants, which some denominate knipes. Among marine animals, too,  the  murex and many other

similar animals have an acute perception of  their  food by its odour. 

It is not equally certain what the organ is whereby they so  perceive. This question, of the organ whereby they

perceive odour, may  well cause a difficulty, if we assume that smelling takes place in  animals only while

respiring (for that this is the fact is manifest in  all the animals which do respire), whereas none of those just

mentioned respires, and yet they have the sense of smell unless,  indeed, they have some other sense not


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

5 11



Top




Page No 14


included in the ordinary  five.  This supposition is, however, impossible. For any sense which  perceives odour

is a sense of smell, and this they do perceive, though  probably not in the same way as creatures which respire,

but when  the  latter are respiring the current of breath removes something  that is  laid like a lid upon the organ

proper (which explains why they  do not  perceive odours when not respiring); while in creatures which  do not

respire this is always off: just as some animals have eyelids  on their  eyes, and when these are not raised they

cannot see,  whereas hardeyed  animals have no lids, and consequently do not  need, besides eyes, an  agency

to raise the lids, but see straightway  [without intermission]  from the actual moment at which it is first

possible for them to do so  [i.e. from the moment when an object  first comes within their field of  vision]. 

Consistently with what has been said above, not one of the lower  animals shows repugnance to the odour of

things which are  essentially  illsmelling, unless one of the latter is positively  pernicious. They  are destroyed,

however, by these things, just as  human beings are;  i.e. as human beings get headaches from, and are  often

asphyxiated by,  the fumes of charcoal, so the lower animals  perish from the strong  fumes of brimstone and

bituminous substances;  and it is owing to  experience of such effects that they shun these.  For the disagreeable

odour in itself they care nothing whatever  (though the odours of many  plants are essentially disagreeable),

unless, indeed, it has some  effect upon the taste of their food. 

The senses making up an odd number, and an odd number having  always a middle unit, the sense of smell

occupies in itself as it were  a middle position between the tactual senses, i.e. Touch and Taste,  and those

which perceive through a medium, i.e. Sight and Hearing.  Hence the object of smell, too, is an affection of

nutrient substances  (which fall within the class of Tangibles), and is also an affection  of the audible and the

visible; whence it is that creatures have the  sense of smell both in air and water. Accordingly, the object of

smell  is something common to both of these provinces, i.e. it appertains  both to the tangible on the one hand,

and on the other to the  audible  and translucent. Hence the propriety of the figure by which it  has  been

described by us as an immersion or washing of dryness in  the  Moist and Fluid. Such then must be our

account of the sense in  which  one is or is not entitled to speak of the odorous as having  species. 

The theory held by certain of the Pythagoreans, that some animals  are nourished by odours alone, is unsound.

For, in the first place, we  see that food must be composite, since the bodies nourished by it  are  not simple.

This explains why waste matter is secreted from  food,  either within the organisms, or, as in plants, outside

them. But  since  even water by itself alone, that is, when unmixed, will not  suffice  for food for anything

which is to form a consistency must be  corporeal, it is still much less conceivable that air should be so

corporealized [and thus fitted to be food]. But, besides this, we  see  that all animals have a receptacle for food,

from which, when it  has  entered, the body absorbs it. Now, the organ which perceives odour  is  in the head,

and odour enters with the inhalation of the breath; so  that it goes to the respiratory region. It is plain,

therefore, that  odour, qua odour, does not contribute to nutrition; that, however,  it  is serviceable to health is

equally plain, as well by immediate  perception as from the arguments above employed; so that odour is in

relation to general health what savour is in the province of nutrition  and in relation to the bodies nourished. 

This then must conclude our discussion of the several organs of  senseperception. 

6

One might ask: if every body is infinitely divisible, are its  sensible qualities Colour, Savour, Odour, Sound,

Weight, Cold or  Heat, [Heaviness or] Lightness, Hardness or Softnessalso infinitely  divisible? Or, is this

impossible? 

[One might well ask this question], because each of them is  productive of senseperception, since, in fact, all

derive their  name  [of 'sensible qualities'] from the very circumstance of their  being  able to stimulate this.

Hence, [if this is so] both our  perception of  them should likewise be divisible to infinity, and every  part of a


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

6 12



Top




Page No 15


body [however small] should be a perceptible magnitude.  For it is  impossible, e.g. to see a thing which is

white but not of  a certain  magnitude. 

Since if it were not so, [if its sensible qualities were not  divisible, pari passu with body], we might conceive a

body existing  but having no colour, or weight, or any such quality; accordingly  not  perceptible at all. For

these qualities are the objects of  senseperception. On this supposition, every perceptible object should  be

regarded as composed not of perceptible [but of imperceptible]  parts. Yet it must [be really composed of

perceptible parts], since  assuredly it does not consist of mathematical [and therefore purely  abstract and

nonsensible] quantities. Again, by what faculty should  we discern and cognize these [hypothetical real

things without  sensible qualities]? Is it by Reason? But they are not objects of  Reason; nor does reason

apprehend objects in space, except when it  acts in conjunction with senseperception. At the same time, if

this  be the case [that there are magnitudes, physically real, but without  sensible quality], it seems to tell in

favour of the atomistic  hypothesis; for thus, indeed, [by accepting this hypothesis], the  question [with which

this chapter begins] might be solved  [negatively]. But it is impossible [to accept this hypothesis]. Our  views

on the subject of atoms are to be found in our treatise on  Movement. 

The solution of these questions will bring with it also the answer  to the question why the species of Colour,

Taste, Sound, and other  sensible qualities are limited. For in all classes of things lying  between extremes the

intermediates must be limited. But contraries are  extremes, and every object of senseperception involves

contrariety:  e.g. in Colour, White x Black; in Savour, Sweet x Bitter, and in all  the other sensibles also the

contraries are extremes. Now, that  which  is continuous is divisible into an infinite number of unequal  parts,

but into a finite number of equal parts, while that which is  not per  se continuous is divisible into species

which are finite in  number.  Since then, the several sensible qualities of things are to be  reckoned as species,

while continuity always subsists in these, we  must take account of the difference between the Potential and

the  Actual. It is owing to this difference that we do not [actually] see  its tenthousandth part in a grain of

millet, although sight has  embraced the whole grain within its scope; and it is owing to this,  too, that the

sound contained in a quartertone escapes notice, and  yet one hears the whole strain, inasmuch as it is a

continuum; but the  interval between the extreme sounds [that bound the quartertone]  escapes the ear [being

only potentially audible, not actually]. So, in  the case of other objects of sense, extremely small constituents

are  unnoticed; because they are only potentially not actually [perceptible  e.g.] visible, unless when they have

been parted from the wholes. So  the footlength too exists potentially in the twofoot length, but  actually only

when it has been separated from the whole. But objective  increments so small as those above might well, if

separated from their  totals, [instead of achieving 'actual' exisistence] be dissolved in  their environments, like

a drop of sapid moisture poured out into  the  sea. But even if this were not so [sc. with the objective

magnitude],  still, since the [subjective] of senseperception is not  perceptible  in itself, nor capable of separate

existence (since it  exists only  potentially in the more distinctly perceivable whole of  senseperception), so

neither will it be possible to perceive  [actually] its correlatively small object [sc. its quantum of  pathema  or

sensible quality] when separated from the objecttotal. But  yet  this [small object] is to be considered as

perceptible: for it  is both  potentially so already [i.e. even when alone], and destined to  be  actually so when it

has become part of an aggregate. Thus,  therefore,  we have shown that some magnitudes and their sensible

qualities escape  notice, and the reason why they do so, as well as the  manner in which  they are still

perceptible or not perceptible in  such cases.  Accordingly then when these [minutely subdivided]  sensibles

have once  again become aggregated in a whole in such a  manner, relatively to one  another, as to be

perceptible actually,  and not merely because they  are in the whole, but even apart from  it, it follows

necessarily [from  what has been already stated] that  their sensible qualities, whether  colours or tastes or

sounds, are  limited in number. 

One might ask: do the objects of senseperception, or the  movements proceeding from them ([since

movements there are,] in  whichever of the two ways [viz. by emanations or by stimulatory  kinesis]

senseperception takes place), when these are actualized  for  perception, always arrive first at a spatial middle

point [between  the  senseorgan and its object], as Odour evidently does, and also  Sound?  For he who is


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

6 13



Top




Page No 16


nearer [to the odorous object] perceives the  Odour  sooner [than who is farther away], and the Sound of a

stroke  reaches  us some time after it has been struck. Is it thus also with an  object  seen, and with Light?

Empedocles, for example, says that the  Light  from the Sun arrives first in the intervening space before it

comes to  the eye, or reaches the Earth. This might plausibly seem to  be the  case. For whatever is moved [in

space], is moved from one place  to  another; hence there must be a corresponding interval of time  also in

which it is moved from the one place to the other. But any  given time  is divisible into parts; so that we should

assume a time  when the  sun's ray was not as yet seen, but was still travelling in  the middle  space. 

Now, even if it be true that the acts of 'hearing' and 'having  heard', and, generally, those of 'perceiving' and

'having  perceived',  form coinstantaneous wholes, in other words, that acts of  senseperception do not

involve a process of becoming, but have  their  being none the less without involving such a process; yet,  just

as,  [in the case of sound], though the stroke which causes the  Sound has  been already struck, the Sound is not

yet at the ear (and  that this  last is a fact is further proved by the transformation which  the  letters [viz. the

consonants as heard] undergo [in the case of  words  spoken from a distance], implying that the local

movement  [involved in  Sound] takes place in the space between [us and the  speaker]; for the  reason why

[persons addressed from a distance] do  not succeed in  catching the sense of what is said is evidently that  the

air [sound  wave] in moving towards them has its form changed)  [granting this,  then, the question arises]: is

the same also true in  the case of  Colour and Light? For certainly it is not true that the  beholder sees,  and the

object is seen, in virtue of some merely  abstract relationship  between them, such as that between equals. For

if it were so, there  would be no need [as there is] that either [the  beholder or the thing  beheld] should occupy

some particular place;  since to the equalization  of things their being near to, or far  from, one another makes

no  difference. 

Now this [travelling through successive positions in the medium]  may  with good reason take place as regards

Sound and Odour, for these,  like [their media] Air and Water, are continuous, but the movement  of  both is

divided into parts. This too is the ground of the fact that  the object which the person first in order of

proximity hears or  smells is the same as that which each subsequent person perceives,  while yet it is not the

same. 

Some, indeed, raise a question also on these very points; they  declare it impossible that one person should

hear, or see, or smell,  the same object as another, urging the impossibility of several  persons in different

places hearing or smelling [the same object], for  the one same thing would [thus] be divided from itself. The

answer  is  that, in perceiving the object which first set up the motion e.g.  a  bell, or frankincense, or fire all

perceive an object numerically  one  and the same; while, of course, in the special object perceived  they

perceive an object numerically different for each, though  specifically  the same for all; and this, accordingly,

explains how it  is that many  persons together see, or smell, or hear [the same  object]. These  things [the odour

or sound proper] are not bodies, but  an affection or  process of some kind (otherwise this [viz.  simultaneous

perception of  the one object by many] would not have  been, as it is, a fact of  experience) though, on the other

hand, they  each imply a body [as  their cause]. 

But [though sound and odour may travel,] with regard to Light the  case is different. For Light has its raison

d'etre in the being [not  becoming] of something, but it is not a movement. And in general, even  in qualitative

change the case is different from what it is in local  movement [both being different species of kinesis]. Local

movements,  of course, arrive first at a point midway before reaching their goal  (and Sound, it is currently

believed, is a movement of something  locally moved), but we cannot go on to assert this [arrival at a point

midway] like manner of things which undergo qualitative change. For  this kind of change may conceivably

take place in a thing all at once,  without one half of it being changed before the other; e.g. it is  conceivable

that water should be frozen simultaneously in every  part.  But still, for all that, if the body which is heated or

frozen  is  extensive, each part of it successively is affected by the part  contiguous, while the part first changed

in quality is so changed by  the cause itself which originates the change, and thus the change  throughout the

whole need not take place coinstantaneously and all  at  once. Tasting would have been as smelling now is, if


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

6 14



Top




Page No 17


we lived in  a  liquid medium, and perceived [the sapid object] at a distance,  before  touching it. 

Naturally, then, the parts of media between a sensory organ and  its object are not all affected at once except

in the case of Light  [illumination] for the reason above stated, and also in the case of  seeing, for the same

reason; for Light is an efficient cause of  seeing. 

7

Another question respecting senseperception is as follows:  assuming, as is natural, that of two

[simultaneous] sensory stimuli  the stronger always tends to extrude the weaker [from  consciousness],  is it

conceivable or not that one should be able to  discern two  objects coinstantaneously in the same individual

time? The  above  assumption explains why persons do not perceive what is  brought before  their eyes, if they

are at the time deep in thought, or  in a fright,  or listening to some loud noise. This assumption, then,  must be

made,  and also the following: that it is easier to discern  each object of  sense when in its simple form than

when an ingredient  in a mixture;  easier, for example, to discern wine when neat than when  blended, and  so

also honey, and [in other provinces] a colour, or to  discern the  nete by itself alone, than [when sounded with

the  hypate] in the  octave; the reason being that component elements tend  to efface [the  distinctive

characteristics of] one another. Such is  the effect [on  one another] of all ingredients of which, when

compounded, some one  thing is formed. 

If, then, the greater stimulus tends to expel the less, it  necessarily follows that, when they concur, this greater

should itself  too be less distinctly perceptible than if it were alone, since the  less by blending with it has

removed some of its individuality,  according to our assumption that simple objects are in all cases  more

distinctly perceptible. 

Now, if the two stimuli are equal but heterogeneous, no perception  of either will ensue; they will alike efface

one another's  characteristics. But in such a case the perception of either  stimulus  in its simple form is

impossible. Hence either there will  then be no  senseperception at all, or there will be a perception

compounded of  both and differing from either. The latter is what  actually seems to  result from ingredients

blended together, whatever  may be the compound  in which they are so mixed. 

Since, then, from some concurrent [sensory stimuli] a resultant  object is produced, while from others no such

resultant is produced,  and of the latter sort are those things which belong to different  sense provinces (for

only those things are capable of mixture whose  extremes are contraries, and no one compound can be formed

from,  e.g.  White and Sharp, except indirectly, i.e. not as a concord is  formed of  Sharp and Grave); there

follows logically the  impossibility of  discerning such concurrent stimuli coinstantaneously.  For we must

suppose that the stimuli, when equal, tend alike to efface  one  another, since no one [form of stimulus] results

from them; while,  if  they are unequal, the stronger alone is distinctly perceptible. 

Again, the soul would be more likely to perceive  coinstantaneously, with one and the same sensory act, two

things in  the same sensory province, such as the Grave and the Sharp in sound;  for the sensory stimulation in

this one province is more likely to  be  unitemporal than that involving two different provinces, as Sight  and

Hearing. But it is impossible to perceive two objects  coinstantaneously in the same sensory act unless they

have been mixed,  [when, however, they are no longer two], for their amalgamation  involves their becoming

one, and the sensory act related to one object  is itself one, and such act, when one, is, of course,

coinstantaneous  with itself. Hence, when things are mixed we of  necessity perceive  them coinstantaneously:

for we perceive them by a  perception actually  one. For an object numerically one means that  which is

perceived by a  perception actually one, whereas an object  specifically one means that  which is perceived by a

sensory act  potentially one [i.e. by an  energeia of the same sensuous faculty]. If  then the actualized

perception is one, it will declare its data to  be one object; they  must, therefore, have been mixed.


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

7 15



Top




Page No 18


Accordingly,  when they have not been  mixed, the actualized perceptions which  perceive them will be two;

but  [if so, their perception must be  successive not coinstantaneous, for]  in one and the same faculty the

perception actualized at any single  moment is necessarily one, only  one stimulation or exertion of a  single

faculty being possible at a  single instant, and in the case  supposed here the faculty is one. It  follows,

therefore, that we  cannot conceive the possibility of  perceiving two distinct objects  coinstantaneously with

one and the  same sense. 

But if it be thus impossible to perceive coinstantaneously two  objects in the same province of sense if they

are really two,  manifestly it is still less conceivable that we should perceive  coinstantaneously objects in two

different sensory provinces, as White  and Sweet. For it appears that when the Soul predicates numerical  unity

it does so in virtue of nothing else than such coinstantaneous  perception [of one object, in one instant, by one

energeia]: while  it  predicates specific unity in virtue of [the unity of] the  discriminating faculty of sense

together with [the unity of] the  mode  in which this operates. What I mean, for example, is this; the  same

sense no doubt discerns White and Black, [which are hence  generically  one] though specifically different

from one another, and  so, too, a  faculty of sense selfidentical, but different from the  former,  discerns Sweet

and Bitter; but while both these faculties  differ from  one another [and each from itself] in their modes of

discerning either  of their respective contraries, yet in perceiving  the coordinates in  each province they

proceed in manners analogous to  one another; for  instance, as Taste perceives Sweet, so Sight  perceives

White; and as  the latter perceives Black, so the former  perceives Bitter. 

Again, if the stimuli of sense derived from Contraries are  themselves Contrary, and if Contraries cannot be

conceived as  subsisting together in the same individual subject, and if Contraries,  e.g. Sweet and Bitter, come

under one and the same sensefaculty, we  must conclude that it is impossible to discern them

coinstantaneously.  It is likewise clearly impossible so to discern such homogeneous  sensibles as are not

[indeed] Contrary, [but are yet of different  species]. For these are, [in the sphere of colour, for instance],

classed some with White, others with Black, and so it is, likewise, in  the other provinces of sense; for

example, of savours, some are  classed with Sweet, and others with Bitter. Nor can one discern the

components in compounds coinstantaneously (for these are ratios of  Contraries, as e.g. the Octave or the

Fifth); unless, indeed, on  condition of perceiving them as one. For thus, and not otherwise,  the  ratios of the

extreme sounds are compounded into one ratio:  since we  should have together the ratio, on the one hand, of

Many to  Few or of  Odd to Even, on the other, that of Few to Many or of Even to  Odd [and  these, to be

perceived together, must be unified]. 

If, then, the sensibles denominated coordinates though in  different  provinces of sense (e.g. I call Sweet and

White coordinates  though in  different provinces) stand yet more aloof, and differ more,  from one  another

than do any sensibles in the same province; while  Sweet  differs from White even more than Black does from

White, it is  still  less conceivable that one should discern them [viz. sensibles in  different sensory provinces

whether coordinates or not]  coinstantaneously than sensibles which are in the same province.  Therefore, if

coinstantaneous perception of the latter be  impossible,  that of the former is a fortiori impossible. 

Some of the writers who treat of concords assert that the sounds  combined in these do not reach us

simultaneously, but only appear to  do so, their real successiveness being unnoticed whenever the time  it

involves is [so small as to be] imperceptible. Is this true or not?  One might perhaps, following this up, go so

far as to say that even  the current opinion that one sees and hears coinstantaneously is due  merely to the fact

that the intervals of time [between the really  successive perceptions of sight and hearing] escape observation.

But  this can scarcely be true, nor is it conceivable that any portion of  time should be [absolutely]

imperceptible, or that any should be  absolutely unnoticeable; the truth being that it is possible to  perceive

every instant of time. [This is so]; because, if it is  inconceivable that a person should, while perceiving

himself or  aught  else in a continuous time, be at any instant unaware of his  own  existence; while, obviously,

the assumption, that there is in  the  timecontinuum a time so small as to be absolutely  imperceptible,  carries

the implication that a person would, during  such time, be  unaware of his own existence, as well as of his


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

7 16



Top




Page No 19


seeing  and perceiving;  [this assumption must be false]. 

Again, if there is any magnitude, whether time or thing,  absolutely imperceptible owing to its smallness, it

follows that there  would not be either a thing which one perceives, or a time in which  one perceives it, unless

in the sense that in some part of the given  time he sees some part of the given thing. For [let there be a line

ab, divided into two parts at g, and let this line represent a whole  object and a corresponding whole time.

Now,] if one sees the whole  line, and perceives it during a time which forms one and the same  continuum,

only in the sense that he does so in some portion of this  time, let us suppose the part gb, representing a time

in which by  supposition he was perceiving nothing, cut off from the whole. Well,  then, he perceives in a

certain part [viz. in the remainder] of the  time, or perceives a part [viz. the remainder] of the line, after  the

fashion in which one sees the whole earth by seeing some given  part of  it, or walks in a year by walking in

some given part of the  year. But  [by hypothesis] in the part bg he perceives nothing:  therefore, in  fact, he is

said to perceive the whole object and during  the whole  time simply because he perceives [some part of the

object]  in some  part of the time ab. But the same argument holds also in the  case of  ag [the remainder,

regarded in its turn as a whole]; for it  will be  found [on this theory of vacant times and imperceptible

magnitudes]  that one always perceives only in some part of a given  whole time, and  perceives only some part

of a whole magnitude, and  that it is  impossible to perceive any [really] whole [object in a  really whole  time; a

conclusion which is absurd, as it would logically  annihilate  the perception of both Objects and Time]. 

Therefore we must conclude that all magnitudes are perceptible,  but their actual dimensions do not present

themselves immediately in  their presentation as objects. One sees the sun, or a fourcubit rod  at a distance, as

a magnitude, but their exact dimensions are not  given in their visual presentation: nay, at times an object of

sight  appears indivisible, but [vision like other special senses, is  fallible respecting 'common sensibles', e.g.

magnitude, and] nothing  that one sees is really indivisible. The reason of this has been  previously explained.

It is clear then, from the above arguments, that  no portion of time is imperceptible. 

But we must here return to the question proposed above for  discussion, whether it is possible or impossible to

perceive several  objects coinstantaneously; by 'coinstantaneously' I mean perceiving  the several objects in a

time one and indivisible relatively to one  another, i.e. indivisible in a sense consistent with its being all a

continuum. 

First, then, is it conceivable that one should perceive the  different things coinstantaneously, but each with a

different part  of  the Soul? Or [must we object] that, in the first place, to begin  with  the objects of one and the

same sense, e.g. Sight, if we assume  it  [the Soul qua exercising Sight] to perceive one colour with one  part,

and another colour with a different part, it will have a  plurality of  parts the same in species, [as they must be,]

since the  objects which  it thus perceives fall within the same genus? 

Should any one [to illustrate how the Soul might have in it two  different parts specifically identical, each

directed to a set of  aistheta the same in genus with that to which the other is directed]  urge that, as there are

two eyes, so there may be in the Soul  something analogous, [the reply is] that of the eyes, doubtless,  some

one organ is formed, and hence their actualization in  perception is  one; but if this is so in the Soul, then, in so

far as  what is formed  of both [i.e. of any two specifically identical parts  as assumed] is  one, the true

perceiving subject also will be one, [and  the  contradictory of the above hypothesis (of different parts of  Soul

remaining engaged in simultaneous perception with one sense) is  what  emerges from the analogy]; while if

the two parts of Soul  remain  separate, the analogy of the eyes will fail, [for of these some  one is  really

formed]. 

Furthermore, [on the supposition of the need of different parts of  Soul, cooperating in each sense, to discern

different objects  coinstantaneously], the senses will be each at the same time one and  many, as if we should

say that they were each a set of diverse  sciences; for neither will an 'activity' exist without its proper  faculty,

nor without activity will there be sensation. 


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

7 17



Top




Page No 20


But if the Soul does not, in the way suggested [i.e. with  different parts of itself acting simultaneously],

perceive in one  and  the same individual time sensibles of the same sense, a fortiori  it is  not thus that it

perceives sensibles of different senses. For it  is,  as already stated, more conceivable that it should perceive a

plurality of the former together in this way than a plurality of  heterogeneous objects. 

If then, as is the fact, the Soul with one part perceives Sweet,  with another, White, either that which results

from these is some  one  part, or else there is no such one resultant. But there must be  such  an one, inasmuch as

the general faculty of senseperception is  one.  What one object, then, does that one faculty [when perceiving

an  object, e.g. as both White and Sweet] perceive? [None]; for  assuredly  no one object arises by composition

of these  [heterogeneous objects,  such as White and Sweet]. We must conclude,  therefore, that there is,  as has

been stated before, some one  faculty in the soul with which the  latter perceives all its  percepts, though it

perceives each different  genus of sensibles  through a different organ. 

May we not, then, conceive this faculty which perceives White and  Sweet to be one qua indivisible [sc. qua

combining its different  simultaneous objects] in its actualization, but different, when it has  become divisible

[sc. qua distinguishing its different simultaneous  objects] in its actualization? 

Or is what occurs in the case of the perceiving Soul conceivably  analogous to what holds true in that of the

things themselves? For the  same numerically one thing is white and sweet, and has many other  qualities,

[while its numerical oneness is not thereby prejudiced]  if  the fact is not that the qualities are really separable

in the  object  from one another, but that the being of each quality is  different  [from that of every other]. In the

same way therefore we  must assume  also, in the case of the Soul, that the faculty of  perception in  general is

in itself numerically one and the same, but  different  [differentiated] in its being; different, that is to say, in

genus as  regards some of its objects, in species as regards others.  Hence too,  we may conclude that one can

perceive [numerically  different objects]  coinstantaneously with a faculty which is  numerically one and the

same, but not the same in its relationship  [sc. according as the  objects to which it is directed are not the

same]. 

That every sensible object is a magnitude, and that nothing which  it  is possible to perceive is indivisible, may

be thus shown. The  distance whence an object could not be seen is indeterminate, but that  whence it is visible

is determinate. We may say the same of the  objects of Smelling and Hearing, and of all sensibles not

discerned by  actual contact. Now, there is, in the interval of distance, some  extreme place, the last from

which the object is invisible, and the  first from which it is visible. This place, beyond which if the object  be

one cannot perceive it, while if the object be on the hither side  one must perceive it, is, I presume, itself

necessarily indivisible.  Therefore, if any sensible object be indivisible, such object, if  set  in the said extreme

place whence imperceptibility ends and  perceptibility begins, will have to be both visible and invisible  their

objects, whether regarded in general or at the same time; but  this is impossible. 

This concludes our survey of the characteristics of the organs of  Senseperception and their objects, whether

regarded in general or  in  relation to each organ. Of the remaining subjects, we must first  consider that of

memory and remembering. 

THE END 


ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE

7 18



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. ON SENSE AND THE SENSIBLE, page = 4

   3. by Aristotle, page = 4

   4.  1, page = 4

   5.  2, page = 5

   6.  3, page = 7

   7.  4, page = 10

   8.  5, page = 12

   9.  6, page = 15

   10.  7, page = 18