Title:   POLITICS

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Page No 44

Page No 45

Page No 46

Page No 47

Page No 48

Page No 49

Page No 50

Page No 51

Page No 52

Page No 53

Page No 54

Page No 55

Page No 56

Page No 57

Page No 58

Page No 59

Page No 60

Page No 61

Page No 62

Page No 63

Page No 64

Page No 65

Page No 66

Page No 67

Page No 68

Page No 69

Page No 70

Page No 71

Page No 72

Page No 73

Page No 74

Page No 75

Page No 76

Page No 77

Page No 78

Page No 79

Page No 80

Page No 81

Page No 82

Page No 83

Page No 84

Page No 85

Page No 86

Page No 87

Page No 88

Page No 89

Page No 90

Page No 91

Page No 92

Page No 93

Page No 94

Page No 95

Page No 96

Page No 97

Page No 98

Page No 99

Page No 100

Page No 101

Page No 102

Page No 103

Page No 104

Page No 105

Page No 106

Page No 107

Page No 108

Page No 109

Page No 110

Page No 111

Page No 112

Page No 113

Page No 114

Bookmarks





Page No 1


POLITICS

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

POLITICS...........................................................................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

BOOK ONE ............................................................................................................................................3

I...............................................................................................................................................................3

II ..............................................................................................................................................................4

III .............................................................................................................................................................5

IV............................................................................................................................................................5

V ..............................................................................................................................................................6

VI............................................................................................................................................................7

VII ...........................................................................................................................................................8

VIII ..........................................................................................................................................................8

IX............................................................................................................................................................9

X ............................................................................................................................................................11

XI..........................................................................................................................................................11

XII .........................................................................................................................................................12

XIII ........................................................................................................................................................13

BOOK TWO......................................................................................................................................................14

I.............................................................................................................................................................14

II ............................................................................................................................................................14

III ...........................................................................................................................................................15

IV..........................................................................................................................................................16

V ............................................................................................................................................................17

VI..........................................................................................................................................................19

VII .........................................................................................................................................................20

VIII ........................................................................................................................................................22

IX..........................................................................................................................................................24

X ............................................................................................................................................................27

XI..........................................................................................................................................................28

XII .........................................................................................................................................................29

BOOK THREE..................................................................................................................................................31

I.............................................................................................................................................................31

II ............................................................................................................................................................32

III ...........................................................................................................................................................32

IV..........................................................................................................................................................33

V ............................................................................................................................................................34

VI..........................................................................................................................................................35

VII .........................................................................................................................................................36

VIII ........................................................................................................................................................36

IX..........................................................................................................................................................37

X ............................................................................................................................................................38

XI..........................................................................................................................................................39

XII .........................................................................................................................................................40

XIII ........................................................................................................................................................41

XIV.......................................................................................................................................................42

XV .........................................................................................................................................................44

XVI.......................................................................................................................................................45

XVII......................................................................................................................................................46

XVIII .....................................................................................................................................................47


POLITICS

i



Top




Page No 3


Table of Contents

BOOK FOUR .....................................................................................................................................................47

I.............................................................................................................................................................47

II ............................................................................................................................................................48

III ...........................................................................................................................................................49

IV..........................................................................................................................................................49

V ............................................................................................................................................................52

VI..........................................................................................................................................................52

VII .........................................................................................................................................................53

VIII ........................................................................................................................................................53

IX..........................................................................................................................................................54

X ............................................................................................................................................................55

XI..........................................................................................................................................................55

XII .........................................................................................................................................................57

XIII ........................................................................................................................................................57

XIV.......................................................................................................................................................58

XV .........................................................................................................................................................60

XVI.......................................................................................................................................................62

BOOK FIVE......................................................................................................................................................62

I.............................................................................................................................................................63

II ............................................................................................................................................................64

III ...........................................................................................................................................................64

IV..........................................................................................................................................................66

V ............................................................................................................................................................67

VI..........................................................................................................................................................68

VII .........................................................................................................................................................69

VIII ........................................................................................................................................................70

IX..........................................................................................................................................................72

X ............................................................................................................................................................74

XI..........................................................................................................................................................77

XII .........................................................................................................................................................79

BOOK SIX .........................................................................................................................................................81

I.............................................................................................................................................................81

II ............................................................................................................................................................82

III ...........................................................................................................................................................82

IV..........................................................................................................................................................83

V ............................................................................................................................................................84

VI..........................................................................................................................................................85

VII .........................................................................................................................................................86

VIII ........................................................................................................................................................86

BOOK SEVEN..................................................................................................................................................88

I.............................................................................................................................................................88

II ............................................................................................................................................................89

III ...........................................................................................................................................................90

IV..........................................................................................................................................................91

V ............................................................................................................................................................92

VI..........................................................................................................................................................92

VII .........................................................................................................................................................93

VIII ........................................................................................................................................................94


POLITICS

ii



Top




Page No 4


Table of Contents

IX..........................................................................................................................................................95

X ............................................................................................................................................................95

XI..........................................................................................................................................................96

XII .........................................................................................................................................................97

XIII ........................................................................................................................................................98

XIV.......................................................................................................................................................99

XV .......................................................................................................................................................101

XVI.....................................................................................................................................................102

XVII....................................................................................................................................................103

BOOK EIGHT.................................................................................................................................................104

I...........................................................................................................................................................104

II ..........................................................................................................................................................104

III .........................................................................................................................................................105

IV........................................................................................................................................................106

V ..........................................................................................................................................................107

VI........................................................................................................................................................108

VII .......................................................................................................................................................109


POLITICS

iii



Top




Page No 5


POLITICS

by Aristotle

Translated by Benjamin Jowett

BOOK ONE 

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII 

VIII 

IX 

X 

XI 

XII 

XIII 

BOOK TWO  

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII 

VIII 

IX 

X 

XI 

XII  

BOOK THREE  

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII 

VIII 

IX 

X 

XI  

POLITICS 1



Top




Page No 6


XII 

XIII 

XIV 

XV 

XVI 

XVII 

XVIII  

BOOK FOUR  

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII 

VIII 

IX 

X 

XI 

XII 

XIII 

XIV 

XV 

XVI  

BOOK FIVE  

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII 

VIII 

IX 

X 

XI 

XII  

BOOK SIX  

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII 

VIII  

BOOK SEVEN  

I 

II 

III 

IV  


POLITICS

POLITICS 2



Top




Page No 7


V 

VI 

VII 

VIII 

IX 

X 

XI 

XII 

XIII 

XIV 

XV 

XVI 

XVII  

BOOK EIGHT  

I 

II 

III 

IV 

V 

VI 

VII  

BOOK ONE

I

EVERY STATE is a community of some kind, and every community is  established with a view to some

good; for mankind always act in  order  to obtain that which they think good. But, if all communities  aim at

some good, the state or political community, which is the  highest of  all, and which embraces all the rest, aims

at good in a  greater degree  than any other, and at the highest good. 

Some people think that the qualifications of a statesman, king,  householder, and master are the same, and that

they differ, not in  kind, but only in the number of their subjects. For example, the ruler  over a few is called a

master; over more, the manager of a  household;  over a still larger number, a statesman or king, as if  there

were no  difference between a great household and a small  state. The  distinction which is made between the

king and the  statesman is as  follows: When the government is personal, the ruler is  a king; when,  according to

the rules of the political science, the  citizens rule and  are ruled in turn, then he is called a statesman. 

But all this is a mistake; for governments differ in kind, as will  be evident to any one who considers the

matter according to the method  which has hitherto guided us. As in other departments of science, so  in

politics, the compound should always be resolved into the simple  elements or least parts of the whole. We

must therefore look at the  elements of which the state is composed, in order that we may see in  what the

different kinds of rule differ from one another, and  whether  any scientific result can be attained about each

one of them. 


POLITICS

BOOK ONE 3



Top




Page No 8


II

He who thus considers things in their first growth and origin,  whether a state or anything else, will obtain the

clearest view of  them. In the first place there must be a union of those who cannot  exist without each other;

namely, of male and female, that the race  may continue (and this is a union which is formed, not of deliberate

purpose, but because, in common with other animals and with plants,  mankind have a natural desire to leave

behind them an image of  themselves), and of natural ruler and subject, that both may be  preserved. For that

which can foresee by the exercise of mind is by  nature intended to be lord and master, and that which can

with its  body give effect to such foresight is a subject, and by nature a  slave; hence master and slave have the

same interest. Now nature has  distinguished between the female and the slave. For she is not  niggardly, like

the smith who fashions the Delphian knife for many  uses; she makes each thing for a single use, and every

instrument is  best made when intended for one and not for many uses. But among  barbarians no distinction is

made between women and slaves, because  there is no natural ruler among them: they are a community of

slaves,  male and female. Wherefore the poets say, 

It is meet that Hellenes should rule over barbarians;  as if they  thought that the barbarian and the slave were

by nature  one. 

Out of these two relationships between man and woman, master and  slave, the first thing to arise is the

family, and Hesiod is right  when he says, 

First house and wife and an ox for the plough,  for the ox is the  poor man's slave. The family is the association

established by nature  for the supply of men's everyday wants, and  the members of it are  called by Charondas

'companions of the  cupboard,' and by Epimenides  the Cretan, 'companions of the manger.'  But when several

families are  united, and the association aims at  something more than the supply of  daily needs, the first

society to be  formed is the village. And the  most natural form of the village  appears to be that of a colony

from  the family, composed of the  children and grandchildren, who are said  to be suckled 'with the  same milk.'

And this is the reason why  Hellenic states were originally  governed by kings; because the  Hellenes were

under royal rule before  they came together, as the  barbarians still are. Every family is ruled  by the eldest, and

therefore in the colonies of the family the  kingly form of government  prevailed because they were of the

same  blood. As Homer says: 

Each one gives law to his children and to his wives.  For they  lived dispersedly, as was the manner in ancient

times.  Wherefore men  say that the Gods have a king, because they themselves  either are or  were in ancient

times under the rule of a king. For they  imagine, not  only the forms of the Gods, but their ways of life to  be

like their  own. 

When several villages are united in a single complete community,  large enough to be nearly or quite

selfsufficing, the state comes  into existence, originating in the bare needs of life, and  continuing  in existence

for the sake of a good life. And therefore, if  the  earlier forms of society are natural, so is the state, for it is  the

end of them, and the nature of a thing is its end. For what each  thing  is when fully developed, we call its

nature, whether we are  speaking  of a man, a horse, or a family. Besides, the final cause  and end of a  thing is

the best, and to be selfsufficing is the end  and the best. 

Hence it is evident that the state is a creation of nature, and  that  man is by nature a political animal. And he

who by nature and not  by  mere accident is without a state, is either a bad man or above  humanity; he is like

the 

Tribeless, lawless, hearthless one,  whom Homer denounces the  natural outcast is forthwith a lover of war;

he may be compared to an  isolated piece at draughts. 


POLITICS

II 4



Top




Page No 9


Now, that man is more of a political animal than bees or any other  gregarious animals is evident. Nature, as

we often say, makes  nothing  in vain, and man is the only animal whom she has endowed  with the gift  of

speech. And whereas mere voice is but an indication  of pleasure or  pain, and is therefore found in other

animals (for  their nature  attains to the perception of pleasure and pain and the  intimation of  them to one

another, and no further), the power of  speech is intended  to set forth the expedient and inexpedient, and

therefore likewise the  just and the unjust. And it is a characteristic  of man that he alone  has any sense of good

and evil, of just and  unjust, and the like, and  the association of living beings who have  this sense makes a

family  and a state. 

Further, the state is by nature clearly prior to the family and to  the individual, since the whole is of necessity

prior to the part; for  example, if the whole body be destroyed, there will be no foot or  hand, except in an

equivocal sense, as we might speak of a stone hand;  for when destroyed the hand will be no better than that.

But things  are defined by their working and power; and we ought not to say that  they are the same when they

no longer have their proper quality, but  only that they have the same name. The proof that the state is a

creation of nature and prior to the individual is that the individual,  when isolated, is not selfsufficing; and

therefore he is like a  part  in relation to the whole. But he who is unable to live in  society, or  who has no need

because he is sufficient for himself, must  be either a  beast or a god: he is no part of a state. A social  instinct is

implanted in all men by nature, and yet he who first  founded the state  was the greatest of benefactors. For

man, when  perfected, is the best  of animals, but, when separated from law and  justice, he is the worst  of all;

since armed injustice is the more  dangerous, and he is  equipped at birth with arms, meant to be used  by

intelligence and  virtue, which he may use for the worst ends.  Wherefore, if he have not  virtue, he is the most

unholy and the most  savage of animals, and the  most full of lust and gluttony. But justice  is the bond of men

in  states, for the administration of justice, which  is the determination  of what is just, is the principle of order

in  political society. 

III

Seeing then that the state is made up of households, before  speaking  of the state we must speak of the

management of the  household. The  parts of household management correspond to the persons  who compose

the household, and a complete household consists of slaves  and  freemen. Now we should begin by examining

everything in its fewest  possible elements; and the first and fewest possible parts of a family  are master and

slave, husband and wife, father and children. We have  therefore to consider what each of these three relations

is and  ought  to be: I mean the relation of master and servant, the marriage  relation (the conjunction of man

and wife has no name of its own), and  thirdly, the procreative relation (this also has no proper name).  And

there is another element of a household, the socalled art of  getting  wealth, which, according to some, is

identical with  household  management, according to others, a principal part of it; the  nature of  this art will

also have to be considered by us. 

Let us first speak of master and slave, looking to the needs of  practical life and also seeking to attain some

better theory of  their  relation than exists at present. For some are of opinion that  the rule  of a master is a

science, and that the management of a  household, and  the mastership of slaves, and the political and royal

rule, as I was  saying at the outset, are all the same. Others affirm  that the rule of  a master over slaves is

contrary to nature, and  that the distinction  between slave and freeman exists by law only, and  not by nature;

and  being an interference with nature is therefore  unjust. 

IV

Property is a part of the household, and the art of acquiring  property is a part of the art of managing the

household; for no man  can live well, or indeed live at all, unless he be provided with  necessaries. And as in

the arts which have a definite sphere the  workers must have their own proper instruments for the


POLITICS

III 5



Top




Page No 10


accomplishment  of their work, so it is in the management of a  household. Now  instruments are of various

sorts; some are living,  others lifeless; in  the rudder, the pilot of a ship has a lifeless, in  the lookout man, a

living instrument; for in the arts the servant  is a kind of  instrument. Thus, too, a possession is an instrument

for maintaining  life. And so, in the arrangement of the family, a  slave is a living  possession, and property a

number of such  instruments; and the servant  is himself an instrument which takes  precedence of all other

instruments. For if every instrument could  accomplish its own work,  obeying or anticipating the will of

others,  like the statues of  Daedalus, or the tripods of Hephaestus, which,  says the poet, 

of their own accord entered the assembly of the Gods;  if, in like  manner, the shuttle would weave and the

plectrum touch the  lyre  without a hand to guide them, chief workmen would not want  servants,  nor masters

slaves. Here, however, another distinction  must be drawn;  the instruments commonly so called are

instruments of  production,  whilst a possession is an instrument of action. The  shuttle, for  example, is not only

of use; but something else is made  by it, whereas  of a garment or of a bed there is only the use.  Further, as

production  and action are different in kind, and both  require instruments, the  instruments which they employ

must likewise  differ in kind. But life  is action and not production, and therefore  the slave is the minister  of

action. Again, a possession is spoken  of as a part is spoken of;  for the part is not only a part of  something

else, but wholly belongs  to it; and this is also true of a  possession. The master is only the  master of the slave;

he does not  belong to him, whereas the slave is  not only the slave of his  master, but wholly belongs to him.

Hence we  see what is the nature and  office of a slave; he who is by nature not  his own but another's  man, is

by nature a slave; and he may be said to  be another's man who,  being a human being, is also a possession.

And a  possession may be  defined as an instrument of action, separable from  the possessor. 

V

But is there any one thus intended by nature to be a slave, and  for whom such a condition is expedient and

right, or rather is not all  slavery a violation of nature? 

There is no difficulty in answering this question, on grounds both  of reason and of fact. For that some should

rule and others be ruled  is a thing not only necessary, but expedient; from the hour of their  birth, some are

marked out for subjection, others for rule. 

And there are many kinds both of rulers and subjects (and that  rule is the better which is exercised over better

subjects for  example, to rule over men is better than to rule over wild beasts; for  the work is better which is

executed by better workmen, and where  one  man rules and another is ruled, they may be said to have a

work); for  in all things which form a composite whole and which are  made up of  parts, whether continuous or

discrete, a distinction  between the  ruling and the subject element comes to fight. Such a  duality exists  in

living creatures, but not in them only; it  originates in the  constitution of the universe; even in things which

have no life there  is a ruling principle, as in a musical mode. But we  are wandering from  the subject. We will

therefore restrict ourselves  to the living  creature, which, in the first place, consists of soul  and body: and of

these two, the one is by nature the ruler, and the  other the subject.  But then we must look for the intentions of

nature in things which  retain their nature, and not in things which  are corrupted. And  therefore we must study

the man who is in the  most perfect state both  of body and soul, for in him we shall see  the true relation of the

two; although in bad or corrupted natures the  body will often appear  to rule over the soul, because they are in

an  evil and unnatural  condition. At all events we may firstly observe  in living creatures  both a despotical and

a constitutional rule; for  the soul rules the  body with a despotical rule, whereas the  intellect rules the appetites

with a constitutional and royal rule.  And it is clear that the rule of  the soul over the body, and of the  mind and

the rational element over  the passionate, is natural and  expedient; whereas the equality of the  two or the rule

of the inferior  is always hurtful. The same holds good  of animals in relation to  men; for tame animals have a

better nature  than wild, and all tame  animals are better off when they are ruled by  man; for then they are

preserved. Again, the male is by nature  superior, and the female  inferior; and the one rules, and the other is


POLITICS

V 6



Top




Page No 11


ruled; this principle,  of necessity, extends to all mankind. 

Where then there is such a difference as that between soul and  body,  or between men and animals (as in the

case of those whose  business  is to use their body, and who can do nothing better), the  lower sort  are by nature

slaves, and it is better for them as for all  inferiors  that they should be under the rule of a master. For he who

can be, and  therefore is, another's and he who participates in  rational  principle enough to apprehend, but not

to have, such a  principle, is a  slave by nature. Whereas the lower animals cannot even  apprehend a  principle;

they obey their instincts. And indeed the use  made of  slaves and of tame animals is not very different; for

both  with  their bodies minister to the needs of life. Nature would like to  distinguish between the bodies of

freemen and slaves, making the one  strong for servile labor, the other upright, and although useless  for  such

services, useful for political life in the arts both of war  and  peace. But the opposite often happens that some

have the souls  and  others have the bodies of freemen. And doubtless if men differed  from  one another in the

mere forms of their bodies as much as the  statues  of the Gods do from men, all would acknowledge that the

inferior class  should be slaves of the superior. And if this is true  of the body, how  much more just that a

similar distinction should  exist in the soul?  but the beauty of the body is seen, whereas the  beauty of the soul

is  not seen. It is clear, then, that some men are  by nature free, and  others slaves, and that for these latter

slavery  is both expedient and  right. 

VI

But that those who take the opposite view have in a certain way  right on their side, may be easily seen. For

the words slavery and  slave are used in two senses. There is a slave or slavery by law as  well as by nature.

The law of which I speak is a sort of convention  the law by which whatever is taken in war is supposed to

belong to the  victors. But this right many jurists impeach, as they would an  orator  who brought forward an

unconstitutional measure: they detest  the  notion that, because one man has the power of doing violence and  is

superior in brute strength, another shall be his slave and subject.  Even among philosophers there is a

difference of opinion. The origin  of the dispute, and what makes the views invade each other's  territory, is as

follows: in some sense virtue, when furnished with  means, has actually the greatest power of exercising

force; and as  superior power is only found where there is superior excellence of  some kind, power seems to

imply virtue, and the dispute to be simply  one about justice (for it is due to one party identifying justice with

goodwill while the other identifies it with the mere rule of the  stronger). If these views are thus set out

separately, the other views  have no force or plausibility against the view that the superior in  virtue ought to

rule, or be master. Others, clinging, as they think,  simply to a principle of justice (for law and custom are a

sort of  justice), assume that slavery in accordance with the custom of war  is  justified by law, but at the same

moment they deny this. For what  if  the cause of the war be unjust? And again, no one would ever say he  is  a

slave who is unworthy to be a slave. Were this the case, men of  the  highest rank would be slaves and the

children of slaves if they or  their parents chance to have been taken captive and sold. Wherefore  Hellenes do

not like to call Hellenes slaves, but confine the term  to  barbarians. Yet, in using this language, they really

mean the  natural  slave of whom we spoke at first; for it must be admitted  that some are  slaves everywhere,

others nowhere. The same principle  applies to  nobility. Hellenes regard themselves as noble everywhere,  and

not only  in their own country, but they deem the barbarians  noble only when at  home, thereby implying that

there are two sorts  of nobility and  freedom, the one absolute, the other relative. The  Helen of Theodectes

says: 

Who would presume to call me servant who am on both sides  sprung  from the stem of the Gods?  What does

this mean but that they  distinguish freedom and slavery,  noble and humble birth, by the two  principles of

good and evil? They  think that as men and animals beget  men and animals, so from good  men a good man

springs. But this is what  nature, though she may intend  it, cannot always accomplish. 

We see then that there is some foundation for this difference of  opinion, and that all are not either slaves by


POLITICS

VI 7



Top




Page No 12


nature or freemen by  nature, and also that there is in some cases a marked distinction  between the two

classes, rendering it expedient and right for the  one  to be slaves and the others to be masters: the one

practicing  obedience, the others exercising the authority and lordship which  nature intended them to have.

The abuse of this authority is injurious  to both; for the interests of part and whole, of body and soul, are  the

same, and the slave is a part of the master, a living but  separated part of his bodily frame. Hence, where the

relation of  master and slave between them is natural they are friends and have a  common interest, but where

it rests merely on law and force the  reverse is true. 

VII

The previous remarks are quite enough to show that the rule of a  master is not a constitutional rule, and that

all the different  kinds  of rule are not, as some affirm, the same with each other. For  there  is one rule exercised

over subjects who are by nature free,  another  over subjects who are by nature slaves. The rule of a  household

is a  monarchy, for every house is under one head: whereas  constitutional  rule is a government of freemen and

equals. The  master is not called a  master because he has science, but because he  is of a certain  character, and

the same remark applies to the slave  and the freeman.  Still there may be a science for the master and  science

for the slave.  The science of the slave would be such as the  man of Syracuse taught,  who made money by

instructing slaves in  their ordinary duties. And  such a knowledge may be carried further, so  as to include

cookery and  similar menial arts. For some duties are  of the more necessary, others  of the more honorable

sort; as the  proverb says, 'slave before slave,  master before master.' But all such  branches of knowledge are

servile.  There is likewise a science of  the master, which teaches the use of  slaves; for the master as such is

concerned, not with the acquisition,  but with the use of them. Yet  this socalled science is not anything  great

or wonderful; for the  master need only know how to order that  which the slave must know  how to execute.

Hence those who are in a  position which places them  above toil have stewards who attend to  their households

while they  occupy themselves with philosophy or with  politics. But the art of  acquiring slaves, I mean of

justly acquiring  them, differs both from  the art of the master and the art of the  slave, being a species of

hunting or war. Enough of the distinction  between master and slave. 

VIII

Let us now inquire into property generally, and into the art of  getting wealth, in accordance with our usual

method, for a slave has  been shown to be a part of property. The first question is whether the  art of getting

wealth is the same with the art of managing a household  or a part of it, or instrumental to it; and if the last,

whether in  the way that the art of making shuttles is instrumental to the art  of  weaving, or in the way that the

casting of bronze is instrumental  to  the art of the statuary, for they are not instrumental in the  same  way, but

the one provides tools and the other material; and by  material I mean the substratum out of which any work is

made; thus  wool is the material of the weaver, bronze of the statuary. Now it  is  easy to see that the art of

household management is not identical  with  the art of getting wealth, for the one uses the material which  the

other provides. For the art which uses household stores can be  no  other than the art of household

management. There is, however, a  doubt  whether the art of getting wealth is a part of household  management

or  a distinct art. If the getter of wealth has to  consider whence wealth  and property can be procured, but there

are  many sorts of property and  riches, then are husbandry, and the care  and provision of food in  general, parts

of the wealthgetting art or  distinct arts? Again,  there are many sorts of food, and therefore  there are many

kinds of  lives both of animals and men; they must all  have food, and the  differences in their food have made

differences  in their ways of life.  For of beasts, some are gregarious, others  are solitary; they live in  the way

which is best adapted to sustain  them, accordingly as they are  carnivorous or herbivorous or  omnivorous: and

their habits are  determined for them by nature in such  a manner that they may obtain  with greater facility the

food of  their choice. But, as different  species have different tastes, the  same things are not naturally  pleasant

to all of them; and therefore  the lives of carnivorous or  herbivorous animals further differ among  themselves.

In the lives of  men too there is a great difference. The  laziest are shepherds, who  lead an idle life, and get


POLITICS

VII 8



Top




Page No 13


their  subsistence without trouble from tame  animals; their flocks having  to wander from place to place in

search  of pasture, they are compelled  to follow them, cultivating a sort of  living farm. Others support

themselves by hunting, which is of  different kinds. Some, for example,  are brigands, others, who dwell  near

lakes or marshes or rivers or a  sea in which there are fish, are  fishermen, and others live by the  pursuit of

birds or wild beasts. The  greater number obtain a living  from the cultivated fruits of the soil.  Such are the

modes of  subsistence which prevail among those whose  industry springs up of  itself, and whose food is not

acquired by  exchange and retail trade  there is the shepherd, the husbandman, the  brigand, the fisherman, the

hunter. Some gain a comfortable  maintenance out of two employments,  eking out the deficiencies of one  of

them by another: thus the life of  a shepherd may be combined with  that of a brigand, the life of a  farmer with

that of a hunter. Other  modes of life are similarly  combined in any way which the needs of men  may require.

Property, in  the sense of a bare livelihood, seems to be  given by nature herself to  all, both when they are first

born, and  when they are grown up. For  some animals bring forth, together with  their offspring, so much  food

as will last until they are able to  supply themselves; of this  the vermiparous or oviparous animals are an

instance; and the  viviparous animals have up to a certain time a  supply of food for  their young in themselves,

which is called milk. In  like manner we may  infer that, after the birth of animals, plants  exist for their sake,

and that the other animals exist for the sake of  man, the tame for use  and food, the wild, if not all at least the

greater part of them,  for food, and for the provision of clothing and  various instruments.  Now if nature makes

nothing incomplete, and  nothing in vain, the  inference must be that she has made all animals  for the sake of

man.  And so, in one point of view, the art of war is a  natural art of  acquisition, for the art of acquisition

includes  hunting, an art which  we ought to practice against wild beasts, and  against men who,  though

intended by nature to be governed, will not  submit; for war  of such a kind is naturally just. 

Of the art of acquisition then there is one kind which by nature  is a part of the management of a household, in

so far as the art of  household management must either find ready to hand, or itself  provide, such things

necessary to life, and useful for the community  of the family or state, as can be stored. They are the elements

of  true riches; for the amount of property which is needed for a good  life is not unlimited, although Solon in

one of his poems says that 

No bound to riches has been fixed for man.  But there is a boundary  fixed, just as there is in the other arts; for

the instruments of any  art are never unlimited, either in number or  size, and riches may be  defined as a

number of instruments to be  used in a household or in a  state. And so we see that there is a  natural art of

acquisition which  is practiced by managers of  households and by statesmen, and what is  the reason of this. 

IX

There is another variety of the art of acquisition which is  commonly  and rightly called an art of

wealthgetting, and has in fact  suggested  the notion that riches and property have no limit. Being  nearly

connected with the preceding, it is often identified with it.  But  though they are not very different, neither are

they the same. The  kind already described is given by nature, the other is gained by  experience and art. 

Let us begin our discussion of the question with the following  considerations: 

Of everything which we possess there are two uses: both belong to  the thing as such, but not in the same

manner, for one is the  proper,  and the other the improper or secondary use of it. For  example, a shoe  is used

for wear, and is used for exchange; both are  uses of the shoe.  He who gives a shoe in exchange for money or

food to  him who wants  one, does indeed use the shoe as a shoe, but this is not  its proper or  primary purpose,

for a shoe is not made to be an  object of barter. The  same may be said of all possessions, for the art  of

exchange extends  to all of them, and it arises at first from what  is natural, from the  circumstance that some

have too little, others  too much. Hence we may  infer that retail trade is not a natural part  of the art of getting

wealth; had it been so, men would have ceased to  exchange when they  had enough. In the first community,


POLITICS

IX 9



Top




Page No 14


indeed, which  is the family, this  art is obviously of no use, but it begins to be  useful when the  society

increases. For the members of the family  originally had all  things in common; later, when the family divided

into parts, the parts  shared in many things, and different parts in  different things, which  they had to give in

exchange for what they  wanted, a kind of barter  which is still practiced among barbarous  nations who

exchange with one  another the necessaries of life and  nothing more; giving and receiving  wine, for example,

in exchange  for coin, and the like. This sort of  barter is not part of the  wealthgetting art and is not contrary

to  nature, but is needed for  the satisfaction of men's natural wants. The  other or more complex  form of

exchange grew, as might have been  inferred, out of the  simpler. When the inhabitants of one country  became

more dependent  on those of another, and they imported what they  needed, and  exported what they had too

much of, money necessarily came  into use.  For the various necessaries of life are not easily carried  about,  and

hence men agreed to employ in their dealings with each  other  something which was intrinsically useful and

easily applicable  to  the purposes of life, for example, iron, silver, and the like. Of  this  the value was at first

measured simply by size and weight, but in  process of time they put a stamp upon it, to save the trouble of

weighing and to mark the value. 

When the use of coin had once been discovered, out of the barter  of necessary articles arose the other art of

wealth getting, namely,  retail trade; which was at first probably a simple matter, but  became  more

complicated as soon as men learned by experience whence  and by  what exchanges the greatest profit might

be made. Originating  in the  use of coin, the art of getting wealth is generally thought  to be  chiefly concerned

with it, and to be the art which produces  riches and  wealth; having to consider how they may be accumulated.

Indeed, riches  is assumed by many to be only a quantity of coin,  because the arts of  getting wealth and retail

trade are concerned with  coin. Others  maintain that coined money is a mere sham, a thing not  natural, but

conventional only, because, if the users substitute  another commodity  for it, it is worthless, and because it is

not  useful as a means to  any of the necessities of life, and, indeed, he  who is rich in coin  may often be in want

of necessary food. But how  can that be wealth of  which a man may have a great abundance and yet  perish

with hunger,  like Midas in the fable, whose insatiable prayer  turned everything  that was set before him into

gold? 

Hence men seek after a better notion of riches and of the art of  getting wealth than the mere acquisition of

coin, and they are  right.  For natural riches and the natural art of wealthgetting are  a  different thing; in their

true form they are part of the  management of  a household; whereas retail trade is the art of  producing wealth,

not  in every way, but by exchange. And it is thought  to be concerned with  coin; for coin is the unit of

exchange and the  measure or limit of it.  And there is no bound to the riches which  spring from this art of

wealth getting. As in the art of medicine  there is no limit to the  pursuit of health, and as in the other arts  there

is no limit to the  pursuit of their several ends, for they aim  at accomplishing their  ends to the uttermost (but of

the means there  is a limit, for the end  is always the limit), so, too, in this art  of wealthgetting there is  no

limit of the end, which is riches of the  spurious kind, and the  acquisition of wealth. But the art of

wealthgetting which consists in  household management, on the other  hand, has a limit; the unlimited

acquisition of wealth is not its  business. And, therefore, in one  point of view, all riches must have a  limit;

nevertheless, as a matter  of fact, we find the opposite to be  the case; for all getters of  wealth increase their

hoard of coin  without limit. The source of the  confusion is the near connection  between the two kinds of

wealthgetting; in either, the instrument  is the same, although the  use is different, and so they pass into  one

another; for each is a use  of the same property, but with a  difference: accumulation is the end  in the one case,

but there is a  further end in the other. Hence some  persons are led to believe that  getting wealth is the object

of  household management, and the whole  idea of their lives is that they  ought either to increase their  money

without limit, or at any rate not  to lose it. The origin of this  disposition in men is that they are  intent upon

living only, and not  upon living well; and, as their  desires are unlimited they also desire  that the means of

gratifying  them should be without limit. Those who  do aim at a good life seek the  means of obtaining bodily

pleasures;  and, since the enjoyment of these  appears to depend on property,  they are absorbed in getting

wealth:  and so there arises the second  species of wealthgetting. For, as  their enjoyment is in excess,  they

seek an art which produces the  excess of enjoyment; and, if  they are not able to supply their  pleasures by the


POLITICS

IX 10



Top




Page No 15


art of getting  wealth, they try other arts, using in  turn every faculty in a manner  contrary to nature. The

quality of  courage, for example, is not  intended to make wealth, but to inspire  confidence; neither is this  the

aim of the general's or of the  physician's art; but the one aims  at victory and the other at health.  Nevertheless,

some men turn  every quality or art into a means of  getting wealth; this they  conceive to be the end, and to the

promotion  of the end they think all  things must contribute. 

Thus, then, we have considered the art of wealthgetting which is  unnecessary, and why men want it; and

also the necessary art of  wealthgetting, which we have seen to be different from the other, and  to be a

natural part of the art of managing a household, concerned  with the provision of food, not, however, like the

former kind,  unlimited, but having a limit. 

X

And we have found the answer to our original question, Whether the  art of getting wealth is the business of

the manager of a household  and of the statesman or not their business? viz., that wealth is  presupposed by

them. For as political science does not make men, but  takes them from nature and uses them, so too nature

provides them with  earth or sea or the like as a source of food. At this stage begins the  duty of the manager of

a household, who has to order the things  which  nature supplies; he may be compared to the weaver who has

not to  make  but to use wool, and to know, too, what sort of wool is good  and  serviceable or bad and

unserviceable. Were this otherwise, it  would be  difficult to see why the art of getting wealth is a part of  the

management of a household and the art of medicine not; for  surely the  members of a household must have

health just as they must  have life or  any other necessary. The answer is that as from one point  of view the

master of the house and the ruler of the state have to  consider about  health, from another point of view not

they but the  physician; so in  one way the art of household management, in another  way the  subordinate art,

has to consider about wealth. But, strictly  speaking,  as I have already said, the means of life must be provided

beforehand  by nature; for the business of nature is to furnish food to  that which  is born, and the food of the

offspring is always what  remains over of  that from which it is produced. Wherefore the art of  getting wealth

out of fruits and animals is always natural. 

There are two sorts of wealthgetting, as I have said; one is a  part  of household management, the other is

retail trade: the former  necessary and honorable, while that which consists in exchange is  justly censured; for

it is unnatural, and a mode by which men gain  from one another. The most hated sort, and with the greatest

reason,  is usury, which makes a gain out of money itself, and not from the  natural object of it. For money was

intended to be used in exchange,  but not to increase at interest. And this term interest, which means  the birth

of money from money, is applied to the breeding of money  because the offspring resembles the parent.

Wherefore of an modes of  getting wealth this is the most unnatural. 

XI

Enough has been said about the theory of wealthgetting; we will  now  proceed to the practical part. The

discussion of such matters is  not  unworthy of philosophy, but to be engaged in them practically is  illiberal

and irksome. The useful parts of wealthgetting are,  first,  the knowledge of livestock which are most

profitable, and  where, and  how as, for example, what sort of horses or sheep or  oxen or any  other animals

are most likely to give a return. A man  ought to know  which of these pay better than others, and which pay

best in  particular places, for some do better in one place and some in  another. Secondly, husbandry, which

may be either tillage or planting,  and the keeping of bees and of fish, or fowl, or of any animals  which  may be

useful to man. These are the divisions of the true or  proper  art of wealthgetting and come first. Of the other,

which  consists in  exchange, the first and most important division is  commerce (of which  there are three

kinds the provision of a ship, the  conveyance of  goods, exposure for sale these again differing as  they are

safer or  more profitable), the second is usury, the third,  service for hire of  this, one kind is employed in the


POLITICS

X 11



Top




Page No 16


mechanical  arts, the other in  unskilled and bodily labor. There is still a  third sort of wealth  getting

intermediate between this and the first  or natural mode which  is partly natural, but is also concerned with

exchange, viz., the  industries that make their profit from the  earth, and from things  growing from the earth

which, although they  bear no fruit, are  nevertheless profitable; for example, the cutting  of timber and all

mining. The art of mining, by which minerals are  obtained, itself has  many branches, for there are various

kinds of  things dug out of the  earth. Of the several divisions of  wealthgetting I now speak  generally; a

minute consideration of them  might be useful in practice,  but it would be tiresome to dwell upon  them at

greater length now. 

Those occupations are most truly arts in which there is the least  element of chance; they are the meanest in

which the body is most  deteriorated, the most servile in which there is the greatest use of  the body, and the

most illiberal in which there is the least need of  excellence. 

Works have been written upon these subjects by various persons;  for example, by Chares the Parian, and

Apollodorus the Lemnian, who  have treated of Tillage and Planting, while others have treated of  other

branches; any one who cares for such matters may refer to  their  writings. It would be well also to collect the

scattered stories  of  the ways in which individuals have succeeded in amassing a fortune;  for all this is useful

to persons who value the art of getting wealth.  There is the anecdote of Thales the Milesian and his financial

device,  which involves a principle of universal application, but is attributed  to him on account of his

reputation for wisdom. He was reproached  for  his poverty, which was supposed to show that philosophy was

of  no use.  According to the story, he knew by his skill in the stars  while it was  yet winter that there would be

a great harvest of  olives in the coming  year; so, having a little money, he gave deposits  for the use of all  the

olivepresses in Chios and Miletus, which he  hired at a low price  because no one bid against him. When the

harvesttime came, and many  were wanted all at once and of a sudden,  he let them out at any rate  which he

pleased, and made a quantity of  money. Thus he showed the  world that philosophers can easily be rich  if they

like, but that  their ambition is of another sort. He is  supposed to have given a  striking proof of his wisdom,

but, as I was  saying, his device for  getting wealth is of universal application, and  is nothing but the  creation

of a monopoly. It is an art often  practiced by cities when  they are want of money; they make a  monopoly of

provisions. 

There was a man of Sicily, who, having money deposited with him,  bought up an the iron from the iron

mines; afterwards, when the  merchants from their various markets came to buy, he was the only  seller, and

without much increasing the price he gained 200 per  cent.  Which when Dionysius heard, he told him that he

might take  away his  money, but that he must not remain at Syracuse, for he  thought that  the man had

discovered a way of making money which was  injurious to  his own interests. He made the same discovery as

Thales; they both  contrived to create a monopoly for themselves. And  statesmen as well  ought to know these

things; for a state is often  as much in want of  money and of such devices for obtaining it as a  household, or

even  more so; hence some public men devote themselves  entirely to finance. 

XII

Of household management we have seen that there are three parts  one  is the rule of a master over slaves,

which has been discussed  already,  another of a father, and the third of a husband. A husband  and father,  we

saw, rules over wife and children, both free, but the  rule differs,  the rule over his children being a royal, over

his wife  a  constitutional rule. For although there may be exceptions to the  order  of nature, the male is by

nature fitter for command than the  female,  just as the elder and fullgrown is superior to the younger  and

more  immature. But in most constitutional states the citizens rule  and  are ruled by turns, for the idea of a

constitutional state implies  that the natures of the citizens are equal, and do not differ at  all.  Nevertheless,

when one rules and the other is ruled we endeavor  to  create a difference of outward forms and names and

titles of  respect,  which may be illustrated by the saying of Amasis about his  footpan.  The relation of the


POLITICS

XII 12



Top




Page No 17


male to the female is of this kind,  but there the  inequality is permanent. The rule of a father over his  children

is  royal, for he rules by virtue both of love and of the  respect due to  age, exercising a kind of royal power.

And therefore  Homer has  appropriately called Zeus 'father of Gods and men,'  because he is the  king of them

all. For a king is the natural superior  of his subjects,  but he should be of the same kin or kind with them,  and

such is the  relation of elder and younger, of father and son. 

XIII

Thus it is clear that household management attends more to men  than to the acquisition of inanimate things,

and to human excellence  more than to the excellence of property which we call wealth, and to  the virtue of

freemen more than to the virtue of slaves. A question  may indeed be raised, whether there is any excellence at

all in a  slave beyond and higher than merely instrumental and ministerial  qualities whether he can have the

virtues of temperance, courage,  justice, and the like; or whether slaves possess only bodily and  ministerial

qualities. And, whichever way we answer the question, a  difficulty arises; for, if they have virtue, in what will

they  differ  from freemen? On the other hand, since they are men and share  in  rational principle, it seems

absurd to say that they have no  virtue. A  similar question may be raised about women and children,  whether

they  too have virtues: ought a woman to be temperate and brave  and just,  and is a child to be called

temperate, and intemperate, or  note So in  general we may ask about the natural ruler, and the natural  subject,

whether they have the same or different virtues. For if a  noble nature  is equally required in both, why should

one of them  always rule, and  the other always be ruled? Nor can we say that this  is a question of  degree, for

the difference between ruler and  subject is a difference  of kind, which the difference of more and less  never

is. Yet how  strange is the supposition that the one ought, and  that the other  ought not, to have virtue! For if

the ruler is  intemperate and unjust,  how can he rule well? If the subject, how  can he obey well? If he be

licentious and cowardly, he will  certainly not do his duty. It is  evident, therefore, that both of them  must have

a share of virtue, but  varying as natural subjects also vary  among themselves. Here the very  constitution of

the soul has shown  us the way; in it one part  naturally rules, and the other is  subject, and the virtue of the

ruler  we in maintain to be different  from that of the subject; the one being  the virtue of the rational,  and the

other of the irrational part. Now,  it is obvious that the same  principle applies generally, and therefore  almost

all things rule  and are ruled according to nature. But the kind  of rule differs; the  freeman rules over the slave

after another manner  from that in which  the male rules over the female, or the man over the  child; although

the parts of the soul are present in an of them, they  are present in  different degrees. For the slave has no

deliberative  faculty at all;  the woman has, but it is without authority, and the  child has, but  it is immature. So

it must necessarily be supposed to  be with the  moral virtues also; all should partake of them, but only  in such

manner and degree as is required by each for the fulfillment  of his  duty. Hence the ruler ought to have moral

virtue in perfection,  for  his function, taken absolutely, demands a master artificer, and  rational principle is

such an artificer; the subjects, oil the other  hand, require only that measure of virtue which is proper to each

of  them. Clearly, then, moral virtue belongs to all of them; but the  temperance of a man and of a woman, or

the courage and justice of a  man and of a woman, are not, as Socrates maintained, the same; the  courage of a

man is shown in commanding, of a woman in obeying. And  this holds of all other virtues, as will be more

clearly seen if we  look at them in detail, for those who say generally that virtue  consists in a good disposition

of the soul, or in doing rightly, or  the like, only deceive themselves. Far better than such definitions is  their

mode of speaking, who, like Gorgias, enumerate the virtues.  All  classes must be deemed to have their special

attributes; as the  poet  says of women, 

Silence is a woman's glory,  but this is not equally the glory of  man. The child is imperfect,  and therefore

obviously his virtue is not  relative to himself alone,  but to the perfect man and to his teacher,  and in like

manner the  virtue of the slave is relative to a master.  Now we determined that  a slave is useful for the wants

of life, and  therefore he will  obviously require only so much virtue as will  prevent him from failing  in his

duty through cowardice or lack of  selfcontrol. Some one will  ask whether, if what we are saying is  true,

virtue will not be  required also in the artisans, for they often  fail in their work  through the lack of self


POLITICS

XIII 13



Top




Page No 18


control? But is there not  a great  difference in the two cases? For the slave shares in his  master's  life; the

artisan is less closely connected with him, and  only attains  excellence in proportion as he becomes a slave.

The  meaner sort of  mechanic has a special and separate slavery; and  whereas the slave  exists by nature, not

so the shoemaker or other  artisan. It is  manifest, then, that the master ought to be the source  of such

excellence in the slave, and not a mere possessor of the art  of  mastership which trains the slave in his duties.

Wherefore they are  mistaken who forbid us to converse with slaves and say that we  should  employ command

only, for slaves stand even more in need of  admonition  than children. 

So much for this subject; the relations of husband and wife,  parent and child, their several virtues, what in

their intercourse  with one another is good, and what is evil, and how we may pursue  the  good and good and

escape the evil, will have to be discussed  when we  speak of the different forms of government. For, inasmuch

as  every  family is a part of a state, and these relationships are the  parts of  a family, and the virtue of the part

must have regard to  the virtue of  the whole, women and children must be trained by  education with an eye  to

the constitution, if the virtues of either of  them are supposed to  make any difference in the virtues of the  state.

And they must make a  difference: for the children grow up to be  citizens, and half the free  persons in a state

are women. 

Of these matters, enough has been said; of what remains, let us  speak at another time. Regarding, then, our

present inquiry as  complete, we will make a new beginning. And, first, let us examine the  various theories of

a perfect state. 

BOOK TWO

I

OUR PURPOSE is to consider what form of political community is  best of all for those who are most able to

realize their ideal of  life. We must therefore examine not only this but other constitutions,  both such as

actually exist in wellgoverned states, and any  theoretical forms which are held in esteem; that what is good

and  useful may be brought to light. And let no one suppose that in seeking  for something beyond them we are

anxious to make a sophistical display  at any cost; we only undertake this inquiry because all the  constitutions

with which we are acquainted are faulty. 

We will begin with the natural beginning of the subject. Three  alternatives are conceivable: The members of

a state must either  have  (1) all things or (2) nothing in common, or (3) some things in  common  and some not.

That they should have nothing in common is  clearly  impossible, for the constitution is a community, and

must at  any rate  have a common place one city will be in one place, and the  citizens  are those who share in

that one city. But should a well  ordered state  have all things, as far as may be, in common, or some  only and

not  others? For the citizens might conceivably have wives and  children and  property in common, as Socrates

proposes in the  Republic of Plato.  Which is better, our present condition, or the  proposed new order of

society. 

II

There are many difficulties in the community of women. And the  principle on which Socrates rests the

necessity of such an institution  evidently is not established by his arguments. Further, as a means  to  the end

which he ascribes to the state, the scheme, taken literally  is  impracticable, and how we are to interpret it is

nowhere  precisely  stated. I am speaking of the premise from which the argument  of  Socrates proceeds, 'that

the greater the unity of the state the  better.' Is it not obvious that a state may at length attain such a  degree of

unity as to be no longer a state? since the nature of a  state is to be a plurality, and in tending to greater unity,

from  being a state, it becomes a family, and from being a family, an  individual; for the family may be said to


POLITICS

BOOK TWO 14



Top




Page No 19


be more than the state,  and  the individual than the family. So that we ought not to attain  this  greatest unity

even if we could, for it would be the  destruction of  the state. Again, a state is not made up only of so  many

men, but of  different kinds of men; for similars do not  constitute a state. It is  not like a military alliance The

usefulness of the latter depends upon  its quantity even where there is  no difference in quality (for mutual

protection is the end aimed  at), just as a greater weight of anything  is more useful than a less  (in like manner,

a state differs from a  nation, when the nation has  not its population organized in villages,  but lives an

Arcadian sort  of life); but the elements out of which a  unity is to be formed differ  in kind. Wherefore the

principle of  compensation, as I have already  remarked in the Ethics, is the  salvation of states. Even among

freemen  and equals this is a principle  which must be maintained, for they  cannot an rule together, but must

change at the end of a year or  some other period of time or in some  order of succession. The result  is that

upon this plan they all  govern; just as if shoemakers and  carpenters were to exchange their  occupations, and

the same persons  did not always continue shoemakers  and carpenters. And since it is  better that this should be

so in  politics as well, it is clear that  while there should be continuance  of the same persons in power where

this is possible, yet where this is  not possible by reason of the  natural equality of the citizens, and at  the same

time it is just that  an should share in the government  (whether to govern be a good thing  or a bad), an

approximation to this  is that equals should in turn  retire from office and should, apart  from official position,

be  treated alike. Thus the one party rule and  the others are ruled in  turn, as if they were no longer the same

persons. In like manner  when they hold office there is a variety in  the offices held. Hence it  is evident that a

city is not by nature one  in that sense which some  persons affirm; and that what is said to be  the greatest good

of  cities is in reality their destruction; but  surely the good of  things must be that which preserves them.

Again, in  another point of  view, this extreme unification of the state is  clearly not good; for a  family is more

selfsufficing than an  individual, and a city than a  family, and a city only comes into being  when the

community is large  enough to be selfsufficing. If then  selfsufficiency is to be  desired, the lesser degree of

unity is more  desirable than the  greater. 

III

But, even supposing that it were best for the community to have  the greatest degree of unity, this unity is by

no means proved to  follow from the fact 'of all men saying "mine" and "not mine" at the  same instant of

time,' which, according to Socrates, is the sign of  perfect unity in a state. For the word 'all' is ambiguous. If

the  meaning be that every individual says 'mine' and 'not mine' at the  same time, then perhaps the result at

which Socrates aims may be in  some degree accomplished; each man will call the same person his own  son

and the same person his wife, and so of his property and of all  that falls to his lot. This, however, is not the

way in which people  would speak who had their had their wives and children in common; they  would say 'all'

but not 'each.' In like manner their property would be  described as belonging to them, not severally but

collectively.  There  is an obvious fallacy in the term 'all': like some other  words,  'both,' 'odd,' 'even,' it is

ambiguous, and even in abstract  argument  becomes a source of logical puzzles. That all persons call  the same

thing mine in the sense in which each does so may be a fine  thing, but  it is impracticable; or if the words are

taken in the other  sense,  such a unity in no way conduces to harmony. And there is  another  objection to the

proposal. For that which is common to the  greatest  number has the least care bestowed upon it. Every one

thinks chiefly  of his own, hardly at all of the common interest; and  only when he is  himself concerned as an

individual. For besides  other considerations,  everybody is more inclined to neglect the duty  which he expects

another to fulfill; as in families many attendants  are often less  useful than a few. Each citizen will have a

thousand  sons who will not  be his sons individually but anybody will be equally  the son of  anybody, and will

therefore be neglected by all alike.  Further, upon  this principle, every one will use the word 'mine' of  one who

is  prospering or the reverse, however small a fraction he  may himself be  of the whole number; the same boy

will be 'so and  so's son,' the son  of each of the thousand, or whatever be the  number of the citizens;  and even

about this he will not be positive;  for it is impossible to  know who chanced to have a child, or  whether, if one

came into  existence, it has survived. But which is  better for each to say  'mine' in this way, making a man the

same  relation to two thousand or  ten thousand citizens, or to use the  word 'mine' in the ordinary and  more


POLITICS

III 15



Top




Page No 20


restricted sense? For usually the  same person is called by one  man his own son whom another calls his  own

brother or cousin or  kinsman blood relation or connection by  marriage either of himself or  of some relation

of his, and yet another  his clansman or tribesman;  and how much better is it to be the real  cousin of

somebody than to be  a son after Plato's fashion! Nor is  there any way of preventing  brothers and children and

fathers and  mothers from sometimes  recognizing one another; for children are  born like their parents, and

they will necessarily be finding  indications of their relationship to  one another. Geographers  declare such to

be the fact; they say that in  part of Upper Libya,  where the women are common, nevertheless the  children

who are born are  assigned to their respective fathers on the  ground of their  likeness. And some women, like

the females of other  animals for  example, mares and cows have a strong tendency to  produce offspring

resembling their parents, as was the case with the  Pharsalian mare  called Honest. 

IV

Other evils, against which it is not easy for the authors of such  a community to guard, will be assaults and

homicides, voluntary as  well as involuntary, quarrels and slanders, all which are most  unholy  acts when

committed against fathers and mothers and near  relations,  but not equally unholy when there is no

relationship.  Moreover, they  are much more likely to occur if the relationship is  unknown, and,  when they

have occurred, the customary expiations of  them cannot be  made. Again, how strange it is that Socrates, after

having made the  children common, should hinder lovers from carnal  intercourse only,  but should permit love

and familiarities between  father and son or  between brother and brother, than which nothing  can be more

unseemly,  since even without them love of this sort is  improper. How strange,  too, to forbid intercourse for

no other  reason than the violence of  the pleasure, as though the relationship  of father and son or of  brothers

with one another made no difference. 

This community of wives and children seems better suited to the  husbandmen than to the guardians, for if

they have wives and  children  in common, they will be bound to one another by weaker  ties, as a  subject class

should be, and they will remain obedient  and not rebel.  In a word, the result of such a law would be just the

opposite of  which good laws ought to have, and the intention of  Socrates in making  these regulations about

women and children would  defeat itself. For  friendship we believe to be the greatest good of  states and the

preservative of them against revolutions; neither is  there anything  which Socrates so greatly lauds as the unity

of the  state which he and  all the world declare to be created by  friendship. But the unity which  he commends

would be like that of  the lovers in the Symposium, who, as  Aristophanes says, desire to grow  together in the

excess of their  affection, and from being two to  become one, in which case one or both  would certainly

perish.  Whereas in a state having women and children  common, love will be  watery; and the father will

certainly not say 'my  son,' or the son 'my  father.' As a little sweet wine mingled with a  great deal of water  is

imperceptible in the mixture, so, in this sort  of community, the  idea of relationship which is based upon these

names  will be lost;  there is no reason why the socalled father should care  about the son,  or the son about the

father, or brothers about one  another. Of the two  qualities which chiefly inspire regard and  affection that a

thing  is your own and that it is your only  oneneither can exist in such a  state as this. 

Again, the transfer of children as soon as they are born from the  rank of husbandmen or of artisans to that of

guardians, and from the  rank of guardians into a lower rank, will be very difficult to  arrange; the givers or

transferrers cannot but know whom they are  giving and transferring, and to whom. And the previously

mentioned  evils, such as assaults, unlawful loves, homicides, will happen more  often amongst those who are

transferred to the lower classes, or who  have a place assigned to them among the guardians; for they will no

longer call the members of the class they have left brothers, and  children, and fathers, and mothers, and will

not, therefore, be afraid  of committing any crimes by reason of consanguinity. Touching the  community of

wives and children, let this be our conclusion. 


POLITICS

IV 16



Top




Page No 21


V

Next let us consider what should be our arrangements about  property:  should the citizens of the perfect state

have their  possessions in  common or not? This question may be discussed  separately from the  enactments

about women and children. Even  supposing that the women and  children belong to individuals, according  to

the custom which is at  present universal, may there not be an  advantage in having and using  possessions in

common? Three cases are  possible: (1) the soil may be  appropriated, but the produce may be  thrown for

consumption into the  common stock; and this is the practice  of some nations. Or (2), the  soil may be

common, and may be cultivated  in common, but the produce  divided among individuals for their private  use;

this is a form of  common property which is said to exist among  certain barbarians. Or  (3), the soil and the

produce may be alike  common. 

When the husbandmen are not the owners, the case will be different  and easier to deal with; but when they till

the ground for  themselves  the question of ownership will give a world of trouble.  If they do not  share equally

enjoyments and toils, those who labor  much and get  little will necessarily complain of those who labor  little

and receive  or consume much. But indeed there is always a  difficulty in men living  together and having all

human relations in  common, but especially in  their having common property. The  partnerships of

fellowtravelers are  an example to the point; for they  generally fall out over everyday  matters and quarrel

about any  trifle which turns up. So with servants:  we are most able to take  offense at those with whom we

most we most  frequently come into  contact in daily life. 

These are only some of the disadvantages which attend the  community of property; the present arrangement,

if improved as it  might be by good customs and laws, would be far better, and would have  the advantages of

both systems. Property should be in a certain  sense  common, but, as a general rule, private; for, when

everyone  has a  distinct interest, men will not complain of one another, and  they will  make more progress,

because every one will be attending to  his own  business. And yet by reason of goodness, and in respect of

use,  'Friends,' as the proverb says, 'will have all things common.'  Even  now there are traces of such a

principle, showing that it is  not  impracticable, but, in wellordered states, exists already to a  certain extent

and may be carried further. For, although every man has  his own property, some things he will place at the

disposal of his  friends, while of others he shares the use with them. The  Lacedaemonians, for example, use

one another's slaves, and horses, and  dogs, as if they were their own; and when they lack provisions on a

journey, they appropriate what they find in the fields throughout  the  country. It is clearly better that property

should be private, but  the  use of it common; and the special business of the legislator is to  create in men this

benevolent disposition. Again, how immeasurably  greater is the pleasure, when a man feels a thing to be his

own; for  surely the love of self is a feeling implanted by nature and not given  in vain, although selfishness is

rightly censured; this, however, is  not the mere love of self, but the love of self in excess, like the  miser's love

of money; for all, or almost all, men love money and  other such objects in a measure. And further, there is the

greatest  pleasure in doing a kindness or service to friends or guests or  companions, which can only be

rendered when a man has private  property. These advantages are lost by excessive unification of the  state.

The exhibition of two virtues, besides, is visibly  annihilated  in such a state: first, temperance towards women

(for it  is an  honorable action to abstain from another's wife for  temperance' sake);  secondly, liberality in the

matter of property.  No one, when men have  all things in common, will any longer set an  example of liberality

or  do any liberal action; for liberality  consists in the use which is  made of property. 

Such legislation may have a specious appearance of benevolence;  men readily listen to it, and are easily

induced to believe that in  some wonderful manner everybody will become everybody's friend,  especially

when some one is heard denouncing the evils now existing in  states, suits about contracts, convictions for

perjury, flatteries  of  rich men and the like, which are said to arise out of the  possession  of private property.

These evils, however, are due to a  very different  cause the wickedness of human nature. Indeed, we see  that

there is  much more quarrelling among those who have all things in  common,  though there are not many of


POLITICS

V 17



Top




Page No 22


them when compared with the  vast numbers  who have private property. 

Again, we ought to reckon, not only the evils from which the  citizens will be saved, but also the advantages

which they will  lose.  The life which they are to lead appears to be quite  impracticable. The  error of Socrates

must be attributed to the false  notion of unity from  which he starts. Unity there should be, both of  the family

and of the  state, but in some respects only. For there is a  point at which a  state may attain such a degree of

unity as to be no  longer a state, or  at which, without actually ceasing to exist, it  will become an  inferior state,

like harmony passing into unison, or  rhythm which has  been reduced to a single foot. The state, as I was

saying, is a  plurality which should be united and made into a  community by  education; and it is strange that

the author of a  system of education  which he thinks will make the state virtuous,  should expect to improve  his

citizens by regulations of this sort, and  not by philosophy or by  customs and laws, like those which prevail  at

Sparta and Crete  respecting common meals, whereby the legislator  has made property  common. Let us

remember that we should not disregard  the experience of  ages; in the multitude of years these things, if  they

were good, would  certainly not have been unknown; for almost  everything has been found  out, although

sometimes they are not put  together; in other cases men  do not use the knowledge which they have.  Great

light would be thrown  on this subject if we could see such a  form of government in the  actual process of

construction; for the  legislator could not form a  state at all without distributing and  dividing its constituents

into  associations for common meals, and into  phratries and tribes. But all  this legislation ends only in

forbidding  agriculture to the guardians,  a prohibition which the Lacedaemonians  try to enforce already. 

But, indeed, Socrates has not said, nor is it easy to decide, what  in such a community will be the general form

of the state. The  citizens who are not guardians are the majority, and about them  nothing has been

determined: are the husbandmen, too, to have their  property in common? Or is each individual to have his

own? And are the  wives and children to be individual or common. If, like the guardians,  they are to have all

things in common, what do they differ from  them,  or what will they gain by submitting to their government?

Or,  upon  what principle would they submit, unless indeed the governing  class  adopt the ingenious policy of

the Cretans, who give their slaves  the  same institutions as their own, but forbid them gymnastic  exercises  and

the possession of arms. If, on the other hand, the  inferior  classes are to be like other cities in respect of

marriage  and  property, what will be the form of the community? Must it not  contain  two states in one, each

hostile to the other He makes the  guardians  into a mere occupying garrison, while the husbandmen and

artisans and  the rest are the real citizens. But if so the suits and  quarrels, and  all the evils which Socrates

affirms to exist in other  states, will  exist equally among them. He says indeed that, having  so good an

education, the citizens will not need many laws, for  example laws  about the city or about the markets; but

then he confines  his  education to the guardians. Again, he makes the husbandmen  owners of  the property

upon condition of their paying a tribute. But  in that  case they are likely to be much more unmanageable and

conceited than  the Helots, or Penestae, or slaves in general. And  whether community  of wives and property

be necessary for the lower  equally with the  higher class or not, and the questions akin to  this, what will be the

education, form of government, laws of the  lower class, Socrates has  nowhere determined: neither is it easy

to  discover this, nor is their  character of small importance if the  common life of the guardians is  to be

maintained. 

Again, if Socrates makes the women common, and retains private  property, the men will see to the fields, but

who will see to the  house? And who will do so if the agricultural class have both their  property and their

wives in common? Once more: it is absurd to  argue,  from the analogy of the animals, that men and women

should  follow the  same pursuits, for animals have not to manage a  household. The  government, too, as

constituted by Socrates, contains  elements of  danger; for he makes the same persons always rule. And  if this

is  often a cause of disturbance among the meaner sort, how  much more  among highspirited warriors? But

that the persons whom he  makes  rulers must be the same is evident; for the gold which the God  mingles  in

the souls of men is not at one time given to one, at  another time  to another, but always to the same: as he

says, 'God  mingles gold in  some, and silver in others, from their very birth; but  brass and iron  in those who

are meant to be artisans and  husbandmen.' Again, he  deprives the guardians even of happiness, and  says that


POLITICS

V 18



Top




Page No 23


the legislator  ought to make the whole state happy. But  the whole cannot be happy  unless most, or all, or

some of its parts  enjoy happiness. In this  respect happiness is not like the even  principle in numbers, which

may  exist only in the whole, but in  neither of the parts; not so  happiness. And if the guardians are not  happy,

who are? Surely not the  artisans, or the common people. The  Republic of which Socrates  discourses has all

these difficulties,  and others quite as great. 

VI

The same, or nearly the same, objections apply to Plato's later  work, the Laws, and therefore we had better

examine briefly the  constitution which is therein described. In the Republic, Socrates has  definitely settled in

all a few questions only; such as the  community  of women and children, the community of property, and the

constitution  of the state. The population is divided into two classes  one of  husbandmen, and the other of

warriors; from this latter is  taken a  third class of counselors and rulers of the state. But  Socrates has  not

determined whether the husbandmen and artisans are to  have a share  in the government, and whether they,

too, are to carry  arms and share  in military service, or not. He certainly thinks that  the women ought  to share

in the education of the guardians, and to  fight by their  side. The remainder of the work is filled up with

digressions foreign  to the main subject, and with discussions about  the education of the  guardians. In the

Laws there is hardly anything  but laws; not much is  said about the constitution. This, which he  had intended

to make more  of the ordinary type, he gradually brings  round to the other or ideal  form. For with the

exception of the  community of women and property,  he supposes everything to be the same  in both states;

there is to be  the same education; the citizens of  both are to live free from servile  occupations, and there are

to be  common meals in both. The only  difference is that in the Laws, the  common meals are extended to

women, and the warriors number 5000,  but in the Republic only 1000. 

The discourses of Socrates are never commonplace; they always  exhibit grace and originality and thought;

but perfection in  everything can hardly be expected. We must not overlook the fact  that  the number of 5000

citizens, just now mentioned, will require a  territory as large as Babylon, or some other huge site, if so many

persons are to be supported in idleness, together with their women and  attendants, who will be a multitude

many times as great. In framing an  ideal we may assume what we wish, but should avoid impossibilities. 

It is said that the legislator ought to have his eye directed to  two  points the people and the country. But

neighboring countries also  must not be forgotten by him, firstly because the state for which he  legislates is to

have a political and not an isolated life. For a  state must have such a military force as will be serviceable

against  her neighbors, and not merely useful at home. Even if the life of  action is not admitted to be the best,

either for individuals or  states, still a city should be formidable to enemies, whether invading  or retreating. 

There is another point: Should not the amount of property be  defined  in some way which differs from this by

being clearer? For  Socrates  says that a man should have so much property as will enable  him to  live

temperately, which is only a way of saying 'to live well';  this  is too general a conception. Further, a man may

live temperately  and  yet miserably. A better definition would be that a man must have  so  much property as

will enable him to live not only temperately but  liberally; if the two are parted, liberally will combine with

luxury;  temperance will be associated with toil. For liberality and  temperance  are the only eligible qualities

which have to do with the  use of  property. A man cannot use property with mildness or courage,  but

temperately and liberally he may; and therefore the practice of  these  virtues is inseparable from property.

There is an inconsistency,  too,  in too, in equalizing the property and not regulating the  number of  the citizens;

the population is to remain unlimited, and  he thinks  that it will be sufficiently equalized by a certain number

of  marriages being unfruitful, however many are born to others,  because  he finds this to be the case in

existing states. But greater  care will  be required than now; for among ourselves, whatever may be  the number

of citizens, the property is always distributed among them,  and  therefore no one is in want; but, if the

property were incapable  of  division as in the Laws, the supernumeraries, whether few or  many,  would get


POLITICS

VI 19



Top




Page No 24


nothing. One would have thought that it was even  more  necessary to limit population than property; and that

the limit  should  be fixed by calculating the chances of mortality in the  children, and  of sterility in married

persons. The neglect of this  subject, which in  existing states is so common, is a neverfailing  cause of

poverty  among the citizens; and poverty is the parent of  revolution and crime.  Pheidon the Corinthian, who

was one of the  most ardent legislators,  thought that the families and the number of  citizens ought to remain

the same, although originally all the lots  may have been of different  sizes: but in the Laws the opposite

principle is maintained. What in  our opinion is the right  arrangement will have to be explained  hereafter. 

There is another omission in the Laws: Socrates does not tell us  how  the rulers differ from their subjects; he

only says that they  should  be related as the warp and the woof, which are made out of  different  wools. He

allows that a man's whole property may be  increased  fivefold, but why should not his land also increase to a

certain  extent? Again, will the good management of a household be  promoted  by his arrangement of

homesteads? For he assigns to each  individual  two homesteads in separate places, and it is difficult to  live in

two houses. 

The whole system of government tends to be neither democracy nor  oligarchy, but something in a mean

between them, which is usually  called a polity, and is composed of the heavyarmed soldiers. Now,  if  he

intended to frame a constitution which would suit the greatest  number of states, he was very likely right, but

not if he meant to say  that this constitutional form came nearest to his first or ideal  state; for many would

prefer the Lacedaemonian, or, possibly, some  other more aristocratic government. Some, indeed, say that the

best  constitution is a combination of all existing forms, and they praise  the Lacedaemonian because it is made

up of oligarchy, monarchy, and  democracy, the king forming the monarchy, and the council of elders  the

oligarchy while the democratic element is represented by the  Ephors; for the Ephors are selected from the

people. Others,  however,  declare the Ephoralty to be a tyranny, and find the element  of  democracy in the

common meals and in the habits of daily life. In  the  Laws it is maintained that the best constitution is made

up of  democracy and tyranny, which are either not constitutions at all, or  are the worst of all. But they are

nearer the truth who combine many  forms; for the constitution is better which is made up of more  numerous

elements. The constitution proposed in the Laws has no  element of monarchy at all; it is nothing but

oligarchy and democracy,  leaning rather to oligarchy. This is seen in the mode of appointing  magistrates; for

although the appointment of them by lot from among  those who have been already selected combines both

elements, the way  in which the rich are compelled by law to attend the assembly and vote  for magistrates or

discharge other political duties, while the rest  may do as they like, and the endeavor to have the greater

number of  the magistrates appointed out of the richer classes and the highest  officers selected from those who

have the greatest incomes, both these  are oligarchical features. The oligarchical principle prevails also in  the

choice of the council, for all are compelled to choose, but the  compulsion extends only to the choice out of

the first class, and of  an equal number out of the second class and out of the third class,  but not in this latter

case to all the voters but to those of the  first three classes; and the selection of candidates out of the fourth

class is only compulsory on the first and second. Then, from the  persons so chosen, he says that there ought

to be an equal number of  each class selected. Thus a preponderance will be given to the  better  sort of people,

who have the larger incomes, because many of  the lower  classes, not being compelled will not vote. These

considerations, and  others which will be adduced when the time comes  for examining similar  polities, tend to

show that states like  Plato's should not be composed  of democracy and monarchy. There is  also a danger in

electing the  magistrates out of a body who are  themselves elected; for, if but a  small number choose to

combine,  the elections will always go as they  desire. Such is the  constitution which is described in the Laws. 

VII

Other constitutions have been proposed; some by private persons,  others by philosophers and statesmen,

which all come nearer to  established or existing ones than either of Plato's. No one else has  introduced such

novelties as the community of women and children, or  public tables for women: other legislators begin with


POLITICS

VII 20



Top




Page No 25


what is  necessary. In the opinion of some, the regulation of property is the  chief point of all, that being the

question upon which all revolutions  turn. This danger was recognized by Phaleas of Chalcedon, who was  the

first to affirm that the citizens of a state ought to have equal  possessions. He thought that in a new colony the

equalization might be  accomplished without difficulty, not so easily when a state was  already established;

and that then the shortest way of compassing  the  desired end would be for the rich to give and not to receive

marriage  portions, and for the poor not to give but to receive them. 

Plato in the Laws was of opinion that, to a certain extent,  accumulation should be allowed, forbidding, as I

have already  observed, any citizen to possess more than five times the minimum  qualification But those who

make such laws should remember what they  are apt to forget that the legislator who fixes the amount of

property should also fix the number of children; for, if the  children  are too many for the property, the law

must be broken. And,  besides  the violation of the law, it is a bad thing that many from  being rich  should

become poor; for men of ruined fortunes are sure  to stir up  revolutions. That the equalization of property

exercises an  influence  on political society was clearly understood even by some  of the old  legislators. Laws

were made by Solon and others prohibiting  an  individual from possessing as much land as he pleased; and

there  are  other laws in states which forbid the sale of property: among  the  Locrians, for example, there is a

law that a man is not to sell  his  property unless he can prove unmistakably that some misfortune has  befallen

him. Again, there have been laws which enjoin the  preservation of the original lots. Such a law existed in the

island of  Leucas, and the abrogation of it made the constitution too democratic,  for the rulers no longer had

the prescribed qualification. Again,  where there is equality of property, the amount may be either too  large or

too small, and the possessor may be living either in luxury  or penury. Clearly, then, the legislator ought not

only to aim at  the  equalization of properties, but at moderation in their amount.  Further, if he prescribe this

moderate amount equally to all, he  will  be no nearer the mark; for it is not the possessions but the  desires  of

mankind which require to be equalized, and this is  impossible,  unless a sufficient education is provided by

the laws. But  Phaleas  will probably reply that this is precisely what he means;  and that, in  his opinion, there

ought to be in states, not only  equal property, but  equal education. Still he should tell precisely  what he

means; and  that, in his opinion, there ought to be in be in  having one and the  same for all, if it is of a sort that

predisposes  men to avarice, or  ambition, or both. Moreover, civil troubles  arise, not only out of the  inequality

of property, but out of the  inequality of honor, though in  opposite ways. For the common people  quarrel

about the inequality of  property, the higher class about the  equality of honor; as the poet  says, 

The bad and good alike in honor share. 

There are crimes of which the motive is want; and for these  Phaleas expects to find a cure in the equalization

of property,  which  will take away from a man the temptation to be a highwayman,  because  he is hungry or

cold. But want is not the sole incentive to  crime; men  also wish to enjoy themselves and not to be in a state of

desire they  wish to cure some desire, going beyond the necessities of  life, which  preys upon them; nay, this

is not the only reason they  may desire  superfluities in order to enjoy pleasures unaccompanied  with pain,

and  therefore they commit crimes. 

Now what is the cure of these three disorders? Of the first,  moderate possessions and occupation; of the

second, habits of  temperance; as to the third, if any desire pleasures which depend on  themselves, they will

find the satisfaction of their desires nowhere  but in philosophy; for all other pleasures we are dependent on

others.  The fact is that the greatest crimes are caused by excess and not by  necessity. Men do not become

tyrants in order that they may not suffer  cold; and hence great is the honor bestowed, not on him who kills a

thief, but on him who kills a tyrant. Thus we see that the  institutions of Phaleas avail only against petty

crimes. 

There is another objection to them. They are chiefly designed to  promote the internal welfare of the state. But

the legislator should  consider also its relation to neighboring nations, and to all who  are  outside of it. The

government must be organized with a view to  military strength; and of this he has said not a word. And so


POLITICS

VII 21



Top




Page No 26


with  respect to property: there should not only be enough to supply the  internal wants of the state, but also to

meet dangers coming from  without. The property of the state should not be so large that more  powerful

neighbors may be tempted by it, while the owners are unable  to repel the invaders; nor yet so small that the

state is unable to  maintain a war even against states of equal power, and of the same  character. Phaleas has

not laid down any rule; but we should bear in  mind that abundance of wealth is an advantage. The best limit

will  probably be, that a more powerful neighbor must have no inducement  to  go to war with you by reason of

the excess of your wealth, but only  such as he would have had if you had possessed less. There is a  story  that

Eubulus, when Autophradates was going to besiege  Atarneus, told  him to consider how long the operation

would take,  and then reckon up  the cost which would be incurred in the time.  'For,' said he, 'I am  willing for a

smaller sum than that to leave  Atarneus at once.' These  words of Eubulus made an impression on

Autophradates, and he desisted  from the siege. 

The equalization of property is one of the things that tend to  prevent the citizens from quarrelling. Not that

the gain in this  direction is very great. For the nobles will be dissatisfied because  they think themselves

worthy of more than an equal share of honors;  and this is often found to be a cause of sedition and revolution.

And  the avarice of mankind is insatiable; at one time two obols was  pay  enough; but now, when this sum has

become customary, men always  want  more and more without end; for it is of the nature of desire  not to be

satisfied, and most men live only for the gratification of  it. The  beginning of reform is not so much to

equalize property as  to train  the nobler sort of natures not to desire more, and to prevent  the  lower from

getting more; that is to say, they must be kept down,  but  not illtreated. Besides, the equalization proposed by

Phaleas  is  imperfect; for he only equalizes land, whereas a man may be rich  also  in slaves, and cattle, and

money, and in the abundance of what  are  called his movables. Now either all these things must be  equalized,

or  some limit must be imposed on them, or they must an be  let alone. It  would appear that Phaleas is

legislating for a small  city only, if, as  he supposes, all the artisans are to be public  slaves and not to form  a

supplementary part of the body of citizens.  But if there is a law  that artisans are to be public slaves, it should

only apply to those  engaged on public works, as at Epidamnus, or at  Athens on the plan  which Diophantus

once introduced. 

From these observations any one may judge how far Phaleas was  wrong or right in his ideas. 

VIII

Hippodamus, the son of Euryphon, a native of Miletus, the same who  invented the art of planning cities, and

who also laid out the  Piraeus a strange man, whose fondness for distinction led him into  a  general

eccentricity of life, which made some think him affected  (for  he would wear flowing hair and expensive

ornaments; but these  were  worn on a cheap but warm garment both in winter and summer);  he,  besides

aspiring to be an adept in the knowledge of nature, was  the  first person not a statesman who made inquiries

about the best  form of  government. 

The city of Hippodamus was composed of 10,000 citizens divided  into three parts one of artisans, one of

husbandmen, and a third of  armed defenders of the state. He also divided the land into three  parts, one sacred,

one public, the third private: the first was set  apart to maintain the customary worship of the Gods, the second

was to  support the warriors, the third was the property of the husbandmen. He  also divided laws into three

classes, and no more, for he maintained  that there are three subjects of lawsuits insult, injury, and  homicide.

He likewise instituted a single final court of appeal, to  which all causes seeming to have been improperly

decided might be  referred; this court he formed of elders chosen for the purpose. He  was further of opinion

that the decisions of the courts ought not to  be given by the use of a voting pebble, but that every one should

have  a tablet on which he might not only write a simple condemnation, or  leave the tablet blank for a simple

acquittal; but, if he partly  acquitted and partly condemned, he was to distinguish accordingly.  To  the existing

law he objected that it obliged the judges to be  guilty  of perjury, whichever way they voted. He also enacted


POLITICS

VIII 22



Top




Page No 27


that  those who  discovered anything for the good of the state should be  honored; and  he provided that the

children of citizens who died in  battle should be  maintained at the public expense, as if such an  enactment

had never  been heard of before, yet it actually exists at  Athens and in other  places. As to the magistrates, he

would have  them all elected by the  people, that is, by the three classes  already mentioned, and those who

were elected were to watch over the  interests of the public, of  strangers, and of orphans. These are the  most

striking points in the  constitution of Hippodamus. There is not  much else. 

The first of these proposals to which objection may be taken is  the threefold division of the citizens. The

artisans, and the  husbandmen, and the warriors, all have a share in the government.  But  the husbandmen have

no arms, and the artisans neither arms nor  land,  and therefore they become all but slaves of the warrior class.

That  they should share in all the offices is an impossibility; for  generals  and guardians of the citizens, and

nearly all the principal  magistrates, must be taken from the class of those who carry arms.  Yet, if the two

other classes have no share in the government, how can  they be loyal citizens? It may be said that those who

have arms must  necessarily be masters of both the other classes, but this is not so  easily accomplished unless

they are numerous; and if they are, why  should the other classes share in the government at all, or have power

to appoint magistrates? Further, what use are farmers to the city?  Artisans there must be, for these are wanted

in every city, and they  can live by their craft, as elsewhere; and the husbandmen too, if they  really provided

the warriors with food, might fairly have a share in  the government. But in the republic of Hippodamus they

are supposed to  have land of their own, which they cultivate for their private  benefit. Again, as to this

common land out of which the soldiers are  maintained, if they are themselves to be the cultivators of it, the

warrior class will be identical with the husbandmen, although the  legislator intended to make a distinction

between them. If, again,  there are to be other cultivators distinct both from the husbandmen,  who have land of

their own, and from the warriors, they will make a  fourth class, which has no place in the state and no share

in  anything. Or, if the same persons are to cultivate their own lands,  and those of the public as well, they will

have difficulty in  supplying the quantity of produce which will maintain two  households:  and why, in this

case, should there be any division, for  they might  find food themselves and give to the warriors from the

same  land and  the same lots? There is surely a great confusion in all this. 

Neither is the law to commended which says that the judges, when a  simple issue is laid before them, should

distinguish in their  judgement; for the judge is thus converted into an arbitrator. Now, in  an arbitration,

although the arbitrators are many, they confer with  one another about the decision, and therefore they can

distinguish;  but in courts of law this is impossible, and, indeed, most legislators  take pains to prevent the

judges from holding any communication with  one another. Again, will there not be confusion if the judge

thinks  that damages should be given, but not so much as the suitor demands?  He asks, say, for twenty minae,

and the judge allows him ten minae (or  in general the suitor asks for more and the judge allows less),  while

another judge allows five, another four minae. In this way  they will  go on splitting up the damages, and some

will grant the  whole and  others nothing: how is the final reckoning to be taken?  Again, no one  contends that

he who votes for a simple acquittal or  condemnation  perjures himself, if the indictment has been laid in an

unqualified  form; and this is just, for the judge who acquits does not  decide that  the defendant owes nothing,

but that he does not owe the  twenty minae.  He only is guilty of perjury who thinks that the  defendant ought

not  to pay twenty minae, and yet condemns him. 

To honor those who discover anything which is useful to the state  is  a proposal which has a specious sound,

but cannot safely be enacted  by  law, for it may encourage informers, and perhaps even lead to  political

commotions. This question involves another. It has been  doubted whether it is or is not expedient to make

any changes in the  laws of a country, even if another law be better. Now, if an changes  are inexpedient, we

can hardly assent to the proposal of Hippodamus;  for, under pretense of doing a public service, a man may

introduce  measures which are really destructive to the laws or to the  constitution. But, since we have touched

upon this subject, perhaps we  had better go a little into detail, for, as I was saying, there is a  difference of

opinion, and it may sometimes seem desirable to make  changes. Such changes in the other arts and sciences

have certainly  been beneficial; medicine, for example, and gymnastic, and every other  art and craft have


POLITICS

VIII 23



Top




Page No 28


departed from traditional usage. And, if politics  be an art, change must be necessary in this as in any other art.

That  improvement has occurred is shown by the fact that old customs  are  exceedingly simple and barbarous.

For the ancient Hellenes went  about  armed and bought their brides of each other. The remains of  ancient  laws

which have come down to us are quite absurd; for example,  at  Cumae there is a law about murder, to the

effect that if the  accuser  produce a certain number of witnesses from among his own  kinsmen, the  accused

shall be held guilty. Again, men in general  desire the good,  and not merely what their fathers had. But the

primeval inhabitants,  whether they were born of the earth or were  the survivors of some  destruction, may be

supposed to have been no  better than ordinary or  even foolish people among ourselves (such is  certainly the

tradition  concerning the earthborn men); and it would  be ridiculous to rest  contented with their notions.

Even when laws  have been written down,  they ought not always to remain unaltered.  As in other sciences, so

in  politics, it is impossible that all things  should be precisely set  down in writing; for enactments must be

universal, but actions are  concerned with particulars. Hence we  infer that sometimes and in  certain cases laws

may be changed; but  when we look at the matter from  another point of view, great caution  would seem to be

required. For  the habit of lightly changing the  laws is an evil, and, when the  advantage is small, some errors

both of  lawgivers and rulers had  better be left; the citizen will not gain  so much by making the change  as he

will lose by the habit of  disobedience. The analogy of the arts  is false; a change in a law is a  very different

thing from a change in  an art. For the law has no power  to command obedience except that of  habit, which

can only be given  by time, so that a readiness to change  from old to new laws  enfeebles the power of the law.

Even if we admit  that the laws are  to be changed, are they all to be changed, and in  every state? And are  they

to be changed by anybody who likes, or only  by certain persons?  These are very important questions; and

therefore  we had better  reserve the discussion of them to a more suitable  occasion. 

IX

In the governments of Lacedaemon and Crete, and indeed in all  governments, two points have to be

considered: first, whether any  particular law is good or bad, when compared with the perfect state;  secondly,

whether it is or is not consistent with the idea and  character which the lawgiver has set before his citizens.

That in a  wellordered state the citizens should have leisure and not have to  provide for their daily wants is

generally acknowledged, but there  is  a difficulty in seeing how this leisure is to be attained. The  Thessalian

Penestae have often risen against their masters, and the  Helots in like manner against the Lacedaemonians,

for whose  misfortunes they are always lying in wait. Nothing, however, of this  kind has as yet happened to

the Cretans; the reason probably is that  the neighboring cities, even when at war with one another, never  form

an alliance with rebellious serfs, rebellions not being for their  interest, since they themselves have a

dependent population. Whereas  all the neighbors of the Lacedaemonians, whether Argives,  Messenians,  or

Arcadians, were their enemies. In Thessaly, again,  the original  revolt of the slaves occurred because the

Thessalians  were still at  war with the neighboring Achaeans, Perrhaebians, and  Magnesians.  Besides, if there

were no other difficulty, the  treatment or  management of slaves is a troublesome affair; for, if not  kept in

hand, they are insolent, and think that they are as good as  their  masters, and, if harshly treated, they hate and

conspire against  them.  Now it is clear that when these are the results the citizens  of a  state have not found out

the secret of managing their subject  population. 

Again, the license of the Lacedaemonian women defeats the  intention of the Spartan constitution, and is

adverse to the happiness  of the state. For, a husband and wife being each a part of every  family, the state may

be considered as about equally divided into  men  and women; and, therefore, in those states in which the

condition of  the women is bad, half the city may be regarded as having  no laws. And  this is what has actually

happened at Sparta; the  legislator wanted to  make the whole state hardy and temperate, and  he has carried out

his  intention in the case of the men, but he has  neglected the women, who  live in every sort of intemperance

and  luxury. The consequence is that  in such a state wealth is too highly  valued, especially if the citizen  fall

under the dominion of their  wives, after the manner of most  warlike races, except the Celts and  a few others

who openly approve of  male loves. The old mythologer  would seem to have been right in  uniting Ares and


POLITICS

IX 24



Top




Page No 29


Aphrodite, for all  warlike races are prone to the  love either of men or of women. This  was exemplified among

the  Spartans in the days of their greatness;  many things were managed by  their women. But what difference

does it  make whether women rule, or  the rulers are ruled by women? The  result is the same. Even in regard  to

courage, which is of no use in  daily life, and is needed only in  war, the influence of the  Lacedaemonian

women has been most  mischievous. The evil showed  itself in the Theban invasion, when,  unlike the women

other cities,  they were utterly useless and caused  more confusion than the enemy.  This license of the

Lacedaemonian women  existed from the earliest  times, and was only what might be expected.  For, during the

wars of  the Lacedaemonians, first against the Argives,  and afterwards  against the Arcadians and Messenians,

the men were long  away from  home, and, on the return of peace, they gave themselves into  the  legislator's

hand, already prepared by the discipline of a  soldier's  life (in which there are many elements of virtue), to

receive his  enactments. But, when Lycurgus, as tradition says, wanted  to bring the  women under his laws,

they resisted, and he gave up the  attempt. These  then are the causes of what then happened, and this  defect in

the  constitution is clearly to be attributed to them. We are  not, however,  considering what is or is not to be

excused, but what is  right or  wrong, and the disorder of the women, as I have already said,  not only  gives an

air of indecorum to the constitution considered in  itself,  but tends in a measure to foster avarice. 

The mention of avarice naturally suggests a criticism on the  inequality of property. While some of the

Spartan citizen have quite  small properties, others have very large ones; hence the land has  passed into the

hands of a few. And this is due also to faulty laws;  for, although the legislator rightly holds up to shame the

sale or  purchase of an inheritance, he allows anybody who likes to give or  bequeath it. Yet both practices lead

to the same result. And nearly  twofifths of the whole country are held by women; this is owing to  the

number of heiresses and to the large dowries which are  customary.  It would surely have been better to have

given no dowries  at all, or,  if any, but small or moderate ones. As the law now stands,  a man may  bestow his

heiress on any one whom he pleases, and, if he  die  intestate, the privilege of giving her away descends to his

heir.  Hence, although the country is able to maintain 1500 cavalry and  30,000 hoplites, the whole number of

Spartan citizens fell below 1000.  The result proves the faulty nature of their laws respecting property;  for the

city sank under a single defeat; the want of men was their  ruin. There is a tradition that, in the days of their

ancient kings,  they were in the habit of giving the rights of citizenship to  strangers, and therefore, in spite of

their long wars, no lack of  population was experienced by them; indeed, at one time Sparta is said  to have

numbered not less than 10,000 citizens Whether this  statement  is true or not, it would certainly have been

better to  have maintained  their numbers by the equalization of property.  Again, the law which  relates to the

procreation of children is adverse  to the correction of  this inequality. For the legislator, wanting to  have as

many Spartans  as he could, encouraged the citizens to have  large families; and there  is a law at Sparta that the

father of  three sons shall be exempt from  military service, and he who has  four from all the burdens of the

state. Yet it is obvious that, if  there were many children, the land  being distributed as it is, many of  them must

necessarily fall into  poverty. 

The Lacedaemonian constitution is defective in another point; I  mean  the Ephoralty. This magistracy has

authority in the highest  matters,  but the Ephors are chosen from the whole people, and so the  office  is apt to

fall into the hands of very poor men, who, being  badly  off, are open to bribes. There have been many

examples at Sparta  of  this evil in former times; and quite recently, in the matter of the  Andrians, certain of the

Ephors who were bribed did their best to ruin  the state. And so great and tyrannical is their power, that even

the  kings have been compelled to court them, so that, in this way as  well  together with the royal office, the

whole constitution has  deteriorated, and from being an aristocracy has turned into a  democracy. The

Ephoralty certainly does keep the state together; for  the people are contented when they have a share in the

highest office,  and the result, whether due to the legislator or to chance, has been  advantageous. For if a

constitution is to be permanent, all the  parts  of the state must wish that it should exist and the same

arrangements  be maintained. This is the case at Sparta, where the  kings desire its  permanence because they

have due honor in their own  persons; the  nobles because they are represented in the council of  elders (for the

office of elder is a reward of virtue); and the  people, because all  are eligible to the Ephoralty. The election of

Ephors out of the whole  people is perfectly right, but ought not to be  carried on in the  present fashion, which


POLITICS

IX 25



Top




Page No 30


is too childish. Again,  they have the decision  of great causes, although they are quite  ordinary men, and

therefore  they should not determine them merely on  their own judgment, but  according to written rules, and

to the laws.  Their way of life, too,  is not in accordance with the spirit of the  constitution they have a  deal too

much license; whereas, in the  case of the other citizens, the  excess of strictness is so intolerable  that they run

away from the law  into the secret indulgence of  sensual pleasures. 

Again, the council of elders is not free from defects. It may be  said that the elders are good men and well

trained in manly virtue;  and that, therefore, there is an advantage to the state in having  them. But that judges

of important causes should hold office for  life  is a disputable thing, for the mind grows old as well as the

body. And  when men have been educated in such a manner that even the  legislator  himself cannot trust them,

there is real danger. Many of  the elders  are well known to have taken bribes and to have been guilty  of

partiality in public affairs. And therefore they ought not to be  irresponsible; yet at Sparta they are so. But (it

may be replied),  'All magistracies are accountable to the Ephors.' Yes, but this  prerogative is too great for

them, and we maintain that the control  should be exercised in some other manner. Further, the mode in which

the Spartans elect their elders is childish; and it is improper that  the person to be elected should canvass for

the office; the  worthiest  should be appointed, whether he chooses or not. And here the  legislator clearly

indicates the same intention which appears in other  parts of his constitution; he would have his citizens

ambitious, and  he has reckoned upon this quality in the election of the elders; for  no one would ask to be

elected if he were not. Yet ambition and  avarice, almost more than any other passions, are the motives of

crime. 

Whether kings are or are not an advantage to states, I will  consider  at another time; they should at any rate be

chosen, not as  they are  now, but with regard to their personal life and conduct. The  legislator himself

obviously did not suppose that he could make them  really good men; at least he shows a great distrust of their

virtue.  For this reason the Spartans used to join enemies with them in the  same embassy, and the quarrels

between the kings were held to be  conservative of the state. 

Neither did the first introducer of the common meals, called  'phiditia,' regulate them well. The entertainment

ought to have been  provided at the public cost, as in Crete; but among the Lacedaemonians  every one is

expected to contribute, and some of them are too poor  to  afford the expense; thus the intention of the

legislator is  frustrated. The common meals were meant to be a popular institution,  but the existing manner of

regulating them is the reverse of  popular.  For the very poor can scarcely take part in them; and,  according to

ancient custom, those who cannot contribute are not  allowed to retain  their rights of citizenship. 

The law about the Spartan admirals has often been censured, and  with  justice; it is a source of dissension, for

the kings are  perpetual  generals, and this office of admiral is but the setting up  of  another king. 

The charge which Plato brings, in the Laws, against the intention  of  the legislator, is likewise justified; the

whole constitution has  regard to one part of virtue only the virtue of the soldier, which  gives victory in war.

So long as they were at war, therefore, their  power was preserved, but when they had attained empire they

fell for  of the arts of peace they knew nothing, and had never engaged in any  employment higher than war.

There is another error, equally great,  into which they have fallen. Although they truly think that the  goods  for

which men contend are to be acquired by virtue rather than  by  vice, they err in supposing that these goods are

to be preferred to  the virtue which gains them. 

Once more: the revenues of the state are illmanaged; there is no  money in the treasury, although they are

obliged to carry on great  wars, and they are unwilling to pay taxes. The greater part of the  land being in the

hands of the Spartans, they do not look closely into  one another's contributions. The result which the

legislator has  produced is the reverse of beneficial; for he has made his city  poor,  and his citizens greedy. 

Enough respecting the Spartan constitution, of which these are the  principal defects. 


POLITICS

IX 26



Top




Page No 31


X

The Cretan constitution nearly resembles the Spartan, and in some  few points is quite as good; but for the

most part less perfect in  form. The older constitutions are generally less elaborate than the  later, and the

Lacedaemonian is said to be, and probably is, in a very  great measure, a copy of the Cretan. According to

tradition, Lycurgus,  when he ceased to be the guardian of King Charillus, went abroad and  spent most of his

time in Crete. For the two countries are nearly  connected; the Lyctians are a colony of the Lacedaemonians,

and the  colonists, when they came to Crete, adopted the constitution which  they found existing among the

inhabitants. Even to this day the  Perioeci, or subject population of Crete, are governed by the original  laws

which Minos is supposed to have enacted. The island seems to be  intended by nature for dominion in Hellas,

and to be well situated; it  extends right across the sea, around which nearly all the Hellenes are  settled; and

while one end is not far from the Peloponnese, the  other  almost reaches to the region of Asia about Triopium

and  Rhodes. Hence  Minos acquired the empire of the sea, subduing some of  the islands and  colonizing

others; at last he invaded Sicily, where he  died near  Camicus. 

The Cretan institutions resemble the Lacedaemonian. The Helots are  the husbandmen of the one, the Perioeci

of the other, and both Cretans  and Lacedaemonians have common meals, which were anciently called by  the

Lacedaemonians not 'phiditia' but 'andria'; and the Cretans have  the same word, the use of which proves that

the common meals  originally came from Crete. Further, the two constitutions are  similar; for the office of the

Ephors is the same as that of the  Cretan Cosmi, the only difference being that whereas the Ephors are  five,

the Cosmi are ten in number. The elders, too, answer to the  elders in Crete, who are termed by the Cretans the

council. And the  kingly office once existed in Crete, but was abolished, and the  Cosmi  have now the duty of

leading them in war. All classes share in  the  ecclesia, but it can only ratify the decrees of the elders and the

Cosmi. 

The common meals of Crete are certainly better managed than the  Lacedaemonian; for in Lacedaemon every

one pays so much per head,  or,  if he fails, the law, as I have already explained, forbids him  to  exercise the

rights of citizenship. But in Crete they are of a more  popular character. There, of all the fruits of the earth and

cattle  raised on the public lands, and of the tribute which is paid by the  Perioeci, one portion is assigned to

the Gods and to the service of  the state, and another to the common meals, so that men, women, and  children

are all supported out of a common stock. The legislator has  many ingenious ways of securing moderation in

eating, which he  conceives to be a gain; he likewise encourages the separation of men  from women, lest they

should have too many children, and the  companionship of men with one another whether this is a good or

bad  thing I shall have an opportunity of considering at another time.  But  that the Cretan common meals are

better ordered than the  Lacedaemonian  there can be no doubt. 

On the other hand, the Cosmi are even a worse institution than the  Ephors, of which they have all the evils

without the good. Like the  Ephors, they are any chance persons, but in Crete this is not  counterbalanced by a

corresponding political advantage. At Sparta  every one is eligible, and the body of the people, having a share

in  the highest office, want the constitution to be permanent. But in  Crete the Cosmi are elected out of certain

families, and not out of  the whole people, and the elders out of those who have been Cosmi. 

The same criticism may be made about the Cretan, which has been  already made about the Lacedaemonian

elders. Their irresponsibility  and life tenure is too great a privilege, and their arbitrary power of  acting upon

their own judgment, and dispensing with written law, is  dangerous. It is no proof of the goodness of the

institution that  the  people are not discontented at being excluded from it. For there  is no  profit to be made out

of the office as out of the Ephoralty,  since,  unlike the Ephors, the Cosmi, being in an island, are removed

from  temptation. 

The remedy by which they correct the evil of this institution is  an extraordinary one, suited rather to a close


POLITICS

X 27



Top




Page No 32


oligarchy than to a  constitutional state. For the Cosmi are often expelled by a conspiracy  of their own

colleagues, or of private individuals; and they are  allowed also to resign before their term of office has

expired. Surely  all matters of this kind are better regulated by law than by the  will  of man, which is a very

unsafe rule. Worst of all is the  suspension of  the office of Cosmi, a device to which the nobles  often have

recourse  when they will not submit to justice. This shows  that the Cretan  government, although possessing

some of the  characteristics of a  constitutional state, is really a close  oligarchy. 

The nobles have a habit, too, of setting up a chief; they get  together a party among the common people and

their own friends and  then quarrel and fight with one another. What is this but the  temporary destruction of

the state and dissolution of society? A  city  is in a dangerous condition when those who are willing are also

able  to attack her. But, as I have already said, the island of Crete  is  saved by her situation; distance has the

same effect as the  Lacedaemonian prohibition of strangers; and the Cretans have no  foreign dominions. This

is the reason why the Perioeci are contented  in Crete, whereas the Helots are perpetually revolting. But when

lately foreign invaders found their way into the island, the  weakness  of the Cretan constitution was revealed.

Enough of the  government of  Crete. 

XI

The Carthaginians are also considered to have an excellent form of  government, which differs from that of

any other state in several  respects, though it is in some very like the Lacedaemonian. Indeed,  all three states

the Lacedaemonian, the Cretan, and the Carthaginian  nearly resemble one another, and are very different

from any others.  Many of the Carthaginian institutions are excellent The superiority of  their constitution is

proved by the fact that the common people remain  loyal to the constitution the Carthaginians have never had

any  rebellion worth speaking of, and have never been under the rule of a  tyrant. 

Among the points in which the Carthaginian constitution resembles  the Lacedaemonian are the following:

The common tables of the clubs  answer to the Spartan phiditia, and their magistracy of the 104 to the  Ephors;

but, whereas the Ephors are any chance persons, the  magistrates of the Carthaginians are elected according to

merit  this  is an improvement. They have also their kings and their  gerusia, or  council of elders, who

correspond to the kings and  elders of Sparta.  Their kings, unlike the Spartan, are not always of  the same

family,  nor that an ordinary one, but if there is some  distinguished family  they are selected out of it and not

appointed  by senority this is far  better. Such officers have great power, and  therefore, if they are  persons of

little worth, do a great deal of  harm, and they have  already done harm at Lacedaemon. 

Most of the defects or deviations from the perfect state, for  which the Carthaginian constitution would be

censured, apply equally  to all the forms of government which we have mentioned. But of the  deflections from

aristocracy and constitutional government, some  incline more to democracy and some to oligarchy. The kings

and elders,  if unanimous, may determine whether they will or will not bring a  matter before the people, but

when they are not unanimous, the  people  decide on such matters as well. And whatever the kings and  elders

bring before the people is not only heard but also determined  by them,  and any one who likes may oppose it;

now this is not  permitted in  Sparta and Crete. That the magistrates of five who have  under them  many

important matters should be coopted, that they should  choose the  supreme council of 100, and should hold

office longer  than other  magistrates (for they are virtually rulers both before  and after they  hold office) these

are oligarchical features; their  being without  salary and not elected by lot, and any similar points,  such as the

practice of having all suits tried by the magistrates, and  not some by  one class of judges or jurors and some

by another, as at  Lacedaemon,  are characteristic of aristocracy. The Carthaginian  constitution  deviates from

aristocracy and inclines to oligarchy,  chiefly on a  point where popular opinion is on their side. For men  in

general think  that magistrates should be chosen not only for  their merit, but for  their wealth: a man, they say,

who is poor cannot  rule well he has  not the leisure. If, then, election of magistrates  for their wealth be

characteristic of oligarchy, and election for  merit of aristocracy,  there will be a third form under which the


POLITICS

XI 28



Top




Page No 33


constitution of Carthage is  comprehended; for the Carthaginians choose  their magistrates, and  particularly the

highest of them their kings  and generals with an  eye both to merit and to wealth. 

But we must acknowledge that, in thus deviating from aristocracy,  the legislator has committed an error.

Nothing is more absolutely  necessary than to provide that the highest class, not only when in  office, but when

out of office, should have leisure and not disgrace  themselves in any way; and to this his attention should be

first  directed. Even if you must have regard to wealth, in order to secure  leisure, yet it is surely a bad thing

that the greatest offices,  such  as those of kings and generals, should be bought. The law which  allows  this

abuse makes wealth of more account than virtue, and the  whole  state becomes avaricious. For, whenever the

chiefs of the  state deem  anything honorable, the other citizens are sure to follow  their  example; and, where

virtue has not the first place, their  aristocracy  cannot be firmly established. Those who have been at the

expense of  purchasing their places will be in the habit of repaying  themselves;  and it is absurd to suppose that

a poor and honest man  will be wanting  to make gains, and that a lower stamp of man who has  incurred a great

expense will not. Wherefore they should rule who  are able to rule  best. And even if the legislator does not

care to  protect the good  from poverty, he should at any rate secure leisure  for them when in  office. 

It would seem also to be a bad principle that the same person  should  hold many offices, which is a favorite

practice among the  Carthaginians, for one business is better done by one man. The  legislator should see to

this and should not appoint the same person  to be a fluteplayer and a shoemaker. Hence, where the state is

large,  it is more in accordance both with constitutional and with democratic  principles that the offices of state

should be distributed among many  persons. For, as I said, this arrangement is fairer to all, and any  action

familiarized by repetition is better and sooner performed.  We  have a proof in military and naval matters; the

duties of command  and  of obedience in both these services extend to all. 

The government of the Carthaginians is oligarchical, but they  successfully escape the evils of oligarchy by

enriching one portion of  the people after another by sending them to their colonies. This is  their panacea and

the means by which they give stability to the state.  Accident favors them, but the legislator should be able to

provide  against revolution without trusting to accidents. As things are, if  any misfortune occurred, and the

bulk of the subjects revolted,  there  would be no way of restoring peace by legal methods. 

Such is the character of the Lacedaemonian, Cretan, and  Carthaginian  constitutions, which are justly

celebrated. 

XII

Of those who have treated of governments, some have never taken  any part at all in public affairs, but have

passed their lives in a  private station; about most of them, what was worth telling has been  already told.

Others have been lawgivers, either in their own or in  foreign cities, whose affairs they have administered; and

of these  some have only made laws, others have framed constitutions; for  example, Lycurgus and Solon did

both. Of the Lacedaemonian  constitution I have already spoken. As to Solon, he is thought by some  to have

been a good legislator, who put an end to the exclusiveness of  the oligarchy, emancipated the people,

established the ancient  Athenian democracy, and harmonized the different elements of the  state. According to

their view, the council of Areopagus was an  oligarchical element, the elected magistracy, aristocratical, and

the  courts of law, democratical. The truth seems to be that the  council  and the elected magistracy existed

before the time of Solon,  and were  retained by him, but that he formed the courts of law out  of an the  citizens,

thus creating the democracy, which is the very  reason why he  is sometimes blamed. For in giving the

supreme power  to the law  courts, which are elected by lot, he is thought to have  destroyed the

nondemocratic element. When the law courts grew  powerful, to please  the people who were now playing

the tyrant the old  constitution was  changed into the existing democracy. Ephialtes and  Pericles curtailed  the

power of the Areopagus; Pericles also  instituted the payment of  the juries, and thus every demagogue in turn


POLITICS

XII 29



Top




Page No 34


increased the power of  the democracy until it became what we now  see. All this is true; it  seems, however, to

be the result of  circumstances, and not to have  been intended by Solon. For the people,  having been

instrumental in  gaining the empire of the sea in the  Persian War, began to get a  notion of itself, and followed

worthless  demagogues, whom the better  class opposed. Solon, himself, appears  to have given the Athenians

only that power of electing to offices and  calling to account the  magistrates which was absolutely necessary;

for  without it they would  have been in a state of slavery and enmity to  the government. All the  magistrates he

appointed from the notables and  the men of wealth, that  is to say, from the pentacosiomedimni, or  from the

class called  zeugitae, or from a third class of socalled  knights or cavalry. The  fourth class were laborers who

had no share in  any magistracy. 

Mere legislators were Zaleucus, who gave laws to the Epizephyrian  Locrians, and Charondas, who legislated

for his own city of Catana,  and for the other Chalcidian cities in Italy and Sicily. Some people  attempt to

make out that Onomacritus was the first person who had  any  special skill in legislation, and that he, although

a Locrian by  birth, was trained in Crete, where he lived in the exercise of his  prophetic art; that Thales was

his companion, and that Lycurgus and  Zaleucus were disciples of Thales, as Charondas was of Zaleucus. But

their account is quite inconsistent with chronology. 

There was also Philolaus, the Corinthian, who gave laws to the  Thebans. This Philolaus was one of the family

of the Bacchiadae, and a  lover of Diocles, the Olympic victor, who left Corinth in horror of  the incestuous

passion which his mother Halcyone had conceived for  him, and retired to Thebes, where the two friends

together ended their  days. The inhabitants still point out their tombs, which are in full  view of one another,

but one is visible from the Corinthian territory,  the other not. Tradition says the two friends arranged them

thus,  Diocles out of horror at his misfortunes, so that the land of  Corinth  might not be visible from his tomb;

Philolaus that it might.  This is  the reason why they settled at Thebes, and so Philolaus  legislated for  the

Thebans, and, besides some other enactments, gave  them laws about  the procreation of children, which they

call the 'Laws  of Adoption.'  These laws were peculiar to him, and were intended to  preserve the  number of

the lots. 

In the legislation of Charondas there is nothing remarkable,  except the suits against false witnesses. He is the

first who  instituted denunciation for perjury. His laws are more exact and  more  precisely expressed than even

those of our modern legislators. 

(Characteristic of Phaleas is the equalization of property; of  Plato, the community of women, children, and

property, the common  meals of women, and the law about drinking, that the sober shall be  masters of the

feast; also the training of soldiers to acquire by  practice equal skill with both hands, so that one should be as

useful  as the other.) 

Draco has left laws, but he adapted them to a constitution which  already existed, and there is no peculiarity in

them which is worth  mentioning, except the greatness and severity of the punishments. 

Pittacus, too, was only a lawgiver, and not the author of a  constitution; he has a law which is peculiar to him,

that, if a  drunken man do something wrong, he shall be more heavily punished than  if he were sober; he

looked not to the excuse which might be offered  for the drunkard, but only to expediency, for drunken more

often  than  sober people commit acts of violence. 

Androdamas of Rhegium gave laws to the Chalcidians of Thrace. Some  of them relate to homicide, and to

heiresses; but there is nothing  remarkable in them. 

And here let us conclude our inquiry into the various  constitutions which either actually exist, or have been

devised by  theorists. 


POLITICS

XII 30



Top




Page No 35


BOOK THREE

I

HE who would inquire into the essence and attributes of various  kinds of governments must first of all

determine 'What is a state?' At  present this is a disputed question. Some say that the state has  done  a certain

act; others, no, not the state, but the oligarchy or  the  tyrant. And the legislator or statesman is concerned

entirely with  the  state; a constitution or government being an arrangement of the  inhabitants of a state. But a

state is composite, like any other whole  made up of many parts; these are the citizens, who compose it. It is

evident, therefore, that we must begin by asking, Who is the  citizen,  and what is the meaning of the term? For

here again there may  be a  difference of opinion. He who is a citizen in a democracy will  often  not be a citizen

in an oligarchy. Leaving out of consideration  those  who have been made citizens, or who have obtained the

name of  citizen  any other accidental manner, we may say, first, that a citizen  is not  a citizen because he lives

in a certain place, for resident  aliens and  slaves share in the place; nor is he a citizen who has no  legal right

except that of suing and being sued; for this right may be  enjoyed  under the provisions of a treaty. Nay,

resident aliens in many  places  do not possess even such rights completely, for they are  obliged to  have a

patron, so that they do but imperfectly  participate in  citizenship, and we call them citizens only in a  qualified

sense, as  we might apply the term to children who are too  young to be on the  register, or to old men who have

been relieved from  state duties. Of  these we do not say quite simply that they are  citizens, but add in  the one

case that they are not of age, and in the  other, that they are  past the age, or something of that sort; the  precise

expression is  immaterial, for our meaning is clear. Similar  difficulties to those  which I have mentioned may

be raised and  answered about deprived  citizens and about exiles. But the citizen  whom we are seeking to

define is a citizen in the strictest sense,  against whom no such  exception can be taken, and his special

characteristic is that he  shares in the administration of justice, and  in offices. Now of  offices some are

discontinuous, and the same  persons are not allowed  to hold them twice, or can only hold them  after a fixed

interval;  others have no limit of time for example, the  office of a dicast or  ecclesiast. It may, indeed, be

argued that these  are not magistrates  at all, and that their functions give them no  share in the government.  But

surely it is ridiculous to say that those  who have the power do  not govern. Let us not dwell further upon  this,

which is a purely  verbal question; what we want is a common term  including both dicast  and ecclesiast. Let

us, for the sake of  distinction, call it  'indefinite office,' and we will assume that  those who share in such  office

are citizens. This is the most  comprehensive definition of a  citizen, and best suits all those who  are generally

so called. 

But we must not forget that things of which the underlying  principles differ in kind, one of them being first,

another second,  another third, have, when regarded in this relation, nothing, or  hardly anything, worth

mentioning in common. Now we see that  governments differ in kind, and that some of them are prior and that

others are posterior; those which are faulty or perverted are  necessarily posterior to those which are perfect.

(What we mean by  perversion will be hereafter explained.) The citizen then of necessity  differs under each

form of government; and our definition is best  adapted to the citizen of a democracy; but not necessarily to

other  states. For in some states the people are not acknowledged, nor have  they any regular assembly, but

only extraordinary ones; and suits  are  distributed by sections among the magistrates. At Lacedaemon,  for

instance, the Ephors determine suits about contracts, which they  distribute among themselves, while the

elders are judges of  homicide,  and other causes are decided by other magistrates. A similar  principle  prevails

at Carthage; there certain magistrates decide all  causes. We  may, indeed, modify our definition of the citizen

so as  to include  these states. In them it is the holder of a definite, not  of an  indefinite office, who legislates

and judges, and to some or all  such  holders of definite offices is reserved the right of deliberating  or  judging

about some things or about all things. The conception of  the  citizen now begins to clear up. 

He who has the power to take part in the deliberative or judicial  administration of any state is said by us to be

a citizens of that  state; and, speaking generally, a state is a body of citizens  sufficing for the purposes of life. 


POLITICS

BOOK THREE 31



Top




Page No 36


II

But in practice a citizen is defined to be one of whom both the  parents are citizens; others insist on going

further back; say to  two  or three or more ancestors. This is a short and practical  definition  but there are some

who raise the further question: How this  third or  fourth ancestor came to be a citizen? Gorgias of Leontini,

partly  because he was in a difficulty, partly in irony, said 'Mortars  are  what is made by the mortarmakers,

and the citizens of Larissa are  those who are made by the magistrates; for it is their trade to make

Larissaeans.' Yet the question is really simple, for, if according  to  the definition just given they shared in the

government, they  were  citizens. This is a better definition than the other. For the  words,  'born of a father or

mother who is a citizen,' cannot  possibly apply  to the first inhabitants or founders of a state. 

There is a greater difficulty in the case of those who have been  made citizens after a revolution, as by

Cleisthenes at Athens after  the expulsion of the tyrants, for he enrolled in tribes many metics,  both strangers

and slaves. The doubt in these cases is, not who is,  but whether he who is ought to be a citizen; and there will

still be a  furthering the state, whether a certain act is or is not an act of the  state; for what ought not to be is

what is false. Now, there are  some  who hold office, and yet ought not to hold office, whom we  describe as

ruling, but ruling unjustly. And the citizen was defined  by the fact  of his holding some kind of rule or office

he who holds a  judicial or  legislative office fulfills our definition of a citizen.  It is  evident, therefore, that the

citizens about whom the doubt has  arisen  must be called citizens. 

III

Whether they ought to be so or not is a question which is bound up  with the previous inquiry. For a parallel

question is raised  respecting the state, whether a certain act is or is not an act of the  state; for example, in the

transition from an oligarchy or a tyranny  to a democracy. In such cases persons refuse to fulfill their  contracts

or any other obligations, on the ground that the tyrant, and  not the state, contracted them; they argue that

some constitutions are  established by force, and not for the sake of the common good. But  this would apply

equally to democracies, for they too may be founded  on violence, and then the acts of the democracy will be

neither more  nor less acts of the state in question than those of an oligarchy or  of a tyranny. This question

runs up into another: on what principle  shall we ever say that the state is the same, or different? It would  be a

very superficial view which considered only the place and the  inhabitants (for the soil and the population may

be separated, and  some of the inhabitants may live in one place and some in another).  This, however, is not a

very serious difficulty; we need only remark  that the word 'state' is ambiguous. 

It is further asked: When are men, living in the same place, to be  regarded as a single city what is the limit?

Certainly not the wall  of the city, for you might surround all Peloponnesus with a wall. Like  this, we may say,

is Babylon, and every city that has the compass of a  nation rather than a city; Babylon, they say, had been

taken for three  days before some part of the inhabitants became aware of the fact.  This difficulty may,

however, with advantage be deferred to another  occasion; the statesman has to consider the size of the state,

and  whether it should consist of more than one nation or not. 

Again, shall we say that while the race of inhabitants, as well as  their place of abode, remain the same, the

city is also the same,  although the citizens are always dying and being born, as we call  rivers and fountains

the same, although the water is always flowing  away and coming again Or shall we say that the generations

of men,  like the rivers, are the same, but that the state changes? For,  since  the state is a partnership, and is a

partnership of citizens  in a  constitution, when the form of government changes, and becomes  different, then it

may be supposed that the state is no longer the  same, just as a tragic differs from a comic chorus, although the

members of both may be identical. And in this manner we speak of every  union or composition of elements

as different when the form of their  composition alters; for example, a scale containing the same sounds is  said

to be different, accordingly as the Dorian or the Phrygian mode  is employed. And if this is true it is evident


POLITICS

II 32



Top




Page No 37


that the sameness of  the state consists chiefly in the sameness of the constitution, and it  may be called or not

called by the same name, whether the  inhabitants  are the same or entirely different. It is quite another

question,  whether a state ought or ought not to fulfill engagements  when the  form of government changes. 

IV

There is a point nearly allied to the preceding: Whether the  virtue of a good man and a good citizen is the

same or not. But,  before entering on this discussion, we must certainly first obtain  some general notion of the

virtue of the citizen. Like the sailor, the  citizen is a member of a community. Now, sailors have different

functions, for one of them is a rower, another a pilot, and a third  a  lookout man, a fourth is described by

some similar term; and  while  the precise definition of each individual's virtue applies  exclusively  to him,

there is, at the same time, a common definition  applicable to  them all. For they have all of them a common

object,  which is safety  in navigation. Similarly, one citizen differs from  another, but the  salvation of the

community is the common business  of them all. This  community is the constitution; the virtue of the  citizen

must  therefore be relative to the constitution of which he  is a member. If,  then, there are many forms of

government, it is  evident that there is  not one single virtue of the good citizen  which is perfect virtue. But  we

say that the good man is he who has  one single virtue which is  perfect virtue. Hence it is evident that  the good

citizen need not of  necessity possess the virtue which  makes a good man. 

The same question may also be approached by another road, from a  consideration of the best constitution. If

the state cannot be  entirely composed of good men, and yet each citizen is expected to  do  his own business

well, and must therefore have virtue, still  inasmuch  as all the citizens cannot be alike, the virtue of the  citizen

and of  the good man cannot coincide. All must have the  virtue of the good  citizen thus, and thus only, can

the state be  perfect; but they will  not have the virtue of a good man, unless we  assume that in the good  state

all the citizens must be good. 

Again, the state, as composed of unlikes, may be compared to the  living being: as the first elements into

which a living being is  resolved are soul and body, as soul is made up of rational principle  and appetite, the

family of husband and wife, property of master and  slave, so of all these, as well as other dissimilar elements,

the  state is composed; and, therefore, the virtue of all the citizens  cannot possibly be the same, any more than

the excellence of the  leader of a chorus is the same as that of the performer who stands  by  his side. I have

said enough to show why the two kinds of virtue  cannot be absolutely and always the same. 

But will there then be no case in which the virtue of the good  citizen and the virtue of the good man coincide?

To this we answer  that the good ruler is a good and wise man, and that he who would be a  statesman must be

a wise man. And some persons say that even the  education of the ruler should be of a special kind; for are not

the  children of kings instructed in riding and military exercises? As  Euripides says: 

No subtle arts for me, but what the state requires.  As though  there were a special education needed by a ruler.

If then  the virtue  of a good ruler is the same as that of a good man, and we  assume  further that the subject is a

citizen as well as the ruler, the  virtue  of the good citizen and the virtue of the good man cannot be  absolutely

the same, although in some cases they may; for the virtue  of a ruler differs from that of a citizen. It was the

sense of this  difference which made Jason say that 'he felt hungry when he was not a  tyrant,' meaning that he

could not endure to live in a private  station. But, on the other hand, it may be argued that men are praised  for

knowing both how to rule and how to obey, and he is said to be a  citizen of approved virtue who is able to do

both. Now if we suppose  the virtue of a good man to be that which rules, and the virtue of the  citizen to

include ruling and obeying, it cannot be said that they are  equally worthy of praise. Since, then, it is

sometimes thought that  the ruler and the ruled must learn different things and not the  same,  but that the

citizen must know and share in them both, the  inference  is obvious. There is, indeed, the rule of a master,

which is  concerned  with menial offices the master need not know how to perform  these,  but may employ


POLITICS

IV 33



Top




Page No 38


others in the execution of them: the other would  be  degrading; and by the other I mean the power actually to

do  menial  duties, which vary much in character and are executed by  various  classes of slaves, such, for

example, as handicraftsmen,  who, as their  name signifies, live by the labor of their hands:  under these the

mechanic is included. Hence in ancient times, and  among some nations,  the working classes had no share in

the  government a privilege which  they only acquired under the extreme  democracy. Certainly the good man

and the statesman and the good  citizen ought not to learn the crafts  of inferiors except for their  own

occasional use; if they habitually  practice them, there will cease  to be a distinction between master and  slave. 

This is not the rule of which we are speaking; but there is a rule  of another kind, which is exercised over

freemen and equals by birth  a constitutional rule, which the ruler must learn by obeying, as he  would learn

the duties of a general of cavalry by being under the  orders of a general of cavalry, or the duties of a general

of infantry  by being under the orders of a general of infantry, and by having  had  the command of a regiment

and of a company. It has been well  said that  'he who has never learned to obey cannot be a good  commander.'

The two  are not the same, but the good citizen ought to be  capable of both; he  should know how to govern

like a freeman, and  how to obey like a  freeman these are the virtues of a citizen. And,  although the

temperance and justice of a ruler are distinct from those  of a  subject, the virtue of a good man will include

both; for the  virtue of  the good man who is free and also a subject, e.g., his  justice, will  not be one but will

comprise distinct kinds, the one  qualifying him to  rule, the other to obey, and differing as the  temperance and

courage  of men and women differ. For a man would be  thought a coward if he had  no more courage than a

courageous woman,  and a woman would be thought  loquacious if she imposed no more  restraint on her

conversation than  the good man; and indeed their part  in the management of the household  is different, for

the duty of the  one is to acquire, and of the other  to preserve. Practical wisdom only  is characteristic of the

ruler: it  would seem that all other virtues  must equally belong to ruler and  subject. The virtue of the subject is

certainly not wisdom, but only  true opinion; he may be compared to the  maker of the flute, while his  master

is like the fluteplayer or  user of the flute. 

From these considerations may be gathered the answer to the  question, whether the virtue of the good man is

the same as that of  the good citizen, or different, and how far the same, and how far  different. 

V

There still remains one more question about the citizen: Is he  only a true citizen who has a share of office, or

is the mechanic to  be included? If they who hold no office are to be deemed citizens, not  every citizen can

have this virtue of ruling and obeying; for this man  is a citizen And if none of the lower class are citizens, in

which  part of the state are they to be placed? For they are not resident  aliens, and they are not foreigners. May

we not reply, that as far  as  this objection goes there is no more absurdity in excluding them  than  in excluding

slaves and freedmen from any of the  abovementioned  classes? It must be admitted that we cannot consider

all those to be  citizens who are necessary to the existence of the  state; for example,  children are not citizen

equally with grownup  men, who are citizens  absolutely, but children, not being grown up,  are only citizens

on a  certain assumption. Nay, in ancient times,  and among some nations the  artisan class were slaves or

foreigners,  and therefore the majority of  them are so now. The best form of  state will not admit them to

citizenship; but if they are admitted,  then our definition of the  virtue of a citizen will not apply to every

citizen nor to every free  man as such, but only to those who are freed  from necessary services.  The necessary

people are either slaves who  minister to the wants of  individuals, or mechanics and laborers who  are the

servants of the  community. These reflections carried a  little further will explain  their position; and indeed

what has been  said already is of itself,  when understood, explanation enough. 

Since there are many forms of government there must be many  varieties of citizen and especially of citizens

who are subjects; so  that under some governments the mechanic and the laborer will be  citizens, but not in

others, as, for example, in aristocracy or the  socalled government of the best (if there be such an one), in


POLITICS

V 34



Top




Page No 39


which  honors are given according to virtue and merit; for no man can  practice virtue who is living the life of

a mechanic or laborer. In  oligarchies the qualification for office is high, and therefore no  laborer can ever be a

citizen; but a mechanic may, for an actual  majority of them are rich. At Thebes there was a law that no man

could  hold office who had not retired from business for ten years. But in  many states the law goes to the

length of admitting aliens; for in  some democracies a man is a citizen though his mother only be a  citizen;

and a similar principle is applied to illegitimate  children;  the law is relaxed when there is a dearth of

population. But  when the  number of citizens increases, first the children of a male or  a female  slave are

excluded; then those whose mothers only are  citizens; and at  last the right of citizenship is confined to those

whose fathers and  mothers are both citizens. 

Hence, as is evident, there are different kinds of citizens; and  he is a citizen in the highest sense who shares in

the honors of the  state. Compare Homer's words, 'like some dishonored stranger'; he  who  is excluded from

the honors of the state is no better than an  alien.  But when his exclusion is concealed, then the object is that

the  privileged class may deceive their fellow inhabitants. 

As to the question whether the virtue of the good man is the same  as  that of the good citizen, the

considerations already adduced prove  that  in some states the good man and the good citizen are the same,  and

in  others different. When they are the same it is not every  citizen who  is a good man, but only the statesman

and those who have  or may have,  alone or in conjunction with others, the conduct of  public affairs. 

VI

Having determined these questions, we have next to consider  whether there is only one form of government

or many, and if many,  what they are, and how many, and what are the differences between  them. 

A constitution is the arrangement of magistracies in a state,  especially of the highest of all. The government is

everywhere  sovereign in the state, and the constitution is in fact the  government. For example, in democracies

the people are supreme, but in  oligarchies, the few; and, therefore, we say that these two forms of  government

also are different: and so in other cases. 

First, let us consider what is the purpose of a state, and how  many forms of government there are by which

human society is  regulated. We have already said, in the first part of this treatise,  when discussing household

management and the rule of a master, that  man is by nature a political animal. And therefore, men, even when

they do not require one another's help, desire to live together; not  but that they are also brought together by

their common interests in  proportion as they severally attain to any measure of wellbeing. This  is certainly

the chief end, both of individuals and of states. And  also for the sake of mere life (in which there is possibly

some  noble  element so long as the evils of existence do not greatly  overbalance  the good) mankind meet

together and maintain the political  community.  And we all see that men cling to life even at the cost of

enduring  great misfortune, seeming to find in life a natural sweetness  and  happiness. 

There is no difficulty in distinguishing the various kinds of  authority; they have been often defined already in

discussions outside  the school. The rule of a master, although the slave by nature and the  master by nature

have in reality the same interests, is nevertheless  exercised primarily with a view to the interest of the master,

but  accidentally considers the slave, since, if the slave perish, the rule  of the master perishes with him. On the

other hand, the government  of  a wife and children and of a household, which we have called  household

management, is exercised in the first instance for the  good of the  governed or for the common good of both

parties, but  essentially for  the good of the governed, as we see to be the case  in medicine,  gymnastic, and the

arts in general, which are only  accidentally  concerned with the good of the artists themselves. For  there is no

reason why the trainer may not sometimes practice  gymnastics, and the  helmsman is always one of the crew.

The trainer or  the helmsman  considers the good of those committed to his care. But,  when he is one  of the


POLITICS

VI 35



Top




Page No 40


persons taken care of, he accidentally  participates in the  advantage, for the helmsman is also a sailor,  and the

trainer becomes  one of those in training. And so in  politics: when the state is framed  upon the principle of

equality  and likeness, the citizens think that  they ought to hold office by  turns. Formerly, as is natural, every

one  would take his turn of  service; and then again, somebody else would  look after his  interest, just as he,

while in office, had looked after  theirs. But  nowadays, for the sake of the advantage which is to be  gained

from the  public revenues and from office, men want to be always  in office.  One might imagine that the rulers,

being sickly, were only  kept in  health while they continued in office; in that case we may be  sure  that they

would be hunting after places. The conclusion is  evident:  that governments which have a regard to the

common interest  are  constituted in accordance with strict principles of justice, and  are  therefore true forms;

but those which regard only the interest of  the rulers are all defective and perverted forms, for they are

despotic, whereas a state is a community of freemen. 

VII

Having determined these points, we have next to consider how many  forms of government there are, and

what they are; and in the first  place what are the true forms, for when they are determined the  perversions of

them will at once be apparent. The words constitution  and government have the same meaning, and the

government, which is the  supreme authority in states, must be in the hands of one, or of a few,  or of the

many. The true forms of government, therefore, are those  in  which the one, or the few, or the many, govern

with a view to the  common interest; but governments which rule with a view to the private  interest, whether

of the one or of the few, or of the many, are  perversions. For the members of a state, if they are truly citizens,

ought to participate in its advantages. Of forms of government in  which one rules, we call that which regards

the common interests,  kingship or royalty; that in which more than one, but not many,  rule,  aristocracy; and it

is so called, either because the rulers  are the  best men, or because they have at heart the best interests  of the

state and of the citizens. But when the citizens at large  administer  the state for the common interest, the

government is called  by the  generic name a constitution. And there is a reason for this  use of  language. One

man or a few may excel in virtue; but as the  number  increases it becomes more difficult for them to attain

perfection in  every kind of virtue, though they may in military  virtue, for this is  found in the masses. Hence

in a constitutional  government the  fightingmen have the supreme power, and those who  possess arms are

the citizens. 

Of the abovementioned forms, the perversions are as follows: of  royalty, tyranny; of aristocracy, oligarchy;

of constitutional  government, democracy. For tyranny is a kind of monarchy which has  in  view the interest of

the monarch only; oligarchy has in view the  interest of the wealthy; democracy, of the needy: none of them

the  common good of all. 

VIII

But there are difficulties about these forms of government, and it  will therefore be necessary to state a little

more at length the  nature of each of them. For he who would make a philosophical study of  the various

sciences, and does not regard practice only, ought not  to  overlook or omit anything, but to set forth the truth

in every  particular. Tyranny, as I was saying, is monarchy exercising the  rule  of a master over the political

society; oligarchy is when men  of  property have the government in their hands; democracy, the  opposite,

when the indigent, and not the men of property, are the  rulers. And  here arises the first of our difficulties, and

it  relates to the  distinction drawn. For democracy is said to be the  government of the  many. But what if the

many are men of property and  have the power in  their hands? In like manner oligarchy is said to  be the

government of  the few; but what if the poor are fewer than  the rich, and have the  power in their hands

because they are stronger?  In these cases the  distinction which we have drawn between these  different forms

of  government would no longer hold good. 


POLITICS

VII 36



Top




Page No 41


Suppose, once more, that we add wealth to the few and poverty to  the  many, and name the governments

accordingly an oligarchy is said  to be  that in which the few and the wealthy, and a democracy that in  which

the many and the poor are the rulers there will still be a  difficulty. For, if the only forms of government are

the ones  already  mentioned, how shall we describe those other governments  also just  mentioned by us, in

which the rich are the more numerous and  the poor  are the fewer, and both govern in their respective states? 

The argument seems to show that, whether in oligarchies or in  democracies, the number of the governing

body, whether the greater  number, as in a democracy, or the smaller number, as in an  oligarchy,  is an

accident due to the fact that the rich everywhere are  few, and  the poor numerous. But if so, there is a

misapprehension of  the causes  of the difference between them. For the real difference  between  democracy

and oligarchy is poverty and wealth. Wherever men  rule by  reason of their wealth, whether they be few or

many, that is  an  oligarchy, and where the poor rule, that is a democracy. But as a  fact  the rich are few and the

poor many; for few are welltodo,  whereas  freedom is enjoyed by an, and wealth and freedom are the

grounds on  which the oligarchical and democratical parties  respectively claim  power in the state. 

IX

Let us begin by considering the common definitions of oligarchy  and democracy, and what is justice

oligarchical and democratical.  For  all men cling to justice of some kind, but their conceptions are  imperfect

and they do not express the whole idea. For example, justice  is thought by them to be, and is, equality, not.

however, for however,  for but only for equals. And inequality is thought to be, and is,  justice; neither is this

for all, but only for unequals. When the  persons are omitted, then men judge erroneously. The reason is that

they are passing judgment on themselves, and most people are bad  judges in their own case. And whereas

justice implies a relation to  persons as well as to things, and a just distribution, as I have  already said in the

Ethics, implies the same ratio between the persons  and between the things, they agree about the equality of

the things,  but dispute about the equality of the persons, chiefly for the  reason  which I have just given

because they are bad judges in their  own  affairs; and secondly, because both the parties to the argument  are

speaking of a limited and partial justice, but imagine  themselves to  be speaking of absolute justice. For the

one party, if  they are  unequal in one respect, for example wealth, consider  themselves to be  unequal in all;

and the other party, if they are  equal in one respect,  for example free birth, consider themselves to  be equal in

all. But  they leave out the capital point. For if men  met and associated out of  regard to wealth only, their

share in the  state would be proportioned  to their property, and the oligarchical  doctrine would then seem to

carry the day. It would not be just that  he who paid one mina should  have the same share of a hundred minae,

whether of the principal or of  the profits, as he who paid the  remaining ninetynine. But a state  exists for the

sake of a good life,  and not for the sake of life only:  if life only were the object,  slaves and brute animals

might form a  state, but they cannot, for they  have no share in happiness or in a  life of free choice. Nor does a

state exist for the sake of alliance  and security from injustice,  nor yet for the sake of exchange and  mutual

intercourse; for then  the Tyrrhenians and the Carthaginians,  and all who have commercial  treaties with one

another, would be the  citizens of one state. True,  they have agreements about imports, and  engagements that

they will  do no wrong to one another, and written  articles of alliance. But  there are no magistrates common to

the  contracting parties who will  enforce their engagements; different  states have each their own  magistracies.

Nor does one state take care  that the citizens of the  other are such as they ought to be, nor see  that those who

come  under the terms of the treaty do no wrong or  wickedness at an, but  only that they do no injustice to one

another.  Whereas, those who care  for good government take into consideration  virtue and vice in states.

Whence it may be further inferred that  virtue must be the care of a  state which is truly so called, and not

merely enjoys the name: for  without this end the community becomes a  mere alliance which differs  only in

place from alliances of which the  members live apart; and  law is only a convention, 'a surety to one  another

of justice,' as the  sophist Lycophron says, and has no real  power to make the citizens 

This is obvious; for suppose distinct places, such as Corinth and  Megara, to be brought together so that their


POLITICS

IX 37



Top




Page No 42


walls touched, still they  would not be one city, not even if the citizens had the right to  intermarry, which is

one of the rights peculiarly characteristic of  states. Again, if men dwelt at a distance from one another, but

not so  far off as to have no intercourse, and there were laws among them that  they should not wrong each

other in their exchanges, neither would  this be a state. Let us suppose that one man is a carpenter, another a

husbandman, another a shoemaker, and so on, and that their number is  ten thousand: nevertheless, if they

have nothing in common but  exchange, alliance, and the like, that would not constitute a state.  Why is this?

Surely not because they are at a distance from one  another: for even supposing that such a community were to

meet in  one  place, but that each man had a house of his own, which was in a  manner  his state, and that they

made alliance with one another, but  only  against evildoers; still an accurate thinker would not deem this  to

be a state, if their intercourse with one another was of the same  character after as before their union. It is clear

then that a state  is not a mere society, having a common place, established for the  prevention of mutual crime

and for the sake of exchange. These are  conditions without which a state cannot exist; but all of them  together

do not constitute a state, which is a community of families  and aggregations of families in wellbeing, for the

sake of a  perfect  and selfsufficing life. Such a community can only be  established  among those who live in

the same place and intermarry.  Hence arise in  cities family connections, brotherhoods, common  sacrifices,

amusements  which draw men together. But these are  created by friendship, for the  will to live together is

friendship.  The end of the state is the good  life, and these are the means towards  it. And the state is the union

of families and villages in a perfect  and selfsufficing life, by  which we mean a happy and honorable life. 

Our conclusion, then, is that political society exists for the  sake of noble actions, and not of mere

companionship. Hence they who  contribute most to such a society have a greater share in it than  those who

have the same or a greater freedom or nobility of birth  but  are inferior to them in political virtue; or than

those who exceed  them in wealth but are surpassed by them in virtue. 

From what has been said it will be clearly seen that all the  partisans of different forms of government speak

of a part of  justice  only. 

X

There is also a doubt as to what is to be the supreme power in the  state: Is it the multitude? Or the wealthy?

Or the good? Or the one  best man? Or a tyrant? Any of these alternatives seems to involve  disagreeable

consequences. If the poor, for example, because they  are  more in number, divide among themselves the

property of the  rich is  not this unjust? No, by heaven (will be the reply), for the  supreme  authority justly

willed it. But if this is not injustice, pray  what  is? Again, when in the first division all has been taken, and the

majority divide anew the property of the minority, is it not  evident,  if this goes on, that they will ruin the

state? Yet surely,  virtue is  not the ruin of those who possess her, nor is justice  destructive of a  state; and

therefore this law of confiscation clearly  cannot be just.  If it were, all the acts of a tyrant must of necessity  be

just; for he  only coerces other men by superior power, just as  the multitude coerce  the rich. But is it just then

that the few and  the wealthy should be  the rulers? And what if they, in like manner,  rob and plunder the

people is this just? if so, the other case will  likewise be just. But  there can be no doubt that all these things

are wrong and unjust. 

Then ought the good to rule and have supreme power? But in that  case  everybody else, being excluded from

power, will be dishonored.  For the  offices of a state are posts of honor; and if one set of men  always  holds

them, the rest must be deprived of them. Then will it be  well  that the one best man should rule? Nay, that is

still more  oligarchical, for the number of those who are dishonored is thereby  increased. Some one may say

that it is bad in any case for a man,  subject as he is to all the accidents of human passion, to have the  supreme

power, rather than the law. But what if the law itself be  democratical or oligarchical, how will that help us out

of our  difficulties? Not at all; the same consequences will follow. 


POLITICS

X 38



Top




Page No 43


XI

Most of these questions may be reserved for another occasion. The  principle that the multitude ought to be

supreme rather than the few  best is one that is maintained, and, though not free from  difficulty,  yet seems to

contain an element of truth. For the many, of  whom each  individual is but an ordinary person, when they

meet  together may very  likely be better than the few good, if regarded  not individually but  collectively, just

as a feast to which many  contribute is better than  a dinner provided out of a single purse. For  each individual

among the  many has a share of virtue and prudence, and  when they meet together,  they become in a manner

one man, who has many  feet, and hands, and  senses; that is a figure of their mind and  disposition. Hence the

many  are better judges than a single man of  music and poetry; for some  understand one part, and some

another,  and among them they understand  the whole. There is a similar  combination of qualities in good men,

who differ from any individual  of the many, as the beautiful are said  to differ from those who are  not

beautiful, and works of art from  realities, because in them the  scattered elements are combined,  although, if

taken separately, the  eye of one person or some other  feature in another person would be  fairer than in the

picture. Whether  this principle can apply to  every democracy, and to all bodies of men,  is not clear. Or rather,

by  heaven, in some cases it is impossible of  application; for the  argument would equally hold about brutes;

and  wherein, it will be  asked, do some men differ from brutes? But there  may be bodies of  men about whom

our statement is nevertheless true.  And if so, the  difficulty which has been already raised, and also  another

which is  akin to it viz., what power should be assigned to  the mass of freemen  and citizens, who are not rich

and have no  personal merit are both  solved. There is still a danger in aflowing  them to share the great

offices of state, for their folly will lead  them into error, and their  dishonesty into crime. But there is a  danger

also in not letting  them share, for a state in which many poor  men are excluded from  office will necessarily

be full of enemies. The  only way of escape  is to assign to them some deliberative and judicial  functions. For

this reason Solon and certain other legislators give  them the power of  electing to offices, and of calling the

magistrates  to account, but  they do not allow them to hold office singly. When  they meet  together their

perceptions are quite good enough, and  combined with  the better class they are useful to the state (just as

impure food  when mixed with what is pure sometimes makes the entire  mass more  wholesome than a small

quantity of the pure would be), but  each  individual, left to himself, forms an imperfect judgment. On the

other  hand, the popular form of government involves certain  difficulties. In  the first place, it might be

objected that he who can  judge of the  healing of a sick man would be one who could himself heal  his disease,

and make him whole that is, in other words, the  physician; and so  in all professions and arts. As, then, the

physician  ought to be  called to account by physicians, so ought men in general  to be  called to account by their

peers. But physicians are of three  kinds:  there is the ordinary practitioner, and there is the physician  of  the

higher class, and thirdly the intelligent man who has studied  the art: in all arts there is such a class; and we

attribute the power  of judging to them quite as much as to professors of the art.  Secondly, does not the same

principle apply to elections? For a  right  election can only be made by those who have knowledge; those who

know  geometry, for example, will choose a geometrician rightly, and  those  who know how to steer, a pilot;

and, even if there be some  occupations  and arts in which private persons share in the ability  to choose, they

certainly cannot choose better than those who know. So  that, according  to this argument, neither the election

of magistrates,  nor the calling  of them to account, should be entrusted to the many.  Yet possibly  these

objections are to a great extent met by our old  answer, that if  the people are not utterly degraded, although

individually they may be  worse judges than those who have special  knowledge as a body they are  as good

or better. Moreover, there are  some arts whose products are  not judged of solely, or best, by the  artists

themselves, namely those  arts whose products are recognized  even by those who do not possess  the art; for

example, the knowledge  of the house is not limited to the  builder only; the user, or, in  other words, the

master, of the house  will be even a better judge than  the builder, just as the pilot will  judge better of a rudder

than  the carpenter, and the guest will judge  better of a feast than the  cook. 

This difficulty seems now to be sufficiently answered, but there  is another akin to it. That inferior persons

should have authority  in  greater matters than the good would appear to be a strange thing,  yet  the election and


POLITICS

XI 39



Top




Page No 44


calling to account of the magistrates is the  greatest  of all. And these, as I was saying, are functions which in

some states  are assigned to the people, for the assembly is supreme in  all such  matters. Yet persons of any

age, and having but a small  property  qualification, sit in the assembly and deliberate and  judge, although  for

the great officers of state, such as treasurers  and generals, a  high qualification is required. This difficulty may

be  solved in the  same manner as the preceding, and the present practice  of democracies  may be really

defensible. For the power does not reside  in the dicast,  or senator, or ecclesiast, but in the court, and the

senate, and the  assembly, of which individual senators, or  ecclesiasts, or dicasts,  are only parts or members.

And for this  reason the many may claim to  have a higher authority than the few; for  the people, and the

senate,  and the courts consist of many persons,  and their property  collectively is greater than the property of

one or  of a few  individuals holding great offices. But enough of this. 

The discussion of the first question shows nothing so clearly as  that laws, when good, should be supreme; and

that the magistrate or  magistrates should regulate those matters only on which the laws are  unable to speak

with precision owing to the difficulty of any  general  principle embracing all particulars. But what are good

laws  has not  yet been clearly explained; the old difficulty remains. The  goodness  or badness, justice or

injustice, of laws varies of necessity  with the  constitutions of states. This, however, is clear, that the  laws

must  be adapted to the constitutions. But if so, true forms of  government  will of necessity have just laws, and

perverted forms of  government  will have unjust laws. 

XII

In all sciences and arts the end is a good, and the greatest good  and in the highest degree a good in the most

authoritative of all  this is the political science of which the good is justice, in other  words, the common

interest. All men think justice to be a sort of  equality; and to a certain extent they agree in the philosophical

distinctions which have been laid down by us about Ethics. For they  admit that justice is a thing and has a

relation to persons, and  that  equals ought to have equality. But there still remains a  question:  equality or

inequality of what? Here is a difficulty which  calls for  political speculation. For very likely some persons will

say  that  offices of state ought to be unequally distributed according to  superior excellence, in whatever

respect, of the citizen, although  there is no other difference between him and the rest of the  community; for

that those who differ in any one respect have different  rights and claims. But, surely, if this is true, the

complexion or  height of a man, or any other advantage, will be a reason for his  obtaining a greater share of

political rights. The error here lies  upon the surface, and may be illustrated from the other arts and  sciences.

When a number of flute players are equal in their art, there  is no reason why those of them who are better

born should have  better  flutes given to them; for they will not play any better on  the flute,  and the superior

instrument should be reserved for him  who is the  superior artist. If what I am saying is still obscure, it  will be

made  clearer as we proceed. For if there were a superior  fluteplayer who  was far inferior in birth and beauty,

although either  of these may be  a greater good than the art of fluteplaying, and  may excel  fluteplaying in a

greater ratio than he excels the others  in his art,  still he ought to have the best flutes given to him,  unless the

advantages of wealth and birth contribute to excellence  in  fluteplaying, which they do not. Moreover, upon

this principle any  good may be compared with any other. For if a given height may be  measured wealth and

against freedom, height in general may be so  measured. Thus if A excels in height more than B in virtue,

even if  virtue in general excels height still more, all goods will be  commensurable; for if a certain amount is

better than some other, it  is clear that some other will be equal. But since no such comparison  can be made, it

is evident that there is good reason why in politics  men do not ground their claim to office on every sort of

inequality  any more than in the arts. For if some be slow, and others swift, that  is no reason why the one

should have little and the others much; it is  in gymnastics contests that such excellence is rewarded. Whereas

the  rival claims of candidates for office can only be based on the  possession of elements which enter into the

composition of a state.  And therefore the noble, or freeborn, or rich, may with good reason  claim office; for

holders of offices must be freemen and taxpayers:  a  state can be no more composed entirely of poor men than

entirely  of  slaves. But if wealth and freedom are necessary elements, justice  and  valor are equally so; for


POLITICS

XII 40



Top




Page No 45


without the former qualities a state  cannot  exist at all, without the latter not well. 

XIII

If the existence of the state is alone to be considered, then it  would seem that all, or some at least, of these

claims are just;  but,  if we take into account a good life, then, as I have already  said,  education and virtue have

superior claims. As, however, those  who are  equal in one thing ought not to have an equal share in all,  nor

those  who are unequal in one thing to have an unequal share in  all, it is  certain that all forms of government

which rest on either  of these  principles are perversions. All men have a claim in a certain  sense,  as I have

already admitted, but all have not an absolute claim.  The  rich claim because they have a greater share in the

land, and land  is  the common element of the state; also they are generally more  trustworthy in contracts. The

free claim under the same tide as the  noble; for they are nearly akin. For the noble are citizens in a truer  sense

than the ignoble, and good birth is always valued in a man's own  home and country. Another reason is, that

those who are sprung from  better ancestors are likely to be better men, for nobility is  excellence of race.

Virtue, too, may be truly said to have a claim,  for justice has been acknowledged by us to be a social virtue,

and  it  implies all others. Again, the many may urge their claim against  the  few; for, when taken collectively,

and compared with the few, they  are  stronger and richer and better. But, what if the good, the rich,  the  noble,

and the other classes who make up a state, are all living  together in the same city, Will there, or will there not,

be any doubt  who shall rule? No doubt at all in determining who ought to rule in  each of the

abovementioned forms of government. For states are  characterized by differences in their governing

bodiesone of them has  a government of the rich, another of the virtuous, and so on. But a  difficulty arises

when all these elements coexist. How are we to  decide? Suppose the virtuous to be very few in number:

may we consider  their numbers in relation to their duties, and ask whether they are  enough to administer the

state, or so many as will make up a state?  Objections may be urged against all the aspirants to political  power.

For those who found their claims on wealth or family might be  thought  to have no basis of justice; on this

principle, if any one  person were  richer than all the rest, it is clear that he ought to  be ruler of  them. In like

manner he who is very distinguished by his  birth ought  to have the superiority over all those who claim on

the  ground that  they are freeborn. In an aristocracy, or government of the  best, a  like difficulty occurs about

virtue; for if one citizen be  better than  the other members of the government, however good they may  be, he

too,  upon the same principle of justice, should rule over them.  And if the  people are to be supreme because

they are stronger than the  few, then  if one man, or more than one, but not a majority, is  stronger than the

many, they ought to rule, and not the many. 

All these considerations appear to show that none of the  principles on which men claim to rule and to hold all

other men in  subjection to them are strictly right. To those who claim to be  masters of the government on the

ground of their virtue or their  wealth, the many might fairly answer that they themselves are often  better and

richer than the few I do not say individually, but  collectively. And another ingenious objection which is

sometimes put  forward may be met in a similar manner. Some persons doubt whether the  legislator who

desires to make the justest laws ought to legislate  with a view to the good of the higher classes or of the

many, when the  case which we have mentioned occurs. Now what is just or right is to  be interpreted in the

sense of 'what is equal'; and that which is  right in the sense of being equal is to be considered with reference

to the advantage of the state, and the common good of the citizens.  And a citizen is one who shares in

governing and being governed. He  differs under different forms of government, but in the best state  he  is one

who is able and willing to be governed and to govern with  a  view to the life of virtue. 

If, however, there be some one person, or more than one, although  not enough to make up the full

complement of a state, whose virtue  is  so preeminent that the virtues or the political capacity of all  the  rest

admit of no comparison with his or theirs, he or they can  be no  longer regarded as part of a state; for justice

will not be done  to  the superior, if he is reckoned only as the equal of those who  are so  far inferior to him in

virtue and in political capacity. Such  an one  may truly be deemed a God among men. Hence we see that


POLITICS

XIII 41



Top




Page No 46


legislation is  necessarily concerned only with those who are equal  in birth and in  capacity; and that for men

of preeminent virtue there  is no law they  are themselves a law. Any would be ridiculous who  attempted to

make  laws for them: they would probably retort what, in  the fable of  Antisthenes, the lions said to the hares,

when in the  council of the  beasts the latter began haranguing and claiming  equality for all. And  for this

reason democratic states have  instituted ostracism; equality  is above all things their aim, and  therefore they

ostracized and  banished from the city for a time  those who seemed to predominate too  much through their

wealth, or  the number of their friends, or through  any other political influence.  Mythology tells us that the

Argonauts  left Heracles behind for a  similar reason; the ship Argo would not  take him because she feared  that

he would have been too much for the  rest of the crew. Wherefore  those who denounce tyranny and blame the

counsel which Periander  gave to Thrasybulus cannot be held altogether  just in their censure.  The story is that

Periander, when the herald  was sent to ask counsel  of him, said nothing, but only cut off the  tallest ears of

corn till  he had brought the field to a level. The  herald did not know the  meaning of the action, but came and

reported  what he had seen to  Thrasybulus, who understood that he was to cut off  the principal men  in the

state; and this is a policy not only  expedient for tyrants or  in practice confined to them, but equally  necessary

in oligarchies and  democracies. Ostracism is a measure of  the same kind, which acts by  disabling and

banishing the most  prominent citizens. Great powers do  the same to whole cities and  nations, as the

Athenians did to the  Samians, Chians, and Lesbians; no  sooner had they obtained a firm  grasp of the empire,

than they humbled  their allies contrary to  treaty; and the Persian king has repeatedly  crushed the Medes,

Babylonians, and other nations, when their spirit  has been stirred  by the recollection of their former greatness. 

The problem is a universal one, and equally concerns all forms of  government, true as well as false; for,

although perverted forms  with  a view to their own interests may adopt this policy, those  which seek  the

common interest do so likewise. The same thing may be  observed in  the arts and sciences; for the painter will

not allow  the figure to  have a foot which, however beautiful, is not in  proportion, nor will  the shipbuilder

allow the stem or any other  part of the vessel to be  unduly large, any more than the chorusmaster  will allow

any one who  sings louder or better than all the rest to  sing in the choir.  Monarchs, too, may practice

compulsion and still  live in harmony with  their cities, if their own government is for  the interest of the  state.

Hence where there is an acknowledged  superiority the argument  in favor of ostracism is based upon a kind of

political justice. It  would certainly be better that the legislator  should from the first so  order his state as to

have no need of such  a remedy. But if the need  arises, the next best thing is that he  should endeavor to correct

the  evil by this or some similar measure.  The principle, however, has not  been fairly applied in states; for,

instead of looking to the good of  their own constitution, they have  used ostracism for factious  purposes. It is

true that under  perverted forms of government, and  from their special point of view,  such a measure is just

and  expedient, but it is also clear that it  is not absolutely just. In the  perfect state there would be great  doubts

about the use of it, not  when applied to excess in strength,  wealth, popularity, or the like,  but when used

against some one who is  preeminent in virtue what is  to be done with him? Mankind will not  say that such

an one is to be  expelled and exiled; on the other  hand, he ought not to be a subject  that would be as if

mankind should  claim to rule over Zeus, dividing  his offices among them. The only  alternative is that all

should  joyfully obey such a ruler, according  to what seems to be the order of  nature, and that men like him

should be kings in their state for life. 

XIV

The preceding discussion, by a natural transition, leads to the  consideration of royalty, which we admit to be

one of the true forms  of government. Let us see whether in order to be well governed a state  or country

should be under the rule of a king or under some other form  of government; and whether monarchy, although

good for some, may not  be bad for others. But first we must determine whether there is one  species of royalty

or many. It is easy to see that there are many, and  that the manner of government is not the same in all of

them. 


POLITICS

XIV 42



Top




Page No 47


Of royalties according to law, (1) the Lacedaemonian is thought to  answer best to the true pattern; but there

the royal power is not  absolute, except when the kings go on an expedition, and then they  take the command.

Matters of religion are likewise committed to  them.  The kingly office is in truth a kind of generalship,

irresponsible and  perpetual. The king has not the power of life and  death, except in a  specified case, as for

instance, in ancient  times, he had it when upon  a campaign, by right of force. This  custom is described in

Homer. For  Agamemnon is patient when he is  attacked in the assembly, but when the  army goes out to battle

he  has the power even of life and death. Does  he not say 'When I find  a man skulking apart from the battle,

nothing  shall save him from  the dogs and vultures, for in my hands is death'? 

This, then, is one form of royaltya generalship for life: and of  such royalties some are hereditary and others

elective. 

(2) There is another sort of monarchy not uncommon among the  barbarians, which nearly resembles tyranny.

But this is both legal and  hereditary. For barbarians, being more servile in character than  Hellenes, and

Asiadics than Europeans, do not rebel against a despotic  government. Such royalties have the nature of

tyrannies because the  people are by nature slaves; but there is no danger of their being  overthrown, for they

are hereditary and legal. Wherefore also their  guards are such as a king and not such as a tyrant would

employ,  that  is to say, they are composed of citizens, whereas the guards of  tyrants are mercenaries. For kings

rule according to law over  voluntary subjects, but tyrants over involuntary; and the one are  guarded by their

fellowcitizens the others are guarded against them. 

These are two forms of monarchy, and there was a third (3) which  existed in ancient Hellas, called an

Aesymnetia or dictatorship.  This  may be defined generally as an elective tyranny, which, like  the  barbarian

monarchy, is legal, but differs from it in not being  hereditary. Sometimes the office was held for life,

sometimes for a  term of years, or until certain duties had been performed. For  example, the Mytilenaeans

elected Pittacus leader against the  exiles,  who were headed by Antimenides and Alcaeus the poet. And

Alcaeus  himself shows in one of his banquet odes that they chose  Pittacus  tyrant, for he reproaches his

fellowcitizens for 'having  made the  lowborn Pittacus tyrant of the spiritless and illfated  city, with  one

voice shouting his praises.' 

These forms of government have always had the character of  tyrannies, because they possess despotic power;

but inasmuch as they  are elective and acquiesced in by their subjects, they are kingly. 

(4) There is a fourth species of kingly rule that of the heroic  times which was hereditary and legal, and was

exercised over  willing  subjects. For the first chiefs were benefactors of the  people in arts  or arms; they either

gathered them into a community, or  procured land  for them; and thus they became kings of voluntary

subjects, and their  power was inherited by their descendants. They  took the command in war  and presided

over the sacrifices, except those  which required a  priest. They also decided causes either with or  without an

oath; and  when they swore, the form of the oath was the  stretching out of their  sceptre. In ancient times their

power extended  continuously to all  things whatsoever, in city and country, as well as  in foreign parts;  but at a

later date they relinquished several of  these privileges, and  others the people took from them, until in  some

states nothing was  left to them but the sacrifices; and where  they retained more of the  reality they had only

the right of  leadership in war beyond the  border. 

These, then, are the four kinds of royalty. First the monarchy of  the heroic ages; this was exercised over

voluntary subjects, but  limited to certain functions; the king was a general and a judge,  and  had the control of

religion The second is that of the  barbarians,  which is a hereditary despotic government in accordance  with

law. A  third is the power of the socalled Aesynmete or Dictator;  this is an  elective tyranny. The fourth is the

Lacedaemonian, which is  in fact a  generalship, hereditary and perpetual. These four forms  differ from  one

another in the manner which I have described. 


POLITICS

XIV 43



Top




Page No 48


(5) There is a fifth form of kingly rule in which one has the  disposal of all, just as each nation or each state

has the disposal of  public matters; this form corresponds to the control of a household.  For as household

management is the kingly rule of a house, so kingly  rule is the household management of a city, or of a

nation, or of many  nations. 

XV

Of these forms we need only consider two, the Lacedaemonian and  the absolute royalty; for most of the

others he in a region between  them, having less power than the last, and more than the first. Thus  the inquiry

is reduced to two points: first, is it advantageous to the  state that there should be a perpetual general, and if

so, should  the  office be confined to one family, or open to the citizens in turn?  Secondly, is it well that a

single man should have the supreme power  in all things? The first question falls under the head of laws  rather

than of constitutions; for perpetual generalship might  equally exist  under any form of government, so that this

matter may be  dismissed for  the present. The other kind of royalty is a sort of  constitution; this  we have now

to consider, and briefly to run over  the difficulties  involved in it. We will begin by inquiring whether it  is

more  advantageous to be ruled by the best man or by the best laws. 

The advocates of royalty maintain that the laws speak only in  general terms, and cannot provide for

circumstances; and that for  any  science to abide by written rules is absurd. In Egypt the  physician is  allowed

to alter his treatment after the fourth day,  but if sooner, he  takes the risk. Hence it is clear that a  government

acting according  to written laws is plainly not the best.  Yet surely the ruler cannot  dispense with the general

principle  which exists in law; and this is a  better ruler which is free from  passion than that in which it is

innate. Whereas the law is  passionless, passion must ever sway the  heart of man. Yes, it may be  replied, but

then on the other hand an  individual will be better  able to deliberate in particular cases. 

The best man, then, must legislate, and laws must be passed, but  these laws will have no authority when they

miss the mark, though in  all other cases retaining their authority. But when the law cannot  determine a point

at all, or not well, should the one best man or  should all decide? According to our present practice assemblies

meet,  sit in judgment, deliberate, and decide, and their judgments  an relate  to individual cases. Now any

member of the assembly, taken  separately,  is certainly inferior to the wise man. But the state is  made up of

many individuals. And as a feast to which all the guests  contribute is  better than a banquet furnished by a

single man, so a  multitude is a  better judge of many things than any individual. 

Again, the many are more incorruptible than the few; they are like  the greater quantity of water which is less

easily corrupted than a  little. The individual is liable to be overcome by anger or by some  other passion, and

then his judgment is necessarily perverted; but  it  is hardly to be supposed that a great number of persons

would all  get  into a passion and go wrong at the same moment. Let us assume that  they are the freemen, and

that they never act in violation of the law,  but fill up the gaps which the law is obliged to leave. Or, if such

virtue is scarcely attainable by the multitude, we need only suppose  that the majority are good men and good

citizens, and ask which will  be the more incorruptible, the one good ruler, or the many who are all  good? Will

not the many? But, you will say, there may be parties among  them, whereas the one man is not divided

against himself. To which  we  may answer that their character is as good as his. If we call the  rule  of many

men, who are all of them good, aristocracy, and the  rule of  one man royalty, then aristocracy will be better for

states  than  royalty, whether the government is supported by force or not,  provided  only that a number of men

equal in virtue can be found. 

The first governments were kingships, probably for this reason,  because of old, when cities were small, men

of eminent virtue were  few. Further, they were made kings because they were benefactors,  and  benefits can

only be bestowed by good men. But when many persons  equal  in merit arose, no longer enduring the

preeminence of one, they  desired to have a commonwealth, and set up a constitution. The  ruling  class soon


POLITICS

XV 44



Top




Page No 49


deteriorated and enriched themselves out of the  public  treasury; riches became the path to honor, and so

oligarchies  naturally grew up. These passed into tyrannies and tyrannies into  democracies; for love of gain in

the ruling classes was always tending  to diminish their number, and so to strengthen the masses, who in  the

end set upon their masters and established democracies. Since  cities  have increased in size, no other form of

government appears  to be any  longer even easy to establish. 

Even supposing the principle to be maintained that kingly power is  the best thing for states, how about the

family of the king? Are his  children to succeed him? If they are no better than anybody else, that  will be

mischievous. But, says the lover of royalty, the king,  though  he might, will not hand on his power to his

children. That,  however,  is hardly to be expected, and is too much to ask of human  nature.  There is also a

difficulty about the force which he is to  employ;  should a king have guards about him by whose aid he may

be  able to  coerce the refractory? If not, how will he administer his  kingdom?  Even if he be the lawful

sovereign who does nothing  arbitrarily or  contrary to law, still he must have some force  wherewith to

maintain  the law. In the case of a limited monarchy there  is not much  difficulty in answering this question;

the king must  have such force  as will be more than a match for one or more  individuals, but not so  great as

that of the people. The ancients  observe this principle when  they have guards to any one whom they

appointed dictator or tyrant.  Thus, when Dionysius asked the  Syracusans to allow him guards,  somebody

advised that they should give  him only such a number. 

XVI

At this place in the discussion there impends the inquiry  respecting  the king who acts solely according to his

own will he has  now to be  considered. The socalled limited monarchy, or kingship  according to  law, as I

have already remarked, is not a distinct form  of government,  for under all governments, as, for example, in a

democracy or  aristocracy, there may be a general holding office for  life, and one  person is often made

supreme over the administration of  a state. A  magistracy of this kind exists at Epidamnus, and also at  Opus,

but  in the latter city has a more limited power. Now, absolute  monarchy,  or the arbitrary rule of a sovereign

over an the citizens,  in a city  which consists of equals, is thought by some to be quite  contrary to  nature; it is

argued that those who are by nature equals  must have the  same natural right and worth, and that for unequals

to  have an equal  share, or for equals to have an uneven share, in the  offices of state,  is as bad as for different

bodily constitutions to  have the same  food and clothing. Wherefore it is thought to be just  that among  equals

every one be ruled as well as rule, and therefore  that an  should have their turn. We thus arrive at law; for an

order of  succession implies law. And the rule of the law, it is argued, is  preferable to that of any individual.

On the same principle, even if  it be better for certain individuals to govern, they should be made  only

guardians and ministers of the law. For magistrates there must  be this is admitted; but then men say that to

give authority to any  one man when all are equal is unjust. Nay, there may indeed be cases  which the law

seems unable to determine, but in such cases can a  man?  Nay, it will be replied, the law trains officers for this

express  purpose, and appoints them to determine matters which are left  undecided by it, to the best of their

judgment. Further, it permits  them to make any amendment of the existing laws which experience  suggests.

Therefore he who bids the law rule may be deemed to bid  God  and Reason alone rule, but he who bids man

rule adds an element of  the  beast; for desire is a wild beast, and passion perverts the  minds of  rulers, even

when they are the best of men. The law is reason  unaffected by desire. We are told that a patient should call

in a  physician; he will not get better if he is doctored out of a book. But  the parallel of the arts is clearly not in

point; for the physician  does nothing contrary to rule from motives of friendship; he only  cures a patient and

takes a fee; whereas magistrates do many things  from spite and partiality. And, indeed, if a man suspected the

physician of being in league with his enemies to destroy him for a  bribe, he would rather have recourse to the

book. But certainly  physicians, when they are sick, call in other physicians, and  trainingmasters, when they

are in training, other trainingmasters,  as if they could not judge judge truly about their own case and  might

be influenced by their feelings. Hence it is evident that in  seeking  for justice men seek for the mean or

neutral, for the law is  the mean.  Again, customary laws have more weight, and relate to more  important


POLITICS

XVI 45



Top




Page No 50


matters, than written laws, and a man may be a safer ruler  than the  written law, but not safer than the

customary law. 

Again, it is by no means easy for one man to superintend many  things; he will have to appoint a number of

subordinates, and what  difference does it make whether these subordinates always existed or  were appointed

by him because he needed theme If, as I said before,  the good man has a right to rule because he is better, still

two  good  men are better than one: this is the old saying, two going  together,  and the prayer of Agamemnon, 

Would that I had ten such councillors!  And at this day there are  magistrates, for example judges, who have

authority to decide some  matters which the law is unable to determine,  since no one doubts that  the law

would command and decide in the  best manner whatever it could.  But some things can, and other things

cannot, be comprehended under  the law, and this is the origin of the  nexted question whether the  best law or

the best man should rule.  For matters of detail about  which men deliberate cannot be included in  legislation.

Nor does any  one deny that the decision of such matters  must be left to man, but it  is argued that there should

be many  judges, and not one only. For  every ruler who has been trained by  the law judges well; and it would

surely seem strange that a person  should see better with two eyes, or  hear better with two ears, or  act better

with two hands or feet, than  many with many; indeed, it  is already the practice of kings to make to

themselves many eyes and  ears and hands and feet. For they make  colleagues of those who are the  friends of

themselves and their  governments. They must be friends of  the monarch and of his  government; if not his

friends, they will not  do what he wants; but  friendship implies likeness and equality; and,  therefore, if he

thinks  that his friends ought to rule, he must  think that those who are equal  to himself and like himself ought

to  rule equally with himself. These  are the principal controversies  relating to monarchy. 

XVII

But may not all this be true in some cases and not in others? for  there is by nature both a justice and an

advantage appropriate to  the  rule of a master, another to kingly rule, another to  constitutional  rule; but there is

none naturally appropriate to  tyranny, or to any  other perverted form of government; for these  come into

being contrary  to nature. Now, to judge at least from what  has been said, it is  manifest that, where men are

alike and equal,  it is neither expedient  nor just that one man should be lord of all,  whether there are laws,  or

whether there are no laws, but he himself  is in the place of law.  Neither should a good man be lord over good

men, nor a bad man over  bad; nor, even if he excels in virtue,  should he have a right to rule,  unless in a

particular case, at  which I have already hinted, and to  which I will once more recur.  But first of all, I must

determine what  natures are suited for  government by a king, and what for an  aristocracy, and what for a

constitutional government. 

A people who are by nature capable of producing a race superior in  the virtue needed for political rule are

fitted for kingly government;  and a people submitting to be ruled as freemen by men whose virtue  renders

them capable of political command are adapted for an  aristocracy; while the people who are suited for

constitutional  freedom are those among whom there naturally exists a warlike  multitude able to rule and to

obey in turn by a law which gives office  to the welltodo according to their desert. But when a whole

family  or some individual, happens to be so preeminent in virtue as to  surpass all others, then it is just that

they should be the royal  family and supreme over all, or that this one citizen should be king  of the whole

nation. For, as I said before, to give them authority  is  not only agreeable to that ground of right which the

founders of  all  states, whether aristocratical, or oligarchical, or again  democratical, are accustomed to put

forward (for these all recognize  the claim of excellence, although not the same excellence), but  accords with

the principle already laid down. For surely it would  not  be right to kill, or ostracize, or exile such a person, or

require  that he should take his turn in being governed. The whole is naturally  superior to the part, and he who

has this preeminence is in the  relation of a whole to a part. But if so, the only alternative is that  he should

have the supreme power, and that mankind should obey him,  not in turn, but always. These are the


POLITICS

XVII 46



Top




Page No 51


conclusions at which we  arrive  respecting royalty and its various forms, and this is the  answer to  the question,

whether it is or is not advantageous to  states, and to  which, and how. 

XVIII

We maintain that the true forms of government are three, and that  the best must be that which is administered

by the best, and in  which  there is one man, or a whole family, or many persons,  excelling all  the others

together in virtue, and both rulers and  subjects are  fitted, the one to rule, the others to be ruled, in  such a

manner as  to attain the most eligible life. We showed at the  commencement of our  inquiry that the virtue of

the good man is  necessarily the same as the  virtue of the citizen of the perfect  state. Clearly then in the same

manner, and by the same means  through which a man becomes truly good,  he will frame a state that  is to be

ruled by an aristocracy or by a  king, and the same  education and the same habits will be found to make  a

good man and a  man fit to be a statesman or a king. 

Having arrived at these conclusions, we must proceed to speak of  the  perfect state, and describe how it comes

into being and is  established. 

BOOK FOUR

I

IN all arts and sciences which embrace the whole of any subject,  and  do not come into being in a fragmentary

way, it is the province of  a  single art or science to consider all that appertains to a single  subject. For

example, the art of gymnastic considers not only the  suitableness of different modes of training to different

bodies (2),  but what sort is absolutely the best (1); (for the absolutely best  must suit that which is by nature

best and best furnished with the  means of life), and also what common form of training is adapted to  the great

majority of men (4). And if a man does not desire the best  habit of body, or the greatest skill in gymnastics,

which might be  attained by him, still the trainer or the teacher of gymnastic  should  be able to impart any

lower degree of either (3). The same  principle  equally holds in medicine and shipbuilding, and the making  of

clothes,  and in the arts generally. 

Hence it is obvious that government too is the subject of a single  science, which has to consider what

government is best and of what  sort it must be, to be most in accordance with our aspirations, if  there were no

external impediment, and also what kind of government is  adapted to particular states. For the best is often

unattainable,  and  therefore the true legislator and statesman ought to be  acquainted,  not only with (1) that

which is best in the abstract,  but also with  (2) that which is best relatively to circumstances. We  should be

able  further to say how a state may be constituted under any  given  conditions (3); both how it is originally

formed and, when  formed, how  it may be longest preserved; the supposed state being so  far from  having the

best constitution that it is unprovided even  with the  conditions necessary for the best; neither is it the best

under the  circumstances, but of an inferior type. 

He ought, moreover, to know (4) the form of government which is  best  suited to states in general; for political

writers, although they  have  excellent ideas, are often unpractical. We should consider, not  only  what form of

government is best, but also what is possible and  what is  easily attainable by all. There are some who would

have none  but the  most perfect; for this many natural advantages are required.  Others,  again, speak of a more

attainable form, and, although they  reject  the constitution under which they are living, they extol some  one in

particular, for example the Lacedaemonian. Any change of  government  which has to be introduced should be

one which men,  starting from  their existing constitutions, will be both willing and  able to  adopt, since there is

quite as much trouble in the reformation  of an  old constitution as in the establishment of a new one, just as  to

unlearn is as hard as to learn. And therefore, in addition to the  qualifications of the statesman already


POLITICS

XVIII 47



Top




Page No 52


mentioned, he should be able  to find remedies for the defects of existing constitutions, as has  been said

before. This he cannot do unless he knows how many forms  of  government there are. It is often supposed that

there is only one  kind  of democracy and one of oligarchy. But this is a mistake; and, in  order to avoid such

mistakes, we must ascertain what differences there  are in the constitutions of states, and in how many ways

they are  combined. The same political insight will enable a man to know which  laws are the best, and which

are suited to different constitutions;  for the laws are, and ought to be, relative to the constitution, and  not the

constitution to the laws. A constitution is the organization  of offices in a state, and determines what is to be

the governing  body, and what is the end of each community. But laws are not to be  confounded with the

principles of the constitution; they are the rules  according to which the magistrates should administer the

state, and  proceed against offenders. So that we must know the varieties, and the  number of varieties, of each

form of government, if only with a view  to making laws. For the same laws cannot be equally suited to all

oligarchies or to all democracies, since there is certainly more  than  one form both of democracy and of

oligarchy. 

II

In our original discussion about governments we divided them into  three true forms: kingly rule, aristocracy,

and constitutional  government, and three corresponding perversions tyranny, oligarchy,  and democracy. Of

kingly rule and of aristocracy, we have already  spoken, for the inquiry into the perfect state is the same thing

with  the discussion of the two forms thus named, since both imply a  principle of virtue provided with

external means. We have already  determined in what aristocracy and kingly rule differ from one  another, and

when the latter should be established. In what follows we  have to describe the socalled constitutional

government, which  bears  the common name of all constitutions, and the other forms,  tyranny,  oligarchy, and

democracy. 

It is obvious which of the three perversions is the worst, and  which  is the next in badness. That which is the

perversion of the  first  and most divine is necessarily the worst. And just as a royal  rule, if  not a mere name,

must exist by virtue of some great personal  superiority in the king, so tyranny, which is the worst of

governments, is necessarily the farthest removed from a  wellconstituted form; oligarchy is little better, for it

is a long  way from aristocracy, and democracy is the most tolerable of the  three. 

A writer who preceded me has already made these distinctions, but  his point of view is not the same as mine.

For he lays down the  principle that when all the constitutions are good (the oligarchy  and  the rest being

virtuous), democracy is the worst, but the best  when  all are bad. Whereas we maintain that they are in any

case  defective,  and that one oligarchy is not to be accounted better than  another, but  only less bad. 

Not to pursue this question further at present, let us begin by  determining (1) how many varieties of

constitution there are (since of  democracy and oligarchy there are several): (2) what constitution is  the most

generally acceptable, and what is eligible in the next degree  after the perfect state; and besides this what other

there is which is  aristocratical and wellconstituted, and at the same time adapted to  states in general; (3) of

the other forms of government to whom each  is suited. For democracy may meet the needs of some better

than  oligarchy, and conversely. In the next place (4) we have to consider  in what manner a man ought to

proceed who desires to establish some  one among these various forms, whether of democracy or of oligarchy;

and lastly, (5) having briefly discussed these subjects to the best of  our power, we will endeavor to ascertain

the modes of ruin and  preservation both of constitutions generally and of each separately,  and to what causes

they are to be attributed. 


POLITICS

II 48



Top




Page No 53


III

The reason why there are many forms of government is that every  state contains many elements. In the first

place we see that all  states are made up of families, and in the multitude of citizen  there  must be some rich

and some poor, and some in a middle condition;  the  rich are heavyarmed, and the poor not. Of the common

people, some  are  husbandmen, and some traders, and some artisans. There are also  among  the notables

differences of wealth and property for example, in  the  number of horses which they keep, for they cannot

afford to keep  them  unless they are rich. And therefore in old times the cities whose  strength lay in their

cavalry were oligarchies, and they used  cavalry  in wars against their neighbors; as was the practice of the

Eretrians  and Chalcidians, and also of the Magnesians on the river  Maeander, and  of other peoples in Asia.

Besides differences of  wealth there are  differences of rank and merit, and there are some  other elements

which  were mentioned by us when in treating of  aristocracy we enumerated the  essentials of a state. Of these

elements, sometimes all, sometimes the  lesser and sometimes the  greater number, have a share in the

government. It is evident then  that there must be many forms of  government, differing in kind,  since the parts

of which they are  composed differ from each other in  kind. For a constitution is an  organization of offices,

which all  the citizens distribute among  themselves, according to the power which  different classes possess,

for example the rich or the poor, or  according to some principle of  equality which includes both. There  must

therefore be as many forms of  government as there are modes of  arranging the offices, according to  the

superiorities and  differences of the parts of the state. 

There are generally thought to be two principal forms: as men say  of  the winds that there are but two north

and south, and that the  rest  of them are only variations of these, so of governments there are  said  to be only

two forms democracy and oligarchy. For aristocracy is  considered to be a kind of oligarchy, as being the

rule of a few,  and  the socalled constitutional government to be really a  democracy, just  as among the winds

we make the west a variation of the  north, and the  east of the south wind. Similarly of musical modes  there

are said to  be two kinds, the Dorian and the Phrygian; the other  arrangements of  the scale are comprehended

under one or other of these  two. About  forms of government this is a very favorite notion. But  in either case

the better and more exact way is to distinguish, as I  have done, the  one or two which are true forms, and to

regard the  others as  perversions, whether of the most perfectly attempered mode  or of the  best form of

government: we may compare the severer and more  overpowering modes to the oligarchical forms, and the

more relaxed and  gentler ones to the democratic. 

IV

It must not be assumed, as some are fond of saying, that democracy  is simply that form of government in

which the greater number are  sovereign, for in oligarchies, and indeed in every government, the  majority

rules; nor again is oligarchy that form of government in  which a few are sovereign. Suppose the whole

population of a city to  be 1300, and that of these 1000 are rich, and do not allow the  remaining 300 who are

poor, but free, and in an other respects their  equals, a share of the government no one will say that this is a

democracy. In like manner, if the poor were few and the masters of the  rich who outnumber them, no one

would ever call such a government,  in  which the rich majority have no share of office, an oligarchy.

Therefore we should rather say that democracy is the form of  government in which the free are rulers, and

oligarchy in which the  rich; it is only an accident that the free are the many and the rich  are the few.

Otherwise a government in which the offices were given  according to stature, as is said to be the case in

Ethiopia, or  according to beauty, would be an oligarchy; for the number of tall  or  goodlooking men is small.

And yet oligarchy and democracy are  not  sufficiently distinguished merely by these two characteristics  of

wealth and freedom. Both of them contain many other elements, and  therefore we must carry our analysis

further, and say that the  government is not a democracy in which the freemen, being few in  number, rule over

the many who are not free, as at Apollonia, on the  Ionian Gulf, and at Thera; (for in each of these states the

nobles,  who were also the earliest settlers, were held in chief honor,  although they were but a few out of


POLITICS

III 49



Top




Page No 54


many). Neither is it a democracy  when the rich have the government because they exceed in number; as  was

the case formerly at Colophon, where the bulk of the inhabitants  were possessed of large property before the

Lydian War. But the form  of government is a democracy when the free, who are also poor and  the  majority,

govern, and an oligarchy when the rich and the noble  govern,  they being at the same time few in number. 

I have said that there are many forms of government, and have  explained to what causes the variety is due.

Why there are more than  those already mentioned, and what they are, and whence they arise, I  will now

proceed to consider, starting from the principle already  admitted, which is that every state consists, not of

one, but of  many  parts. If we were going to speak of the different species of  animals,  we should first of all

determine the organs which are  indispensable to  every animal, as for example some organs of sense and  the

instruments  of receiving and digesting food, such as the mouth and  the stomach,  besides organs of

locomotion. Assuming now that there are  only so many  kinds of organs, but that there may be differences in

them I mean  different kinds of mouths, and stomachs, and perceptive  and locomotive  organs the possible

combinations of these  differences will  necessarily furnish many variedes of animals. (For  animals cannot be

the same which have different kinds of mouths or  of ears.) And when  all the combinations are exhausted,

there will be  as many sorts of  animals as there are combinations of the necessary  organs. The same,  then, is

true of the forms of government which  have been described;  states, as I have repeatedly said, are  composed,

not of one, but of  many elements. One element is the  foodproducing class, who are called  husbandmen; a

second, the class  of mechanics who practice the arts  without which a city cannot  exist; of these arts some are

absolutely  necessary, others  contribute to luxury or to the grace of life. The  third class is  that of traders, and

by traders I mean those who are  engaged in buying  and selling, whether in commerce or in retail trade.  A

fourth class is  that of the serfs or laborers. The warriors make up  the fifth class,  and they are as necessary as

any of the others, if  the country is  not to be the slave of every invader. For how can a  state which has  any title

to the name be of a slavish nature? The  state is independent  and selfsufficing, but a slave is the reverse of

independent. Hence  we see that this subject, though ingeniously, has  not been  satisfactorily treated in the

Republic. Socrates says that a  state  is made up of four sorts of people who are absolutely necessary;  these  are

a weaver, a husbandman, a shoemaker, and a builder;  afterwards,  finding that they are not enough, he adds a

smith, and  again a  herdsman, to look after the necessary animals; then a  merchant, and  then a retail trader. All

these together form the  complement of the  first state, as if a state were established merely  to supply the

necessaries of life, rather than for the sake of the  good, or stood  equally in need of shoemakers and of

husbandmen. But he  does not admit  into the state a military class until the country has  increased in  size, and

is beginning to encroach on its neighbor's  land, whereupon  they go to war. Yet even amongst his four original

citizens, or  whatever be the number of those whom he associates in the  state, there  must be some one who

will dispense justice and determine  what is just.  And as the soul may be said to be more truly part of an

animal than  the body, so the higher parts of states, that is to say,  the warrior  class, the class engaged in the

administration of justice,  and that  engaged in deliberation, which is the special business of  political  common

sensethese are more essential to the state than the  parts  which  minister to the necessaries of life. Whether

their  several  functions are the functions of different citizens, or of the  same for  it may often happen that the

same persons are both warriors  and  husbandmen is immaterial to the argument. The higher as well as  the

lower elements are to be equally considered parts of the state,  and if  so, the military element at any rate must

be included. There  are  also the wealthy who minister to the state with their property;  these form the seventh

class. The eighth class is that of  magistrates  and of officers; for the state cannot exist without  rulers. And

therefore some must be able to take office and to serve  the state,  either always or in turn. There only remains

the class of  those who  deliberate and who judge between disputants; we were just  now  distinguishing them. If

presence of all these elements, and  their fair  and equitable organization, is necessary to states, then  there must

also be persons who have the ability of statesmen.  Different functions  appear to be often combined in the

same  individual; for example, the  warrior may also be a husbandman, or an  artisan; or, again, the  councillor a

judge. And all claim to possess  political ability, and  think that they are quite competent to fill  most offices.

But the same  persons cannot be rich and poor at the same  time. For this reason the  rich and the poor are

regarded in an  especial sense as parts of a  state. Again, because the rich are  generally few in number, while

the  poor are many, they appear to be  antagonistic, and as the one or the  other prevails they form the


POLITICS

III 50



Top




Page No 55


government. Hence arises the common  opinion that there are two kinds  of government democracy and

oligarchy. 

I have already explained that there are many forms of  constitution, and to what causes the variety is due. Let

me now show  that there are different forms both of democracy and oligarchy, as  will indeed be evident from

what has preceded. For both in the  common  people and in the notables various classes are included; of the

common  people, one class are husbandmen, another artisans; another  traders,  who are employed in buying

and selling; another are the  seafaring  class, whether engaged in war or in trade, as ferrymen or as  fishermen.

(In many places any one of these classes forms quite a  large population; for example, fishermen at Tarentum

and Byzantium,  crews of triremes at Athens, merchant seamen at Aegina and Chios,  ferrymen at Tenedos.)

To the classes already mentioned may be added  daylaborers, and those who, owing to their needy

circumstances,  have  no leisure, or those who are not of free birth on both sides; and  there may be other

classes as well. The notables again may be  divided  according to their wealth, birth, virtue, education, and

similar  differences. 

Of forms of democracy first comes that which is said to be based  strictly on equality. In such a democracy the

law says that it is just  for the poor to have no more advantage than the rich; and that neither  should be

masters, but both equal. For if liberty and equality, as  is  thought by some, are chiefly to be found in

democracy, they will be  best attained when all persons alike share in the government to the  utmost. And since

the people are the majority, and the opinion of  the  majority is decisive, such a government must necessarily

be a  democracy. Here then is one sort of democracy. There is another, in  which the magistrates are elected

according to a certain property  qualification, but a low one; he who has the required amount of  property has a

share in the government, but he who loses his  property  loses his rights. Another kind is that in which all the

citizens who  are under no disqualification share in the government,  but still the  law is supreme. In another,

everybody, if he be only a  citizen, is  admitted to the government, but the law is supreme as  before. A fifth

form of democracy, in other respects the same, is that  in which, not  the law, but the multitude, have the

supreme power,  and supersede the  law by their decrees. This is a state of affairs  brought about by the

demagogues. For in democracies which are  subject to the law the best  citizens hold the first place, and there

are no demagogues; but where  the laws are not supreme, there  demagogues spring up. For the people

becomes a monarch, and is many in  one; and the many have the power in  their hands, not as individuals,  but

collectively. Homer says that 'it  is not good to have a rule of  many,' but whether he means this  corporate rule,

or the rule of many  individuals, is uncertain. At all  events this sort of democracy, which  is now a monarch,

and no longer  under the control of law, seeks to  exercise monarchical sway, and  grows into a despot; the

flatterer is  held in honor; this sort of  democracy being relatively to other  democracies what tyranny is to  other

forms of monarchy. The spirit  of both is the same, and they  alike exercise a despotic rule over  the better

citizens. The decrees  of the demos correspond to the edicts  of the tyrant; and the demagogue  is to the one

what the flatterer is  to the other. Both have great  power; the flatterer with the tyrant,  the demagogue with

democracies  of the kind which we are describing.  The demagogues make the decrees  of the people override

the laws, by  referring all things to the  popular assembly. And therefore they  grow great, because the people

have an things in their hands, and they  hold in their hands the votes  of the people, who are too ready to  listen

to them. Further, those who  have any complaint to bring against  the magistrates say, 'Let the  people be

judges'; the people are too  happy to accept the invitation;  and so the authority of every office  is undermined.

Such a democracy  is fairly open to the objection that  it is not a constitution at all;  for where the laws have no

authority,  there is no constitution. The  law ought to be supreme over all, and  the magistracies should judge of

particulars, and only this should  be considered a constitution. So  that if democracy be a real form of

government, the sort of system in  which all things are regulated by  decrees is clearly not even a  democracy in

the true sense of the word,  for decrees relate only to  particulars. 

These then are the different kinds of democracy.


POLITICS

III 51



Top




Page No 56


V

Of oligarchies, too, there are different kinds: one where the  property qualification for office is such that the

poor, although they  form the majority, have no share in the government, yet he who  acquires a qualification

may obtain a share. Another sort is when  there is a qualification for office, but a high one, and the vacancies

in the governing body are fired by cooptation. If the election is  made out of all the qualified persons, a

constitution of this kind  inclines to an aristocracy, if out of a privileged class, to an  oligarchy. Another sort of

oligarchy is when the son succeeds the  father. There is a fourth form, likewise hereditary, in which the

magistrates are supreme and not the law. Among oligarchies this is  what tyranny is among monarchies, and

the lastmentioned form of  democracy among democracies; and in fact this sort of oligarchy  receives the

name of a dynasty (or rule of powerful families). 

These are the different sorts of oligarchies and democracies. It  should, however, be remembered that in many

states the constitution  which is established by law, although not democratic, owing to the  education and

habits of the people may be administered democratically,  and conversely in other states the established

constitution may  incline to democracy, but may be administered in an oligarchical  spirit. This most often

happens after a revolution: for governments do  not change at once; at first the dominant party are content

with  encroaching a little upon their opponents. The laws which existed  previously continue in force, but the

authors of the revolution have  the power in their hands. 

VI

From what has been already said we may safely infer that there are  so many different kinds of democracies

and of oligarchies. For it is  evident that either all the classes whom we mentioned must share in  the

government, or some only and not others. When the class of  husbandmen and of those who possess moderate

fortunes have the supreme  power, the government is administered according to law. For the  citizens being

compelled to live by their labor have no leisure; and  so they set up the authority of the law, and attend

assemblies only  when necessary. They all obtain a share in the government when they  have acquired the

qualification which is fixed by the law the  absolute exclusion of any class would be a step towards

oligarchy;  hence all who have acquired the property qualification are admitted to  a share in the constitution.

But leisure cannot be provided for them  unless there are revenues to support them. This is one sort of

democracy, and these are the causes which give birth to it. Another  kind is based on the distinction which

naturally comes next in  order;  in this, every one to whose birth there is no objection is  eligible,  but actually

shares in the government only if he can find  leisure.  Hence in such a democracy the supreme power is vested

in  the laws,  because the state has no means of paying the citizens. A  third kind is  when all freemen have a

right to share in the  government, but do not  actually share, for the reason which has been  already given; so

that  in this form again the law must rule. A  fourth kind of democracy is  that which comes latest in the history

of states. In our own day, when  cities have far outgrown their  original size, and their revenues have  increased,

all the citizens  have a place in the government, through  the great preponderance of the  multitude; and they

all, including the  poor who receive pay, and  therefore have leisure to exercise their  rights, share in the

administration. Indeed, when they are paid, the  common people have the  most leisure, for they are not

hindered by the  care of their property,  which often fetters the rich, who are thereby  prevented from taking

part in the assembly or in the courts, and so  the state is governed by  the poor, who are a majority, and not by

the  laws. 

So many kinds of democracies there are, and they grow out of these  necessary causes. 

Of oligarchies, one form is that in which the majority of the  citizens have some property, but not very much;

and this is the  first  form, which allows to any one who obtains the required amount  the  right of sharing in the

government. The sharers in the  government  being a numerous body, it follows that the law must govern,  and


POLITICS

V 52



Top




Page No 57


not  individuals. For in proportion as they are further removed  from a  monarchical form of government, and in

respect of property have  neither so much as to be able to live without attending to business,  nor so little as to

need state support, they must admit the rule of  law and not claim to rule themselves. But if the men of

property in  the state are fewer than in the former case, and own more property,  there arises a second form of

oligarchy. For the stronger they are,  the more power they claim, and having this object in view, they

themselves select those of the other classes who are to be admitted to  the government; but, not being as yet

strong enough to rule without  the law, they make the law represent their wishes. When this power  is

intensified by a further diminution of their numbers and increase  of  their property, there arises a third and

further stage of  oligarchy,  in which the governing class keep the offices in their  own hands, and  the law

ordains that the son shall succeed the  father. When, again,  the rulers have great wealth and numerous  friends,

this sort of family  despotism approaches a monarchy;  individuals rule and not the law.  This is the fourth sort

of  oligarchy, and is analogous to the last  sort of democracy. 

VII

There are still two forms besides democracy and oligarchy; one of  them is universally recognized and

included among the four principal  forms of government, which are said to be (1) monarchy, (2) oligarchy,  (3)

democracy, and (4) the socalled aristocracy or government of  the  best. But there is also a fifth, which retains

the generic name of  polity or constitutional government; this is not common, and therefore  has not been

noticed by writers who attempt to enumerate the different  kinds of government; like Plato, in their books

about the state,  they  recognize four only. The term 'aristocracy' is rightly applied to  the  form of government

which is described in the first part of our  treatise; for that only can be rightly called aristocracy which is a

government formed of the best men absolutely, and not merely of men  who are good when tried by any given

standard. In the perfect state  the good man is absolutely the same as the good citizen; whereas in  other states

the good citizen is only good relatively to his own  form  of government. But there are some states differing

from  oligarchies  and also differing from the socalled polity or  constitutional  government; these are termed

aristocracies, and in them  the  magistrates are certainly chosen, both according to their wealth  and  according

to their merit. Such a form of government differs from  each  of the two just now mentioned, and is termed an

aristocracy.  For  indeed in states which do not make virtue the aim of the  community,  men of merit and

reputation for virtue may be found. And so  where a  government has regard to wealth, virtue, and numbers, as

at  Carthage,  that is aristocracy; and also where it has regard only to  two out of  the three, as at Lacedaemon, to

virtue and numbers, and the  two  principles of democracy and virtue temper each other. There are  these  two

forms of aristocracy in addition to the first and perfect  state,  and there is a third form, viz., the constitutions

which  incline more  than the socalled polity towards oligarchy. 

VIII

I have yet to speak of the socalled polity and of tyranny. I put  them in this order, not because a polity or

constitutional  government  is to be regarded as a perversion any more than the above  mentioned  aristocracies.

The truth is, that they an fall short of  the most  perfect form of government, and so they are reckoned among

perversions, and the really perverted forms are perversions of  these,  as I said in the original discussion. Last

of all I will  speak of  tyranny, which I place last in the series because I am  inquiring into  the constitutions of

states, and this is the very  reverse of a  constitution 

Having explained why I have adopted this order, I will proceed to  consider constitutional government; of

which the nature will be  clearer now that oligarchy and democracy have been defined. For polity  or

constitutional government may be described generally as a fusion of  oligarchy and democracy; but the term is

usually applied to those  forms of government which incline towards democracy, and the term  aristocracy to

those which incline towards oligarchy, because birth  and education are commonly the accompaniments of

wealth. Moreover, the  rich already possess the external advantages the want of which is a  temptation to


POLITICS

VII 53



Top




Page No 58


crime, and hence they are called noblemen and gentlemen.  And inasmuch as aristocracy seeks to give

predominance to the best  of  the citizens, people say also of oligarchies that they are composed  of  noblemen

and gentlemen. Now it appears to be an impossible thing  that  the state which is governed not by the best

citizens but by the  worst  should be wellgoverned, and equally impossible that the state  which  is

illgoverned should be governed by the best. But we must  remember  that good laws, if they are not obeyed,

do not constitute  good  government. Hence there are two parts of good government; one  is the  actual

obedience of citizens to the laws, the other part is the  goodness of the laws which they obey; they may obey

bad laws as well  as good. And there may be a further subdivision; they may obey  either  the best laws which

are attainable to them, or the best  absolutely. 

The distribution of offices according to merit is a special  characteristic of aristocracy, for the principle of an

aristocracy  is  virtue, as wealth is of an oligarchy, and freedom of a democracy.  In  all of them there of course

exists the right of the majority, and  whatever seems good to the majority of those who share in the

government has authority. Now in most states the form called polity  exists, for the fusion goes no further than

the attempt to unite the  freedom of the poor and the wealth of the rich, who commonly take  the  place of the

noble. But as there are three grounds on which men  claim  an equal share in the government, freedom, wealth,

and virtue  (for the  fourth or good birth is the result of the two last, being  only ancient  wealth and virtue), it is

clear that the admixture of the  two  elements, that is to say, of the rich and poor, is to be called  a  polity or

constitutional government; and the union of the three is  to  be called aristocracy or the government of the best,

and more  than any  other form of government, except the true and ideal, has a  right to  this name. 

Thus far I have shown the existence of forms of states other than  monarchy, democracy, and oligarchy, and

what they are, and in what  aristocracies differ from one another, and polities from  aristocracies that the two

latter are not very unlike is obvious. 

IX

Next we have to consider how by the side of oligarchy and  democracy the socalled polity or constitutional

government springs  up, and how it should be organized. The nature of it will be at once  understood from a

comparison of oligarchy and democracy; we must  ascertain their different characteristics, and taking a

portion from  each, put the two together, like the parts of an indenture. Now  there  are three modes in which

fusions of government may be  affected. In the  first mode we must combine the laws made by both

governments, say  concerning the administration of justice. In  oligarchies they impose a  fine on the rich if

they do not serve as  judges, and to the poor they  give no pay; but in democracies they give  pay to the poor

and do not  fine the rich. Now (1) the union of these  two modes is a common or  middle term between them,

and is therefore  characteristic of a  constitutional government, for it is a combination  of both. This is  one

mode of uniting the two elements. Or (2) a mean  may be taken  between the enactments of the two: thus

democracies  require no  property qualification, or only a small one, from members  of the  assembly,

oligarchies a high one; here neither of these is  the common  term, but a mean between them. (3) There is a

third mode,  in which  something is borrowed from the oligarchical and something  from the  democratical

principle. For example, the appointment of  magistrates by  lot is thought to be democratical, and the election

of them  oligarchical; democratical again when there is no property  qualification, oligarchical when there is.

In the aristocratical or  constitutional state, one element will be taken from each from  oligarchy the principle

of electing to offices, from democracy the  disregard of qualification. Such are the various modes of

combination. 

There is a true union of oligarchy and democracy when the same  state  may be termed either a democracy or

an oligarchy; those who use  both  names evidently feel that the fusion is complete. Such a fusion  there  is also

in the mean; for both extremes appear in it. The  Lacedaemonian  constitution, for example, is often described

as a  democracy, because  it has many democratical features. In the first  place the youth receive  a democratical


POLITICS

IX 54



Top




Page No 59


education. For the sons of the  poor are brought up with  with the sons of the rich, who are educated  in such a

manner as to make  it possible for the sons of the poor to be  educated by them. A similar  equality prevails in

the following period  of life, and when the  citizens are grown up to manhood the same rule  is observed; there

is  no distinction between the rich and poor. In  like manner they all have  the same food at their public tables,

and  the rich wear only such  clothing as any poor man can afford. Again,  the people elect to one  of the two

greatest offices of state, and in  the other they share;  for they elect the Senators and share in the  Ephoralty. By

others the  Spartan constitution is said to be an  oligarchy, because it has many  oligarchical elements. That all

offices  are filled by election and  none by lot, is one of these oligarchical  characteristics; that the  power of

inflicting death or banishment  rests with a few persons is  another; and there are others. In a well  attempted

polity there should  appear to be both elements and yet  neither; also the government should  rely on itself, and

not on foreign  aid, and on itself not through the  good will of a majority they might  be equally welldisposed

when  there is a vicious form of government  but through the general  willingness of all classes in the state to

maintain the constitution. 

Enough of the manner in which a constitutional government, and in  which the socalled aristocracies ought

to be framed. 

X

Of the nature of tyranny I have still to speak, in order that it  may  have its place in our inquiry (since even

tyranny is reckoned by  us to  be a form of government), although there is not much to be said  about it. I have

already in the former part of this treatise discussed  royalty or kingship according to the most usual meaning

of the term,  and considered whether it is or is not advantageous to states, and  what kind of royalty should be

established, and from what source,  and  how. 

When speaking of royalty we also spoke of two forms of tyranny,  which are both according to law, and

therefore easily pass into  royalty. Among barbarians there are elected monarchs who exercise a  despotic

power; despotic rulers were also elected in ancient Hellas,  called Aesymnetes or Dictators. These monarchies,

when compared with  one another, exhibit certain differences. And they are, as I said  before, royal, in so far as

the monarch rules according to law over  willing subjects; but they are tyrannical in so far as he is  despotic

and rules according to his own fancy. There is also a third  kind of  tyranny, which is the most typical form,

and is the  counterpart of the  perfect monarchy. This tyranny is just that  arbitrary power of an  individual

which is responsible to no one, and  governs all alike,  whether equals or better, with a view to its own

advantage, not to  that of its subjects, and therefore against their  will. No freeman, if  he can escape from it,

will endure such a  government. 

The kinds of tyranny are such and so many, and for the reasons  which  I have given. 

XI

We have now to inquire what is the best constitution for most  states, and the best life for most men, neither

assuming a standard of  virtue which is above ordinary persons, nor an education which is  exceptionally

favored by nature and circumstances, nor yet an ideal  state which is an aspiration only, but having regard to

the life in  which the majority are able to share, and to the form of government  which states in general can

attain. As to those aristocracies, as they  are called, of which we were just now speaking, they either lie

beyond  the possibilities of the greater number of states, or they approximate  to the socalled constitutional

government, and therefore need no  separate discussion. And in fact the conclusion at which we arrive

respecting all these forms rests upon the same grounds. For if what  was said in the Ethics is true, that the

happy life is the life  according to virtue lived without impediment, and that virtue is a  mean, then the life

which is in a mean, and in a mean attainable by  every one, must be the best. And the same the same


POLITICS

X 55



Top




Page No 60


principles of  virtue and vice are characteristic of cities and of constitutions; for  the constitution is in a figure

the life of the city. 

Now in all states there are three elements: one class is very  rich, another very poor, and a third in a mean. It is

admitted that  moderation and the mean are best, and therefore it will clearly be  best to possess the gifts of

fortune in moderation; for in that  condition of life men are most ready to follow rational principle. But  he

who greatly excels in beauty, strength, birth, or wealth, or on the  other hand who is very poor, or very weak,

or very much disgraced,  finds it difficult to follow rational principle. Of these two the  one  sort grow into

violent and great criminals, the others into rogues  and  petty rascals. And two sorts of offenses correspond to

them, the  one  committed from violence, the other from roguery. Again, the middle  class is least likely to

shrink from rule, or to be overambitious for  it; both of which are injuries to the state. Again, those who have

too  much of the goods of fortune, strength, wealth, friends, and the like,  are neither willing nor able to submit

to authority. The evil begins  at home; for when they are boys, by reason of the luxury in which they  are

brought up, they never learn, even at school, the habit of  obedience. On the other hand, the very poor, who

are in the opposite  extreme, are too degraded. So that the one class cannot obey, and  can  only rule

despotically; the other knows not how to command and  must be  ruled like slaves. Thus arises a city, not of

freemen, but  of masters  and slaves, the one despising, the other envying; and  nothing can be  more fatal to

friendship and good fellowship in  states than this: for  good fellowship springs from friendship; when  men are

at enmity with  one another, they would rather not even share  the same path. But a  city ought to be composed,

as far as possible, of  equals and similars;  and these are generally the middle classes.  Wherefore the city which

is composed of middleclass citizens is  necessarily best constituted  in respect of the elements of which we

say the fabric of the state  naturally consists. And this is the  class of citizens which is most  secure in a state,

for they do not,  like the poor, covet their  neighbors' goods; nor do others covet  theirs, as the poor covet the

goods of the rich; and as they neither  plot against others, nor are  themselves plotted against, they pass

through life safely. Wisely then  did Phocylides pray 'Many things are  best in the mean; I desire to be  of a

middle condition in my city.' 

Thus it is manifest that the best political community is formed by  citizens of the middle class, and that those

states are likely to be  welladministered in which the middle class is large, and stronger  if  possible than both

the other classes, or at any rate than either  singly; for the addition of the middle class turns the scale, and

prevents either of the extremes from being dominant. Great then is the  good fortune of a state in which the

citizens have a moderate and  sufficient property; for where some possess much, and the others  nothing, there

may arise an extreme democracy, or a pure oligarchy; or  a tyranny may grow out of either extreme either

out of the most  rampant democracy, or out of an oligarchy; but it is not so likely  to  arise out of the middle

constitutions and those akin to them. I  will  explain the reason of this hereafter, when I speak of the

revolutions  of states. The mean condition of states is clearly best,  for no other  is free from faction; and where

the middle class is  large, there are  least likely to be factions and dissensions. For a  similar reason  large states

are less liable to faction than small  ones, because in  them the middle class is large; whereas in small  states it

is easy to  divide all the citizens into two classes who  are either rich or poor,  and to leave nothing in the

middle. And  democracies are safer and more  permanent than oligarchies, because  they have a middle class

which is  more numerous and has a greater  share in the government; for when  there is no middle class, and the

poor greatly exceed in number,  troubles arise, and the state soon  comes to an end. A proof of the  superiority

of the middle dass is that  the best legislators have been  of a middle condition; for example,  Solon, as his own

verses testify;  and Lycurgus, for he was not a king;  and Charondas, and almost all  legislators. 

These considerations will help us to understand why most  governments  are either democratical or

oligarchical. The reason is  that the middle  class is seldom numerous in them, and whichever party,  whether

the  rich or the common people, transgresses the mean and  predominates,  draws the constitution its own way,

and thus arises  either oligarchy  or democracy. There is another reason the poor and  the rich quarrel  with one

another, and whichever side gets the better,  instead of  establishing a just or popular government, regards

political supremacy  as the prize of victory, and the one party sets up  a democracy and the  other an oligarchy.


POLITICS

X 56



Top




Page No 61


Further, both the parties  which had the  supremacy in Hellas looked only to the interest of their  own form of

government, and established in states, the one,  democracies, and the  other, oligarchies; they thought of their

own  advantage, of the public  not at all. For these reasons the middle form  of government has  rarely, if ever,

existed, and among a very few only.  One man alone  of all who ever ruled in Hellas was induced to give this

middle  constitution to states. But it has now become a habit among the  citizens of states, not even to care

about equality; all men are  seeking for dominion, or, if conquered, are willing to submit. 

What then is the best form of government, and what makes it the  best, is evident; and of other constitutions,

since we say that  there  are many kinds of democracy and many of oligarchy, it is not  difficult  to see which

has the first and which the second or any other  place in  the order of excellence, now that we have determined

which is  the  best. For that which is nearest to the best must of necessity be  better, and that which is furthest

from it worse, if we are judging  absolutely and not relatively to given conditions: I say 'relatively  to given

conditions,' since a particular government may be preferable,  but another form may be better for some

people. 

XII

We have now to consider what and what kind of government is  suitable  to what and what kind of men. I may

begin by assuming, as a  general  principle common to all governments, that the portion of the  state  which

desires the permanence of the constitution ought to be  stronger than that which desires the reverse. Now

every city is  composed of quality and quantity. By quality I mean freedom, wealth,  education, good birth, and

by quantity, superiority of numbers.  Quality may exist in one of the classes which make up the state, and

quantity in the other. For example, the meanlyborn may be more in  number than the wellborn, or the poor

than the rich, yet they may not  so much exceed in quantity as they fall short in quality; and  therefore there

must be a comparison of quantity and quality. Where  the number of the poor is more than proportioned to the

wealth of  the  rich, there will naturally be a democracy, varying in form with  the  sort of people who compose

it in each case. If, for example, the  husbandmen exceed in number, the first form of democracy will then

arise; if the artisans and laboring class, the last; and so with the  intermediate forms. But where the rich and

the notables exceed in  quality more than they fall short in quantity, there oligarchy arises,  similarly assuming

various forms according to the kind of  superiority  possessed by the oligarchs. 

The legislator should always include the middle class in his  government; if he makes his laws oligarchical, to

the middle class let  him look; if he makes them democratical, he should equally by his laws  try to attach this

class to the state. There only can the government  ever be stable where the middle class exceeds one or both of

the  others, and in that case there will be no fear that the rich will  unite with the poor against the rulers. For

neither of them will  ever  be willing to serve the other, and if they look for some form  of  government more

suitable to both, they will find none better than  this, for the rich and the poor will never consent to rule in

turn,  because they mistrust one another. The arbiter is always the one  trusted, and he who is in the middle is

an arbiter. The more perfect  the admixture of the political elements, the more lasting will be  the  constitution.

Many even of those who desire to form aristocratical  governments make a mistake, not only in giving too

much power to the  rich, but in attempting to overreach the people. There comes a time  when out of a false

good there arises a true evil, since the  encroachments of the rich are more destructive to the constitution  than

those of the people. 

XIII

The devices by which oligarchies deceive the people are five in  number; they relate to (1) the assembly; (2)

the magistracies; (3) the  courts of law; (4) the use of arms; (5) gymnastic exercises. (1) The  assemblies are

thrown open to all, but either the rich only are  fined  for nonattendance, or a much larger fine is inflicted

upon  them. (2)  to the magistracies, those who are qualified by property  cannot  decline office upon oath, but


POLITICS

XII 57



Top




Page No 62


the poor may. (3) In the law  courts the  rich, and the rich only, are fined if they do not serve,  the poor are  let

off with impunity, or, as in the laws of Charondas, a  larger fine  is inflicted on the rich, and a smaller one on

the poor.  In some  states all citizen who have registered themselves are  allowed to  attend the assembly and to

try causes; but if after  registration they  do not attend either in the assembly or at the  courts, heavy fines are

imposed upon them. The intention is that  through fear of the fines  they may avoid registering themselves, and

then they cannot sit in the  lawcourts or in the assembly.  concerning (4) the possession of arms,  and (5)

gymnastic exercises,  they legislate in a similar spirit. For  the poor are not obliged to  have arms, but the rich

are fined for not  having them; and in like  manner no penalty is inflicted on the poor  for nonattendance at the

gymnasium, and consequently, having nothing  to fear, they do not  attend, whereas the rich are liable to a fine,

and therefore they take  care to attend. 

These are the devices of oligarchical legislators, and in  democracies they have counter devices. They pay the

poor for attending  the assemblies and the lawcourts, and they inflict no penalty on  the  rich for

nonattendance. It is obvious that he who would duly  mix the  two principles should combine the practice of

both, and  provide that  the poor should be paid to attend, and the rich fined  if they do not  attend, for then all

will take part; if there is no  such combination,  power will be in the hands of one party only. The  government

should be  confined to those who carry arms. As to the  property qualification, no  absolute rule can be laid

down, but we must  see what is the highest  qualification sufficiently comprehensive to  secure that the number

of  those who have the rights of citizens  exceeds the number of those  excluded. Even if they have no share in

office, the poor, provided  only that they are not outraged or deprived  of their property, will be  quiet enough. 

But to secure gentle treatment for the poor is not an easy thing,  since a ruling class is not always humane.

And in time of war the poor  are apt to hesitate unless they are fed; when fed, they are willing  enough to fight.

In some states the government is vested, not only  in  those who are actually serving, but also in those who

have  served;  among the Malians, for example, the governing body consisted  of the  latter, while the

magistrates were chosen from those actually  on  service. And the earliest government which existed among

the  Hellenes,  after the overthrow of the kingly power, grew up out of  the warrior  class, and was originally

taken from the knights (for  strength and  superiority in war at that time depended on cavalry;  indeed, without

discipline, infantry are useless, and in ancient times  there was no  military knowledge or tactics, and therefore

the strength  of armies  lay in their cavalry). But when cities increased and the  heavy armed  grew in strength,

more had a share in the government;  and this is the  reason why the states which we call constitutional

governments have  been hitherto called democracies. Ancient  constitutions, as might be  expected, were

oligarchical and royal;  their population being small  they had no considerable middle class;  the people were

weak in numbers  and organization, and were therefore  more contented to be governed. 

I have explained why there are various forms of government, and  why there are more than is generally

supposed; for democracy, as  well  as other constitutions, has more than one form: also what their  differences

are, and whence they arise, and what is the best form of  government, speaking generally and to whom the

various forms of  government are best suited; all this has now been explained. 

XIV

Having thus gained an appropriate basis of discussion, we will  proceed to speak of the points which follow

next in order. We will  consider the subject not only in general but with reference to  particular constitutions.

All constitutions have three elements,  concerning which the good lawgiver has to regard what is expedient for

each constitution. When they are wellordered, the constitution is  wellordered, and as they differ from one

another, constitutions  differ. There is (1) one element which deliberates about public  affairs; secondly (2) that

concerned with the magistrates the  question being, what they should be, over what they should exercise

authority, and what should be the mode of electing to them; and  thirdly (3) that which has judicial power. 


POLITICS

XIV 58



Top




Page No 63


The deliberative element has authority in matters of war and  peace, in making and unmaking alliances; it

passes laws, inflicts  death, exile, confiscation, elects magistrates and audits their  accounts. These powers

must be assigned either all to all the citizens  or an to some of them (for example, to one or more magistracies,

or  different causes to different magistracies), or some of them to all,  and others of them only to some. That all

things should be decided  by  all is characteristic of democracy; this is the sort of equality  which  the people

desire. But there are various ways in which all may  share  in the government; they may deliberate, not all in

one body, but  by  turns, as in the constitution of Telecles the Milesian. There are  other constitutions in which

the boards of magistrates meet and  deliberate, but come into office by turns, and are elected out of  the  tribes

and the very smallest divisions of the state, until every  one  has obtained office in his turn. The citizens, on the

other  hand, are  assembled only for the purposes of legislation, and to  consult about  the constitution, and to

hear the edicts of the  magistrates. In  another variety of democracy the citizen form one  assembly, but meet

only to elect magistrates, to pass laws, to  advise about war and  peace, and to make scrutinies. Other matters

are referred severally to  special magistrates, who are elected by vote  or by lot out of all the  citizens Or again,

the citizens meet about  election to offices and  about scrutinies, and deliberate concerning  war or alliances

while  other matters are administered by the  magistrates, who, as far as is  possible, are elected by vote. I am

speaking of those magistracies in  which special knowledge is required.  A fourth form of democracy is  when

all the citizens meet to deliberate  about everything, and the  magistrates decide nothing, but only make  the

preliminary inquiries;  and that is the way in which the last and  worst form of democracy,  corresponding, as

we maintain, to the close  family oligarchy and to  tyranny, is at present administered. All these  modes are

democratical. 

On the other hand, that some should deliberate about all is  oligarchical. This again is a mode which, like the

democratical has  many forms. When the deliberative class being elected out of those who  have a moderate

qualification are numerous and they respect and obey  the prohibitions of the law without altering it, and any

one who has  the required qualification shares in the government, then, just  because of this moderation, the

oligarchy inclines towards polity. But  when only selected individuals and not the whole people share in the

deliberations of the state, then, although, as in the former case,  they observe the law, the government is a pure

oligarchy. Or, again,  when those who have the power of deliberation are selfelected, and  son succeeds

father, and they and not the laws are supreme the  government is of necessity oligarchical. Where, again,

particular  persons have authority in particular matters for example, when the  whole people decide about

peace and war and hold scrutinies, but the  magistrates regulate everything else, and they are elected by vote

there the government is an aristocracy. And if some questions are  decided by magistrates elected by vote, and

others by magistrates  elected by lot, either absolutely or out of select candidates, or  elected partly by vote,

partly by lot these practices are partly  characteristic of an aristocratical government, and party of a pure

constitutional government. 

These are the various forms of the deliberative body; they  correspond to the various forms of government.

And the government of  each state is administered according to one or other of the principles  which have been

laid down. Now it is for the interest of democracy,  according to the most prevalent notion of it (I am speaking

of that  extreme form of democracy in which the people are supreme even over  the laws), with a view to better

deliberation to adopt the custom of  oligarchies respecting courts of law. For in oligarchies the rich  who  are

wanted to be judges are compelled to attend under pain of a  fine,  whereas in deinocracies the poor are paid to

attend. And this  practice  of oligarchies should be adopted by democracies in their  public  assemblies, for they

will advise better if they all  deliberate  together the people with the notables and the notables  with the

people. It is also a good plan that those who deliberate  should be  elected by vote or by lot in equal numbers

out of the  different  classes; and that if the people greatly exceed in number  those who  have political training,

pay should not be given to all, but  only to  as many as would balance the number of the notables, or that  the

number in excess should be eliminated by lot. But in oligarchies  either certain persons should be coopted

from the mass, or a class of  officers should be appointed such as exist in some states who are  termed probuli

and guardians of the law; and the citizens should  occupy themselves exclusively with matters on which these

have  previously deliberated; for so the people will have a share in the  deliberations of the state, but will not


POLITICS

XIV 59



Top




Page No 64


be able to disturb the  principles of the constitution. Again, in oligarchies either the  people ought to accept the

measures of the government, or not to  pass  anything contrary to them; or, if all are allowed to share in

counsel,  the decision should rest with the magistrates. The opposite  of what is  done in constitutional

governments should be the rule in  oligarchies;  the veto of the majority should be final, their assent  not final,

but  the proposal should be referred back to the  magistrates. Whereas in  constitutional governments they take

the  contrary course; the few have  the negative, not the affirmative power;  the affirmation of everything  rests

with the multitude. 

These, then, are our conclusions respecting the deliberative, that  is, the supreme element in states. 

XV

Next we will proceed to consider the distribution of offices; this  too, being a part of politics concerning which

many questions arise:  What shall their number be? Over what shall they preside, and what  shall be their

duration? Sometimes they last for six months, sometimes  for less; sometimes they are annual, while in other

cases offices  are  held for still longer periods. Shall they be for life or for a  long  term of years; or, if for a short

term only, shall the same  persons  hold them over and over again, or once only? Also about the  appointment

to them from whom are they to be chosen, by whom, and  how? We should first be in a position to say what

are the possible  varieties of them, and then we may proceed to determine which are  suited to different forms

of government. But what are to be included  under the term 'offices'? That is a question not quite so easily

answered. For a political community requires many officers; and not  every one who is chosen by vote or by

lot is to be regarded as a  ruler. In the first place there are the priests, who must be  distinguished from political

officers; masters of choruses and  heralds, even ambassadors, are elected by vote. Some duties of

superintendence again are political, extending either to all the  citizens in a single sphere of action, like the

office of the  general  who superintends them when they are in the field, or to a  section of  them only, like the

inspectorships of women or of youth.  Other offices  are concerned with household management, like that of

the corn  measurers who exist in many states and are elected  officers. There are  also menial offices which the

rich have executed  by their slaves.  Speaking generally, those are to be called offices to  which the duties  are

assigned of deliberating about certain measures  and ofjudging and  commanding, especially the last; for to

command is  the especial duty  of a magistrate. But the question is not of any  importance in  practice; no one

has ever brought into court the meaning  of the word,  although such problems have a speculative interest. 

What kinds of offices, and how many, are necessary to the  existence of a state, and which, if not necessary,

yet conduce to  its  well being are much more important considerations, affecting all  constitutions, but more

especially small states. For in great states  it is possible, and indeed necessary, that every office should have  a

special function; where the citizens are numerous, many may hold  office. And so it happens that some offices

a man holds a second  time  only after a long interval, and others he holds once only; and  certainly every work

is better done which receives the sole, and not  the divided attention of the worker. But in small states it is

necessary to combine many offices in a few hands, since the small  number of citizens does not admit of many

holding office: for who will  there be to succeed them? And yet small states at times require the  same offices

and laws as large ones; the difference is that the one  want them often, the others only after long intervals.

Hence there  is  no reason why the care of many offices should not be imposed on the  same person, for they

will not interfere with each other. When the  population is small, offices should be like the spits which also

serve  to hold a lamp. We must first ascertain how many magistrates are  necessary in every state, and also

how many are not exactly necessary,  but are nevertheless useful, and then there will be no difficulty in  seeing

what offices can be combined in one. We should also know over  which matters several local tribunals are to

have jurisdiction, and in  which authority should be centralized: for example, should one  person  keep order in

the market and another in some other place, or  should  the same person be responsible everywhere? Again,

should  offices be  divided according to the subjects with which they deal,  or according  to the persons with

whom they deal: I mean to say, should  one person  see to good order in general, or one look after the boys,


POLITICS

XV 60



Top




Page No 65


another  after the women, and so on? Further, under different  constitutions,  should the magistrates be the same

or different? For  example, in  democracy, oligarchy, aristocracy, monarchy, should  there be the same

magistrates, although they are elected, not out of  equal or similar  classes of citizen but differently under

different  constitutions in  aristocracies, for example, they are chosen from the  educated, in  oligarchies from

the wealthy, and in democracies from the  free or are  there certain differences in the offices answering to

them as well,  and may the same be suitable to some, but different  offices to others?  For in some states it may

be convenient that the  same office should  have a more extensive, in other states a narrower  sphere. Special

offices are peculiar to certain forms of government:  for example that  of probuli, which is not a democratic

office,  although a bule or  council is. There must be some body of men whose  duty is to prepare  measures for

the people in order that they may  not be diverted from  their business; when these are few in number, the  state

inclines to an  oligarchy: or rather the probuli must always be  few, and are therefore  an oligarchical element.

But when both  institutions exist in a state,  the probuli are a check on the council;  for the counselors is a

democratic element, but the probuli are  oligarchical. Even the power  of the council disappears when

democracy has taken that extreme form  in which the people themselves  are always meeting and deliberating

about everything. This is the case  when the members of the assembly  receive abundant pay; for they have

nothing to do and are always  holding assemblies and deciding  everything for themselves. A  magistracy which

controls the boys or the  women, or any similar  office, is suited to an aristocracy rather  than to a democracy;

for  how can the magistrates prevent the wives  of the poor from going out  of doors? Neither is it an

oligarchical  office; for the wives of the  oligarchs are too fine to be controlled. 

Enough of these matters. I will now inquire into appointments to  offices. The varieties depend on three terms,

and the combinations  of  these give all possible modes: first, who appoints? secondly,  from  whom? and

thirdly, how? Each of these three admits of three  varieties:  (A) All the citizens, or (B) only some, appoint.

Either (1)  the  magistrates are chosen out of all or (2) out of some who are  distinguished either by a property

qualification, or by birth, or  merit, or for some special reason, as at Megara only those were  eligible who had

returned from exile and fought together against the  democracy. They may be appointed either (a) by vote or

(b) by lot.  Again, these several varieties may be coupled, I mean that (C) some  officers may be elected by

some, others by all, and (3) some again out  of some, and others out of all, and (c) some by vote and others by

lot. Each variety of these terms admits of four modes. 

For either (A 1 a) all may appoint from all by vote, or (A 1 b)  all from all by lot, or (A 2 a) all from some by

vote, or (A 2 b)  all  from some by lot (and from all, either by sections, as, for  example,  by tribes, and wards,

and phratries, until all the citizens  have been  gone through; or the citizens may be in all cases eligible

indiscriminately); or again (A 1 c, A 2 c) to some offices in the  one  way, to some in the other. Again, if it is

only some that appoint,  they may do so either (B 1 a) from all by vote, or (B 1 b) from all by  lot, or (B 2 a)

from some by vote, or (B 2 b) from some by lot, or  to  some offices in the one way, to others in the other, i.e.,

(B 1  c)  from all, to some offices by vote, to some by lot, and (B 2 C) from  some, to some offices by vote, to

some by lot. Thus the modes that  arise, apart from two (C, 3) out of the three couplings, number  twelve. Of

these systems two are popular, that all should appoint from  all (A 1 a) by vote or (A 1 b) by lot or (A 1 c) by

both. That all  should not appoint at once, but should appoint from all or from some  either by lot or by vote or

by both, or appoint to some offices from  all and to others from some ('by both' meaning to some offices by

lot,  to others by vote), is characteristic of a polity. And (B 1 c) that  some should appoint from all, to some

offices by vote, to others by  lot, is also characteristic of a polity, but more oligarchical than  the former

method. And (A 3 a, b, c, B 3 a, b, c) to appoint from  both, to some offices from all, to others from some, is

characteristic  of a polity with a leaning towards aristocracy. That (B 2) some should  appoint from some is

oligarchical even (B 2 b) that some should  appoint from some by lot (and if this does not actually occur, it is

none the less oligarchical in character), or (B 2 C) that some  should  appoint from some by both. (B 1 a) that

some should appoint  from all,  and (A 2 a) that all should appoint from some, by vote, is  aristocratic. 

These are the different modes of constituting magistrates, and  these  correspond to different forms of

government: which are proper to  which, or how they ought to be established, will be evident when we


POLITICS

XV 61



Top




Page No 66


determine the nature of their powers. By powers I mean such powers  as  a magistrate exercises over the

revenue or in defense of the  country;  for there are various kinds of power: the power of the  general, for

example, is not the same with that which regulates  contracts in the  market. 

XVI

Of the three parts of government, the judicial remains to be  considered, and this we shall divide on the same

principle. There  are  three points on which the variedes of lawcourts depend: The  persons  from whom they

are appointed, the matters with which they  are  concerned, and the manner of their appointment. I mean, (1)

are  the  judges taken from all, or from some only? (2) how many kinds of  lawcourts are there? (3) are the

judges chosen by vote or by lot? 

First, let me determine how many kinds of lawcourts there are.  There are eight in number: One is the court

of audits or scrutinies; a  second takes cognizance of ordinary offenses against the state; a  third is concerned

with treason against the constitution; the fourth  determines disputes respecting penalties, whether raised by

magistrates  or by private persons; the fifth decides the more  important civil  cases; the sixth tries cases of

homicide, which are of  various kinds,  (a) premeditated, (b) involuntary, (c) cases in which  the guilt is

confessed but the justice is disputed; and there may be a  fourth court  (d) in which murderers who have fled

from justice are  tried after  their return; such as the Court of Phreatto is said to be  at Athens.  But cases of this

sort rarely happen at all even in large  cities.  The different kinds of homicide may be tried either by the  same

or  by different courts. (7) There are courts for strangers: of  these  there are two subdivisions, (a) for the

settlement of their  disputes  with one another, (b) for the settlement of disputes between  them and  the citizens.

And besides all these there must be (8) courts  for small  suits about sums of a drachma up to five drachmas, or

a  little more,  which have to be determined, but they do not require many  judges. 

Nothing more need be said of these small suits, nor of the courts  for homicide and for strangers: I would

rather speak of political  cases, which, when mismanaged, create division and disturbances in  constitutions. 

Now if all the citizens judge, in all the different cases which I  have distinguished, they may be appointed by

vote or by lot, or  sometimes by lot and sometimes by vote. Or when a single class of  causes are tried, the

judges who decide them may be appointed, some by  vote, and some by lot. These then are the four modes of

appointing  judges from the whole people, and there will be likewise four modes,  if they are elected from a

part only; for they may be appointed from  some by vote and judge in all causes; or they may be appointed

from  some by lot and judge in all causes; or they may be elected in some  cases by vote, and in some cases

taken by lot, or some courts, even  when judging the same causes, may be composed of members some

appointed by vote and some by lot. These modes, then, as was said,  answer to those previously mentioned. 

Once more, the modes of appointment may be combined; I mean, that  some may be chosen out of the whole

people, others out of some, some  out of both; for example, the same tribunal may be composed of some  who

were elected out of all, and of others who were elected out of  some, either by vote or by lot or by both. 

In how many forms lawcourts can be established has now been  considered. The first form, viz., that in

which the judges are taken  from all the citizens, and in which all causes are tried, is  democratical; the second,

which is composed of a few only who try  all  causes, oligarchical; the third, in which some courts are taken

from  all classes, and some from certain classes only, aristocratical  and  constitutional. 

BOOK FIVE


POLITICS

XVI 62



Top




Page No 67


I

THE DESIGN which we proposed to ourselves is now nearly completed.  Next in order follow the causes of

revolution in states, how many, and  of what nature they are; what modes of destruction apply to particular

states, and out of what, and into what they mostly change; also what  are the modes of preservation in states

generally, or in a  particular  state, and by what means each state may be best  preserved: these  questions

remain to be considered. 

In the first place we must assume as our startingpoint that in  the many forms of government which have

sprung up there has always  been an acknowledgment of justice and proportionate equality, although  mankind

fail attaining them, as I have already explained. Democracy,  for example, arises out of the notion that those

who are equal in  any  respect are equal in all respects; because men are equally free,  they  claim to be

absolutely equal. Oligarchy is based on the notion  that  those who are unequal in one respect are in all respects

unequal;  being unequal, that is, in property, they suppose themselves to be  unequal absolutely. The democrats

think that as they are equal they  ought to be equal in all things; while the oligarchs, under the idea  that they

are unequal, claim too much, which is one form of  inequality. All these forms of government have a kind of

justice, but,  tried by an absolute standard, they are faulty; and, therefore, both  parties, whenever their share in

the government does not accord with  their preconceived ideas, stir up revolution. Those who excel in  virtue

have the best right of all to rebel (for they alone can with  reason be deemed absolutely unequal), but then they

are of all men the  least inclined to do so. There is also a superiority which is  claimed  by men of rank; for they

are thought noble because they spring  from  wealthy and virtuous ancestors. Here then, so to speak, are

opened the  very springs and fountains of revolution; and hence arise  two sorts of  changes in governments; the

one affecting the  constitution, when men  seek to change from an existing form into  some other, for example,

from democracy into oligarchy, and from  oligarchy into democracy, or  from either of them into constitutional

government or aristocracy, and  conversely; the other not affecting the  constitution, when, without  disturbing

the form of government, whether  oligarchy, or monarchy, or  any other, they try to get the  administration into

their own hands.  Further, there is a question of  degree; an oligarchy, for example, may  become more or less

oligarchical, and a democracy more or less  democratical; and in like  manner the characteristics of the other

forms of government may be  more or less strictly maintained. Or the  revolution may be directed  against a

portion of the constitution only,  e.g., the establishment or  overthrow of a particular office: as at  Sparta it is

said that  Lysander attempted to overthrow the monarchy,  and King Pausanias,  the Ephoralty. At Epidamnus,

too, the change was  partial. For  instead of phylarchs or heads of tribes, a council was  appointed;  but to this

day the magistrates are the only members of the  ruling  class who are compelled to go to the Heliaea when an

election  takes  place, and the office of the single archon was another  oligarchical  feature. Everywhere

inequality is a cause of revolution,  but an  inequality in which there is no proportion for instance, a  perpetual

monarchy among equals; and always it is the desire of  equality which rises in rebellion. 

Now equality is of two kinds, numerical and proportional; by the  first I mean sameness or equality in number

or size; by the second,  equality of ratios. For example, the excess of three over two is  numerically equal to the

excess of two over one; whereas four  exceeds  two in the same ratio in which two exceeds one, for two is the

same  part of four that one is of two, namely, the half. As I was  saying  before, men agree that justice in the

abstract is proportion,  but they  differ in that some think that if they are equal in any  respect they  are equal

absolutely, others that if they are unequal  in any respect  they should be unequal in all. Hence there are two

principal forms of  government, democracy and oligarchy; for good birth  and virtue are  rare, but wealth and

numbers are more common. In what  city shall we  find a hundred persons of good birth and of virtue?  whereas

the rich  everywhere abound. That a state should be ordered,  simply and wholly,  according to either kind of

equality, is not a good  thing; the proof  is the fact that such forms of government never last.  They are

originally based on a mistake, and, as they begin badly,  cannot fall  to end badly. The inference is that both

kinds of equality  should be  employed; numerical in some cases, and proportionate in  others. 


POLITICS

I 63



Top




Page No 68


Still democracy appears to be safer and less liable to revolution  than oligarchy. For in oligarchies there is the

double danger of the  oligarchs falling out among themselves and also with the people; but  in democracies

there is only the danger of a quarrel with the  oligarchs. No dissension worth mentioning arises among the

people  themselves. And we may further remark that a government which is  composed of the middle class

more nearly approximates to democracy  than to oligarchy, and is the safest of the imperfect forms of

government. 

II

In considering how dissensions and poltical revolutions arise, we  must first of all ascertain the beginnings

and causes of them which  affect constitutions generally. They may be said to be three in  number; and we

have now to give an outline of each. We want to know  (1) what is the feeling? (2) what are the motives of

those who make  them? (3) whence arise political disturbances and quarrels? The  universal and chief cause of

this revolutionary feeling has been  already mentioned; viz., the desire of equality, when men think that  they

are equal to others who have more than themselves; or, again, the  desire of inequality and superiority, when

conceiving themselves to be  superior they think that they have not more but the same or less  than  their

inferiors; pretensions which may and may not be just.  Inferiors  revolt in order that they may be equal, and

equals that they  may be  superior. Such is the state of mind which creates  revolutions. The  motives for making

them are the desire of gain and  honor, or the fear  of dishonor and loss; the authors of them want to  divert

punishment or  dishonor from themselves or their friends. The  causes and reasons of  revolutions, whereby

men are themselves affected  in the way described,  and about the things which I have mentioned,  viewed in

one way may be  regarded as seven, and in another as more  than seven. Two of them have  been already

noticed; but they act in a  different manner, for men are  excited against one another by the  love of gain and

honor not, as in  the case which I have just  supposed, in order to obtain them for  themselves, but at seeing

others, justly or unjustly, engrossing them.  Other causes are  insolence, fear, excessive predominance,

contempt,  disproportionate  increase in some part of the state; causes of another  sort are  election intrigues,

carelessness, neglect about trifles,  dissimilarity  of elements. 

III

What share insolence and avarice have in creating revolutions, and  how they work, is plain enough. When the

magistrates are insolent  and  grasping they conspire against one another and also against the  constitution from

which they derive their power, making their gains  either at the expense of individuals or of the public. It is

evident,  again, what an influence honor exerts and how it is a cause  of  revolution. Men who are themselves

dishonored and who see others  obtaining honors rise in rebellion; the honor or dishonor when  undeserved is

unjust; and just when awarded according to merit. 

Again, superiority is a cause of revolution when one or more  persons  have a power which is too much for the

state and the power of  the  government; this is a condition of affairs out of which there  arises a  monarchy, or a

family oligarchy. And therefore, in some  places, as  at Athens and Argos, they have recourse to ostracism. But

how much  better to provide from the first that there should be no such  preeminent individuals instead of

letting them come into existence  and then finding a remedy. 

Another cause of revolution is fear. Either men have committed  wrong, and are afraid of punishment, or they

are expecting to suffer  wrong and are desirous of anticipating their enemy. Thus at Rhodes the  notables

conspired against the people through fear of the suits that  were brought against them. Contempt is also a

cause of insurrection  and revolution; for example, in oligarchies when those who have no  share in the state

are the majority, they revolt, because they think  that they are the stronger. Or, again, in democracies, the rich

despise the disorder and anarchy of the state; at Thebes, for example,  where, after the battle of Oenophyta,

the bad administration of the  democracy led to its ruin. At Megara the fall of the democracy was due  to a


POLITICS

II 64



Top




Page No 69


defeat occasioned by disorder and anarchy. And at Syracuse the  democracy aroused contempt before the

tyranny of Gelo arose; at  Rhodes, before the insurrection. 

Political revolutions also spring from a disproportionate increase  in any part of the state. For as a body is

made up of many members,  and every member ought to grow in proportion, that symmetry may be  preserved;

but loses its nature if the foot be four cubits long and  the rest of the body two spans; and, should the abnormal

increase be  one of quality as well as of quantity, may even take the form of  another animal: even so a state

has many parts, of which some one  may  often grow imperceptibly; for example, the number of poor in

democracies and in constitutional states. And this disproportion may  sometimes happen by an accident, as at

Tarentum, from a defeat in  which many of the notables were slain in a battle with the Iapygians  just after the

Persian War, the constitutional government in  consequence becoming a democracy; or as was the case at

Argos, where  the Argives, after their army had been cut to pieces on the seventh  day of the month by

Cleomenes the Lacedaemonian, were compelled to  admit to citizen some of their Perioeci; and at Athens,

when, after  frequent defeats of their infantry at the time of the Peloponnesian  War, the notables were reduced

in number, because the soldiers had  to  be taken from the roll of citizens. Revolutions arise from this  cause  as

well, in democracies as in other forms of government, but not  to so  great an extent. When the rich grow

numerous or properties  increase,  the form of government changes into an oligarchy or a  government of

families. Forms of government also change sometimes  even without  revolution, owing to election contests,

as at Heraea  (where, instead  of electing their magistrates, they took them by  lot, because the  electors were in

the habit of choosing their own  partisans); or owing  to carelessness, when disloyal persons are  allowed to

find their way  into the highest offices, as at Oreum,  where, upon the accession of  Heracleodorus to office, the

oligarchy  was overthrown, and changed by  him into a constitutional and  democratical government. 

Again, the revolution may be facilitated by the slightness of the  change; I mean that a great change may

sometimes slip into the  constitution through neglect of a small matter; at Ambracia, for  instance, the

qualification for office, small at first, was eventually  reduced to nothing. For the Ambraciots thought that a

small  qualification was much the same as none at all. 

Another cause of revolution is difference of races which do not at  once acquire a common spirit; for a state is

not the growth of a  day,  any more than it grows out of a multitude brought together by  accident. Hence the

reception of strangers in colonies, either at  the  time of their foundation or afterwards, has generally produced

revolution; for example, the Achaeans who joined the Troezenians in  the foundation of Sybaris, becoming

later the more numerous,  expelled  them; hence the curse fell upon Sybaris. At Thurii the  Sybarites  quarrelled

with their fellowcolonists; thinking that the  land  belonged to them, they wanted too much of it and were

driven out.  At  Byzantium the new colonists were detected in a conspiracy, and were  expelled by force of

arms; the people of Antissa, who had received the  Chian exiles, fought with them, and drove them out; and

the Zancleans,  after having received the Samians, were driven by them out of their  own city. The citizens of

Apollonia on the Euxine, after the  introduction of a fresh body of colonists, had a revolution; the  Syracusans,

after the expulsion of their tyrants, having admitted  strangers and mercenaries to the rights of citizenship,

quarrelled and  came to blows; the people of Amphipolis, having received Chalcidian  colonists, were nearly

all expelled by them. 

Now, in oligarchies the masses make revolution under the idea that  they are unjustly treated, because, as I

said before, they are equals,  and have not an equal share, and in democracies the notables revolt,  because they

are not equals, and yet have only an equal share. 

Again, the situation of cities is a cause of revolution when the  country is not naturally adapted to preserve the

unity of the state.  For example, the Chytians at Clazomenae did not agree with the  people  of the island; and

the people of Colophon quarrelled with the  Notians;  at Athens too, the inhabitants of the Piraeus are more

democratic than  those who live in the city. For just as in war the  impediment of a  ditch, though ever so small,

may break a regiment,  so every cause of  difference, however slight, makes a breach in a  city. The greatest


POLITICS

II 65



Top




Page No 70


opposition is confessedly that of virtue and  vice; next comes that of  wealth and poverty; and there are other

antagonistic elements, greater  or less, of which one is this  difference of place. 

IV

In revolutions the occasions may be trifling, but great interests  are at stake. Even trifles are most important

when they concern the  rulers, as was the case of old at Syracuse; for the Syracusan  constitution was once

changed by a lovequarrel of two young men,  who  were in the government. The story is that while one of

them was  away  from home his beloved was gained over by his companion, and he to  revenge himself

seduced the other's wife. They then drew the members  of the ruling class into their quarrel and so split all the

people  into portions. We learn from this story that we should be on our guard  against the beginnings of such

evils, and should put an end to the  quarrels of chiefs and mighty men. The mistake lies in the  beginning  as

the proverb says 'Well begun is half done'; so an error  at the  beginning, though quite small, bears the same

ratio to the  errors in  the other parts. In general, when the notables quarrel,  the whole city  is involved, as

happened in Hesdaea after the Persian  War. The  occasion was the division of an inheritance; one of two

brothers  refused to give an account of their father's property and the  treasure  which he had found: so the

poorer of the two quarrelled  with him and  enlisted in his cause the popular party, the other, who  was very

rich,  the wealthy classes. 

At Delphi, again, a quarrel about a marriage was the beginning of  all the troubles which followed. In this case

the bridegroom, fancying  some occurrence to be of evil omen, came to the bride, and went away  without

taking her. Whereupon her relations, thinking that they were  insulted by him, put some of the sacred treasure

among his offerings  while he was sacrificing, and then slew him, pretending that he had  been robbing the

temple. At Mytilene, too, a dispute about heiresses  was the beginning of many misfortunes, and led to the war

with the  Athenians in which Paches took their city. A wealthy citizen, named  Timophanes, left two

daughters; Dexander, another citizen, wanted to  obtain them for his sons; but he was rejected in his suit,

whereupon  he stirred up a revolution, and instigated the Athenians (of whom he  was proxenus) to interfere. A

similar quarrel about an heiress arose  at Phocis between Mnaseas the father of Mnason, and Euthycrates the

father of Onomarchus; this was the beginning of the Sacred War. A  marriagequarrel was also the cause of a

change in the government of  Epidamnus. A certain man betrothed his daughter to a person whose  father,

having been made a magistrate, fined the father of the girl,  and the latter, stung by the insult, conspired with

the unenfranchised  classes to overthrow the state. 

Governments also change into oligarchy or into democracy or into a  constitutional government because the

magistrates, or some other  section of the state, increase in power or renown. Thus at Athens  the  reputation

gained by the court of the Areopagus, in the Persian  War,  seemed to tighten the reins of government. On the

other hand, the  victory of Salamis, which was gained by the common people who served  in the fleet, and won

for the Athenians the empire due to command of  the sea, strengthened the democracy. At Argos, the notables,

having  distinguished themselves against the Lacedaemonians in the battle of  Mantinea, attempted to put

down the democracy. At Syracuse, the  people, having been the chief authors of the victory in the war with  the

Athenians, changed the constitutional government into democracy.  At Chalcis, the people, uniting with the

notables, killed Phoxus the  tyrant, and then seized the government. At Ambracia, the people, in  like manner,

having joined with the conspirators in expelling the  tyrant Periander, transferred the government to

themselves. And  generally it should be remembered that those who have secured power to  the state, whether

private citizens, or magistrates, or tribes, or any  other part or section of the state, are apt to cause revolutions.

For  either envy of their greatness draws others into rebellion, or  they  themselves, in their pride of superiority,

are unwilling to  remain on  a level with others. 

Revolutions also break out when opposite parties, e.g., the rich  and  the people, are equally balanced, and

there is little or no middle  class; for, if either party were manifestly superior, the other  would  not risk an


POLITICS

IV 66



Top




Page No 71


attack upon them. And, for this reason, those who  are  eminent in virtue usually do not stir up insurrections,

always  being a  minority. Such are the beginnings and causes of the  disturbances and  revolutions to which

every form of government is  liable. 

Revolutions are effected in two ways, by force and by fraud. Force  may be applied either at the time of

making the revolution or  afterwards. Fraud, again, is of two kinds; for (1) sometimes the  citizens are deceived

into acquiescing in a change of government,  and  afterwards they are held in subjection against their will. This

was  what happened in the case of the Four Hundred, who deceived the  people  by telling them that the king

would provide money for the war  against  the Lacedaemonians, and, having cheated the people, still

endeavored  to retain the government. (2) In other cases the people are  persuaded  at first, and afterwards, by a

repetition of the persuasion,  their  goodwill and allegiance are retained. The revolutions which  effect

constitutions generally spring from the abovementioned causes. 

V

And now, taking each constitution separately, we must see what  follows from the principles already laid

down. 

Revolutions in democracies are generally caused by the  intemperance of demagogues, who either in their

private capacity lay  information against rich men until they compel them to combine (for  a  common danger

unites even the bitterest enemies), or coming  forward in  public stir up the people against them. The truth of

this  remark is  proved by a variety of examples. At Cos the democracy was  overthrown  because wicked

demagogues arose, and the notables combined.  At Rhodes  the demagogues not only provided pay for the

multitude,  but prevented  them from making good to the trierarchs the sums which  had been  expended by

them; and they, in consequence of the suits which  were  brought against them, were compelled to combine

and put down  the  democracy. The democracy at Heraclea was overthrown shortly  after the  foundation of the

colony by the injustice of the demagogues,  which  drove out the notables, who came back in a body and put

an end  to the  democracy. Much in the same manner the democracy at Megara  was  overturned; there the

demagogues drove out many of the notables in  order that they might be able to confiscate their property. At

length  the exiles, becoming numerous, returned, and, engaging and  defeating  the people, established the

oligarchy. The same thing  happened with  the democracy of Cyme, which was overthrown by  Thrasymachus.

And we  may observe that in most states the changes  have been of this  character. For sometimes the

demagogues, in order to  curry favor with  the people, wrong the notables and so force them to  combine; either

they make a division of their property, or diminish  their incomes by  the imposition of public services, and

sometimes they  bring  accusations against the rich that they may have their wealth  to  confiscate. 

Of old, the demagogue was also a general, and then democracies  changed into tyrannies. Most of the ancient

tyrants were originally  demagogues. They are not so now, but they were then; and the reason is  that they were

generals and not orators, for oratory had not yet  come  into fashion. Whereas in our day, when the art of

rhetoric has  made  such progress, the orators lead the people, but their ignorance  of  military matters prevents

them from usurping power; at any rate  instances to the contrary are few and slight. Tyrannies were more

common formerly than now, for this reason also, that great power was  placed in the hands of individuals; thus

a tyranny arose at Miletus  out of the office of the Prytanis, who had supreme authority in many  important

matters. Moreover, in those days, when cities were not  large, the people dwelt in the fields, busy at their

work; and their  chiefs, if they possessed any military talent, seized the opportunity,  and winning the

confidence of the masses by professing their hatred of  the wealthy, they succeeded in obtaining the tyranny.

Thus at Athens  Peisistratus led a faction against the men of the plain, and Theagenes  at Megara slaughtered

the cattle of the wealthy, which he found by the  river side, where they had put them to graze in land not their

own.  Dionysius, again, was thought worthy of the tyranny because he  denounced Daphnaeus and the rich; his

enmity to the notables won for  him the confidence of the people. Changes also take place from the  ancient to


POLITICS

V 67



Top




Page No 72


the latest form of democracy; for where there is a  popular  election of the magistrates and no property

qualification, the  aspirants for office get hold of the people, and contrive at last even  to set them above the

laws. A more or less complete cure for this  state of things is for the separate tribes, and not the whole  people,

to elect the magistrates. 

These are the principal causes of revolutions in democracies. 

VI

There are two patent causes of revolutions in oligarchies: (1)  First, when the oligarchs oppress the people, for

then anybody is good  enough to be their champion, especially if he be himself a member of  the oligarchy, as

Lygdamis at Naxos, who afterwards came to be tyrant.  But revolutions which commence outside the

governing class may be  further subdivided. Sometimes, when the government is very  exclusive,  the

revolution is brought about by persons of the wealthy  class who  are excluded, as happened at Massalia and

Istros and  Heraclea, and  other cities. Those who had no share in the government  created a  disturbance, until

first the elder brothers, and then the  younger,  were admitted; for in some places father and son, in others  elder

and  younger brothers, do not hold office together. At Massalia  the  oligarchy became more like a

constitutional government, but at  Istros  ended in a democracy, and at Heraclea was enlarged to 600. At

Cnidos,  again, the oligarchy underwent a considerable change. For  the notables  fell out among themselves,

because only a few shared in  the  government; there existed among them the rule already mentioned,  that

father and son not hold office together, and, if there were  several  brothers, only the eldest was admitted. The

people took  advantage of  the quarrel, and choosing one of the notables to be their  leader,  attacked and

conquered the oligarchs, who were divided, and  division  is always a source of weakness. The city of

Erythrae, too, in  old  times was ruled, and ruled well, by the Basilidae, but the  people took  offense at the

narrowness of the oligarchy and changed the  constitution. 

(2) Of internal causes of revolutions in oligarchies one is the  personal rivalry of the oligarchs, which leads

them to play the  demagogue. Now, the oligarchical demagogue is of two sorts: either (a)  he practices upon

the oligarchs themselves (for, although the  oligarchy are quite a small number, there may be a demagogue

among  them, as at Athens Charicles' party won power by courting the  Thirty,  that of Phrynichus by courting

the Four Hundred); or (b) the  oligarchs  may play the demagogue with the people. This was the case at

Larissa,  where the guardians of the citizens endeavored to gain over  the people  because they were elected by

them; and such is the fate  of all  oligarchies in which the magistrates are elected, as at Abydos,  not by  the

class to which they belong, but by the heavyarmed or by  the  people, although they may be required to have

a high  qualification, or  to be members of a political club; or, again,  where the lawcourts are  composed of

persons outside the government,  the oligarchs flatter the  people in order to obtain a decision in  their own

favor, and so they  change the constitution; this happened at  Heraclea in Pontus. Again,  oligarchies change

whenever any attempt  is made to narrow them; for  then those who desire equal rights are  compelled to call in

the  people. Changes in the oligarchy also occur  when the oligarchs waste  their private property by

extravagant living;  for then they want to  innovate, and either try to make themselves  tyrants, or install some

one else in the tyranny, as Hipparinus did  Dionysius at Syracuse, and  as at Amphipolis a man named

Cleotimus  introduced Chalcidian  colonists, and when they arrived, stirred them  up against the rich.  For a like

reason in Aegina the person who  carried on the negotiation  with Chares endeavored to revolutionize the  state.

Sometimes a party  among the oligarchs try directly to create  a political change;  sometimes they rob the

treasury, and then either  the thieves or, as  happened at Apollonia in Pontus, those who resist  them in their

thieving quarrel with the rulers. But an oligarchy which  is at unity  with itself is not easily destroyed from

within; of this  we may see an  example at Pharsalus, for there, although the rulers are  few in  number, they

govern a large city, because they have a good  understanding among themselves. 

Oligarchies, again, are overthrown when another oligarchy is  created  within the original one, that is to say,


POLITICS

VI 68



Top




Page No 73


when the whole  governing body  is small and yet they do not all share in the highest  offices. Thus at  Elis the

governing body was a small senate; and very  few ever found  their way into it, because the senators were only

ninety in number,  and were elected for life and out of certain  families in a manner  similar to the

Lacedaemonian elders. Oligarchy is  liable to  revolutions alike in war and in peace; in war because, not  being

able to trust the people, the oligarchs are compelled to hire  mercenaries, and the general who is in command

of them often ends in  becoming a tyrant, as Timophanes did at Corinth; or if there are  more  generals than one

they make themselves into a company of tyrants.  Sometimes the oligarchs, fearing this danger, give the

people a  share  in the government because their services are necessary to  them. And in  time of peace, from

mutual distrust, the two parties hand  over the  defense of the state to the army and to an arbiter between  the

two  factions, who often ends the master of both. This happened  at Larissa  when Simos the Aleuad had the

government, and at Abydos  in the days of  Iphiades and the political clubs. Revolutions also  arise out of

marriages or lawsuits which lead to the overthrow of  one party among  the oligarchs by another. Of quarrels

about  marriages I have already  mentioned some instances; another occurred at  Eretria, where Diagoras

overturned the oligarchy of the knights  because he had been wronged  about a marriage. A revolution at

Heraclea, and another at Thebes,  both arose out of decisions of  lawcourts upon a charge of adultery;  in both

cases the punishment was  just, but executed in the spirit of  party, at Heraclea upon  Eurytion, and at Thebes

upon Archias; for  their enemies were jealous  of them and so had them pilloried in the  agora. Many

oligarchies  have been destroyed by some members of the  ruling class taking offense  at their excessive

despotism; for example,  the oligarchy at Cnidus and  at Chios. 

Changes of constitutional governments, and also of oligarchies  which  limit the office of counselor, judge, or

other magistrate to  persons  having a certain money qualification, often occur by accident.  The  qualification

may have been originally fixed according to the  circumstances of the time, in such a manner as to include in

an  oligarchy a few only, or in a constitutional government the middle  class. But after a time of prosperity,

whether arising from peace or  some other good fortune, the same property becomes many times as  valuable,

and then everybody participates in every office; this  happens sometimes gradually and insensibly, and

sometimes quickly.  These are the causes of changes and revolutions in oligarchies. 

We must remark generally both of democracies and oligarchies, that  they sometimes change, not into the

opposite forms of government,  but  only into another variety of the same class; I mean to say, from  those

forms of democracy and oligarchy which are regulated by law into  those  which are arbitrary, and conversely. 

VII

In aristocracies revolutions are stirred up when a few only share  in  the honors of the state; a cause which has

been already shown to  affect oligarchies; for an aristocracy is a sort of oligarchy, and,  like an oligarchy, is the

government of a few, although few not for  the same reason; hence the two are often confounded. And

revolutions  will be most likely to happen, and must happen, when the mass of the  people are of the

highspirited kind, and have a notion that they  are  as good as their rulers. Thus at Lacedaemon the socalled

Partheniae,  who were the [illegitimate] sons of the Spartan peers,  attempted a  revolution, and, being detected,

were sent away to  colonize Tarentum.  Again, revolutions occur when great men who are  at least of equal

merit are dishonored by those higher in office, as  Lysander was by the  kings of Sparta; or, when a brave man

is  excluded from the honors of  the state, like Cinadon, who conspired  against the Spartans in the  reign of

Agesilaus; or, again, when some  are very poor and others very  rich, a state of society which is most  often the

result of war, as at  Lacedaemon in the days of the Messenian  War; this is proved from the  poem of Tyrtaeus,

entitled 'Good  Order'; for he speaks of certain  citizens who were ruined by the war  and wanted to have a

redistribution of the land. Again, revolutions  arise when an  individual who is great, and might be greater,

wants  to rule alone,  as, at Lacedaemon, Pausanias, who was general in the  Persian War, or  like Hanno at

Carthage. 


POLITICS

VII 69



Top




Page No 74


Constitutional governments and aristocracies are commonly  overthrown  owing to some deviation from

justice in the constitution  itself; the  cause of the downfall is, in the former, the illmingling  of the two

elements, democracy and oligarchy; in the latter, of the  three  elements, democracy, oligarchy, and virtue, but

especially  democracy  and oligarchy. For to combine these is the endeavor of  constitutional governments; and

most of the socalled aristocracies  have a like aim, but differ from polities in the mode of  combination;  hence

some of them are more and some less permanent.  Those which  incline more to oligarchy are called

aristocracies, and  those which  incline to democracy constitutional governments. And  therefore the  latter are

the safer of the two; for the greater the  number, the  greater the strength, and when men are equal they are

contented. But  the rich, if the constitution gives them power, are apt  to be insolent  and avaricious; and, in

general, whichever way the  constitution  inclines, in that direction it changes as either party  gains strength,  a

constitutional government becoming a democracy, an  aristocracy an  oligarchy. But the process may be

reversed, and  aristocracy may change  into democracy. This happens when the poor,  under the idea that they

are being wronged, force the constitution  to take an opposite form. In  like manner constitutional governments

change into oligarchies. The  only stable principle of government is  equality according to  proportion, and for

every man to enjoy his own. 

What I have just mentioned actually happened at Thurii, where the  qualification for office, at first high, was

therefore reduced, and  the magistrates increased in number. The notables had previously  acquired the whole

of the land contrary to law; for the government  tended to oligarchy, and they were able to encroach.... But the

people, who had been trained by war, soon got the better of the guards  kept by the oligarchs, until those who

had too much gave up their  land. 

Again, since all aristocratical governments incline to oligarchy,  the notables are apt to be grasping; thus at

Lacedaemon, where  property tends to pass into few hands, the notables can do too much as  they like, and are

allowed to marry whom they please. The city of  Locri was ruined by a marriage connection with Dionysius,

but such a  thing could never have happened in a democracy, or in a wellbalanced  aristocracy. 

I have already remarked that in all states revolutions are  occasioned by trifles. In aristocracies, above all, they

are of a  gradual and imperceptible nature. The citizens begin by giving up some  part of the constitution, and

so with greater ease the government  change something else which is a little more important, until they  have

undermined the whole fabric of the state. At Thurii there was a  law that generals should only be reelected

after an interval of  five  years, and some young men who were popular with the soldiers of  the  guard for their

military prowess, despising the magistrates and  thinking that they would easily gain their purpose, wanted to

abolish  this law and allow their generals to hold perpetual  commands; for they  well knew that the people

would be glad enough to  elect them.  Whereupon the magistrates who had charge of these matters,  and who

are  called councillors, at first determined to resist, but  they afterwards  consented, thinking that, if only this

one law was  changed, no further  inroad would be made on the constitution. But  other changes soon  followed

which they in vain attempted to oppose;  and the state passed  into the hands of the revolutionists, who

established a dynastic  oligarchy. 

All constitutions are overthrown either from within or from  without;  the latter, when there is some

government close at hand  having an  opposite interest, or at a distance, but powerful. This was  exemplified in

the old times of the Athenians and the  Lacedaemonians;  the Athenians everywhere put down the oligarchies,

and  the  Lacedaemonians the democracies. 

I have now explained what are the chief causes of revolutions and  dissensions in states. 

VIII

We have next to consider what means there are of preserving  constitutions in general, and in particular cases.


POLITICS

VIII 70



Top




Page No 75


In the first  place  it is evident that if we know the causes which destroy  constitutions,  we also know the causes

which preserve them; for  opposites produce  opposites, and destruction is the opposite of  preservation. 

In all wellattempered governments there is nothing which should  be more jealously maintained than the

spirit of obedience to law, more  especially in small matters; for transgression creeps in unperceived  and at

last ruins the state, just as the constant recurrence of  small  expenses in time eats up a fortune. The expense

does not take  place at  once, and therefore is not observed; the mind is deceived, as  in the  fallacy which says

that 'if each part is little, then the whole  is  little.' this is true in one way, but not in another, for the whole  and

the all are not little, although they are made up of littles. 

In the first place, then, men should guard against the beginning  of change, and in the second place they

should not rely upon the  political devices of which I have already spoken invented only to  deceive the people,

for they are proved by experience to be useless.  Further, we note that oligarchies as well as aristocracies may

last,  not from any inherent stability in such forms of government, but  because the rulers are on good terms

both with the unenfranchised  and  with the governing classes, not maltreating any who are excluded  from  the

government, but introducing into it the leading spirits among  them. They should never wrong the ambitious

in a matter of honor, or  the common people in a matter of money; and they should treat one  another and their

fellow citizen in a spirit of equality. The equality  which the friends of democracy seek to establish for the

multitude  is  not only just but likewise expedient among equals. Hence, if the  governing class are numerous,

many democratic institutions are useful;  for example, the restriction of the tenure of offices to six months,

that all those who are of equal rank may share in them. Indeed, equals  or peers when they are numerous

become a kind of democracy, and  therefore demagogues are very likely to arise among them, as I have

already remarked. The short tenure of office prevents oligarchies  and  aristocracies from falling into the hands

of families; it is not  easy  for a person to do any great harm when his tenure of office is  short,  whereas long

possession begets tyranny in oligarchies and  democracies.  For the aspirants to tyranny are either the principal

men  of the  state, who in democracies are demagogues and in oligarchies  members of  ruling houses, or those

who hold great offices, and have  a long tenure  of them. 

Constitutions are preserved when their destroyers are at a  distance,  and sometimes also because they are near,

for the fear of  them makes  the government keep in hand the constitution. Wherefore the  ruler  who has a care

of the constitution should invent terrors, and  bring  distant dangers near, in order that the citizens may be on

their  guard, and, like sentinels in a night watch, never relax their  attention. He should endeavor too by help of

the laws to control the  contentions and quarrels of the notables, and to prevent those who  have not hitherto

taken part in them from catching the spirit of  contention. No ordinary man can discern the beginning of evil,

but  only the true statesman. 

As to the change produced in oligarchies and constitutional  governments by the alteration of the qualification,

when this  arises,  not out of any variation in the qualification but only out  of the  increase of money, it is well

to compare the general  valuation of  property with that of past years, annually in those  cities in which  the

census is taken annually and in larger cities  every third or fifth  year. If the whole is many times greater or

many times less than when  the ratings recognized by the constitution  were fixed, there should be  power given

by law to raise or lower the  qualification as the amount  is greater or less. Where this is not done  a

constitutional government  passes into an oligarchy, and an oligarchy  is narrowed to a rule of  families; or in

the opposite case  constitutional government becomes  democracy, and oligarchy either  constitutional

government or  democracy. 

It is a principle common to democracy, oligarchy, and every other  form of government not to allow the

disproportionate increase of any  citizen but to give moderate honor for a long time rather than great  honor for

a short time. For men are easily spoilt; not every one can  bear prosperity. But if this rule is not observed, at

any rate the  honors which are given all at once should be taken away by degrees and  not all at once.

Especially should the laws provide against any one  having too much power, whether derived from friends or


POLITICS

VIII 71



Top




Page No 76


money; if he  has, he should be sent clean out of the country. And since innovations  creep in through the

private life of individuals also, there ought  to  be a magistracy which will have an eye to those whose life is

not  in  harmony with the government, whether oligarchy or democracy or  any  other. And for a like reason an

increase of prosperity in any part  of  the state should be carefully watched. The proper remedy for this  evil  is

always to give the management of affairs and offices of  state to  opposite elements; such opposites are the

virtuous and the  many, or  the rich and the poor. Another way is to combine the poor and  the rich  in one body,

or to increase the middle class: thus an end  will be put  to the revolutions which arise from inequality. 

But above all every state should be so administered and so  regulated  by law that its magistrates cannot

possibly make money. In  oligarchies  special precautions should be used against this evil. For  the people  do

not take any great offense at being kept out of the  government  indeed they are rather pleased than otherwise

at having  leisure for  their private business but what irritates them is to  think that their  rulers are stealing the

public money; then they are  doubly annoyed;  for they lose both honor and profit. If office brought  no profit,

then  and then only could democracy and aristocracy be  combined; for both  notables and people might have

their wishes  gratified. All would be  able to hold office, which is the aim of  democracy, and the notables

would be magistrates, which is the aim of  aristocracy. And this result  may be accomplished when there is no

possibility of making money out  of the offices; for the poor will not  want to have them when there  is nothing

to be gained from them they  would rather be attending to  their own concerns; and the rich, who do  not want

money from the  public treasury, will be able to take them;  and so the poor will  keep to their work and grow

rich, and the  notables will not be  governed by the lower class. In order to avoid  peculation of the  public

money, the transfer of the revenue should be  made at a  general assembly of the citizens, and duplicates of the

accounts  deposited with the different brotherhoods, companies, and  tribes.  And honors should be given by

law to magistrates who have the  reputation of being incorruptible. In democracies the rich should be  spared;

not only should their property not be divided, but their  incomes also, which in some states are taken from

them  imperceptibly,  should be protected. It is a good thing to prevent  the wealthy  citizens, even if they are

willing from undertaking  expensive and  useless public services, such as the giving of choruses,  torchraces,

and the like. In an oligarchy, on the other hand, great  care should be  taken of the poor, and lucrative offices

should go to  them; if any of  the wealthy classes insult them, the offender should  be punished more  severely

than if he had wronged one of his own class.  Provision should  be made that estates pass by inheritance and

not by  gift, and no  person should have more than one inheritance; for in this  way  properties will be equalized,

and more of the poor rise to  competency.  It is also expedient both in a democracy and in an  oligarchy to

assign  to those who have less share in the government  (i.e., to the rich in a  democracy and to the poor in an

oligarchy)  an equality or preference  in all but the principal offices of state.  The latter should be  entrusted

chiefly or only to members of the  governing class. 

IX

There are three qualifications required in those who have to fill  the highest offices (1) first of all, loyalty to

the established  constitution; (2) the greatest administrative capacity; (3) virtue and  justice of the kind proper

to each form of government; for, if what is  just is not the same in all governments, the quality of justice must

also differ. There may be a doubt, however, when all these qualities  do not meet in the same person, how the

selection is to be made;  suppose, for example, a good general is a bad man and not a friend  to  the

constitution, and another man is loyal and just, which should  we  choose? In making the election ought we not

to consider two points?  what qualities are common, and what are rare. Thus in the choice of  a  general, we

should regard his skill rather than his virtue; for  few  have military skill, but many have virtue. In any office

of  trust or  stewardship, on the other hand, the opposite rule should be  observed;  for more virtue than ordinary

is required in the holder of  such an  office, but the necessary knowledge is of a sort which all men  possess. 

It may, however, be asked what a man wants with virtue if he have  political ability and is loyal, since these

two qualities alone will  make him do what is for the public interest. But may not men have both  of them and


POLITICS

IX 72



Top




Page No 77


yet be deficient in selfcontrol? If, knowing and loving  their own interests, they do not always attend to

them, may they not  be equally negligent of the interests of the public? 

Speaking generally, we may say that whatever legal enactments are  held to be for the interest of various

constitutions, all these  preserve them. And the great preserving principle is the one which has  been repeatedly

mentioned to have a care that the loyal citizen  should be stronger than the disloyal. Neither should we forget

the  mean, which at the present day is lost sight of in perverted forms  of  government; for many practices

which appear to be democratical  are the  ruin of democracies, and many which appear to be  oligarchical are

the  ruin of oligarchies. Those who think that all  virtue is to be found in  their own party principles push

matters to  extremes; they do not  consider that disproportion destroys a state.  A nose which varies from  the

ideal of straightness to a hook or snub  may still be of good shape  and agreeable to the eye; but if the excess

be very great, all  symmetry is lost, and the nose at last ceases to be  a nose at all on  account of some excess in

one direction or defect  in the other; and  this is true of every other part of the human  body. The same law of

proportion equally holds in states. Oligarchy or  democracy, although a  departure from the most perfect form,

may yet be  a good enough  government, but if any one attempts to push the  principles of either  to an extreme,

he will begin by spoiling the  government and end by  having none at all. Wherefore the legislator and  the

statesman ought  to know what democratical measures save and what  destroy a democracy,  and what

oligarchical measures save or destroy an  oligarchy. For  neither the one nor the other can exist or continue  to

exist unless  both rich and poor are included in it. If equality  of property is  introduced, the state must of

necessity take another  form; for when by  laws carried to excess one or other element in the  state is ruined,  the

constitution is ruined. 

There is an error common both to oligarchies and to democracies:  in the latter the demagogues, when the

multitude are above the law,  are always cutting the city in two by quarrels with the rich,  whereas  they should

always profess to be maintaining their cause; just  as in  oligarchies the oligarchs should profess to maintaining

the  cause of  the people, and should take oaths the opposite of those which  they now  take. For there are cities

in which they swear 'I will be an  enemy to  the people, and will devise all the harm against them which I

can';  but they ought to exhibit and to entertain the very opposite  feeling;  in the form of their oath there should

be an express  declaration 'I  will do no wrong to the people.' 

But of all the things which I have mentioned that which most  contributes to the permanence of constitutions

is the adaptation of  education to the form of government, and yet in our own day this  principle is universally

neglected. The best laws, though sanctioned  by every citizen of the state, will be of no avail unless the young

are trained by habit and education in the spirit of the  constitution,  if the laws are democratical, democratically

or  oligarchically, if the  laws are oligarchical. For there may be a  want of selfdiscipline in  states as well as in

individuals. Now, to  have been educated in the  spirit of the constitution is not to perform  the actions in which

oligarchs or democrats delight, but those by  which the existence of an  oligarchy or of a democracy is made

possible. Whereas among ourselves  the sons of the ruling class in an  oligarchy live in luxury, but the  sons of

the poor are hardened by  exercise and toil, and hence they are  both more inclined and better  able to make a

revolution. And in  democracies of the more extreme type  there has arisen a false idea of  freedom which is

contradictory to the  true interests of the state. For  two principles are characteristic  of democracy, the

government of the  majority and freedom. Men think  that what is just is equal; and that  equality is the

supremacy of  the popular will; and that freedom means  the doing what a man likes.  In such democracies

every one lives as he  pleases, or in the words  of Euripides, 'according to his fancy.' But  this is all wrong; men

should not think it slavery to live according  to the rule of the  constitution; for it is their salvation. 

I have now discussed generally the causes of the revolution and  destruction of states, and the means of their

preservation and  continuance. 


POLITICS

IX 73



Top




Page No 78


X

I have still to speak of monarchy, and the causes of its  destruction  and preservation. What I have said already

respecting  forms of  constitutional government applies almost equally to royal and  to  tyrannical rule. For royal

rule is of the nature of an aristocracy,  and a tyranny is a compound of oligarchy and democracy in their most

extreme forms; it is therefore most injurious to its subjects, being  made up of two evil forms of government,

and having the perversions  and errors of both. These two forms of monarchy are contrary in  their  very origin.

The appointment of a king is the resource of the  better  classes against the people, and he is elected by them

out of  their own  number, because either he himself or his family excel in  virtue and  virtuous actions; whereas

a tyrant is chosen from the  people to be  their protector against the notables, and in order to  prevent them  from

being injured. History shows that almost all tyrants  have been  demagogues who gained the favor of the

people by their  accusation of  the notables. At any rate this was the manner in which  the tyrannies  arose in the

days when cities had increased in power.  Others which  were older originated in the ambition of kings

wanting to  overstep the  limits of their hereditary power and become despots.  Others again grew  out of the

class which were chosen to be chief  magistrates; for in  ancient times the people who elected them gave the

magistrates,  whether civil or religious, a long tenure. Others arose  out of the  custom which oligarchies had of

making some individual  supreme over  the highest offices. In any of these ways an ambitious  man had no

difficulty, if he desired, in creating a tyranny, since  he had the  power in his hands already, either as king or as

one of the  officers  of state. Thus Pheidon at Argos and several others were  originally  kings, and ended by

becoming tyrants; Phalaris, on the  other hand, and  the Ionian tyrants, acquired the tyranny by holding  great

offices.  Whereas Panaetius at Leontini, Cypselus at Corinth,  Peisistratus at  Athens, Dionysius at Syracuse,

and several others  who afterwards  became tyrants, were at first demagogues. 

And so, as I was saying, royalty ranks with aristocracy, for it is  based upon merit, whether of the individual

or of his family, or on  benefits conferred, or on these claims with power added to them. For  all who have

obtained this honor have benefited, or had in their power  to benefit, states and nations; some, like Codrus,

have prevented  the  state from being enslaved in war; others, like Cyrus, have given  their  country freedom, or

have settled or gained a territory, like the  Lacedaemonian, Macedonian, and Molossian kings. The idea of a

king  is  to be a protector of the rich against unjust treatment, of the  people  against insult and oppression.

Whereas a tyrant, as has often  been  repeated, has no regard to any public interest, except as  conducive to  his

private ends; his aim is pleasure, the aim of a king,  honor.  Wherefore also in their desires they differ; the

tyrant is  desirous of  riches, the king, of what brings honor. And the guards  of a king are  citizens, but of a

tyrant mercenaries. 

That tyranny has all the vices both of democracy and oligarchy is  evident. As of oligarchy so of tyranny, the

end is wealth; (for by  wealth only can the tyrant maintain either his guard or his luxury).  Both mistrust the

people, and therefore deprive them of their arms.  Both agree too in injuring the people and driving them out

of the city  and dispersing them. From democracy tyrants have borrowed the art of  making war upon the

notables and destroying them secretly or openly,  or of exiling them because they are rivals and stand in the

way of  their power; and also because plots against them are contrived by  men  of this dass, who either want to

rule or to escape subjection.  Hence  Periander advised Thrasybulus by cutting off the tops of the  tallest  ears of

corn, meaning that he must always put out of the way  the  citizens who overtop the rest. And so, as I have

already  intimated,  the beginnings of change are the same in monarchies as in  forms of  constitutional

government; subjects attack their sovereigns  out of  fear or contempt, or because they have been unjustly

treated by  them.  And of injustice, the most common form is insult, another is  confiscation of property. 

The ends sought by conspiracies against monarchies, whether  tyrannies or royalties, are the same as the ends

sought by  conspiracies against other forms of government. Monarchs have great  wealth and honor, which are

objects of desire to all mankind. The  attacks are made sometimes against their lives, sometimes against  the

office; where the sense of insult is the motive, against their  lives.  Any sort of insult (and there are many) may


POLITICS

X 74



Top




Page No 79


stir up anger,  and when  men are angry, they commonly act out of revenge, and not from  ambition. For

example, the attempt made upon the Peisistratidae  arose  out of the public dishonor offered to the sister of

Harmodius  and the  insult to himself. He attacked the tyrant for his sister's  sake, and  Aristogeiton joined in the

attack for the sake of Harmodius.  A  conspiracy was also formed against Periander, the tyrant of  Ambracia,

because, when drinking with a favorite youth, he asked him  whether by  this time he was not with child by

him. Philip, too, was  attacked by  Pausanias because he permitted him to be insulted by  Attalus and his

friends, and Amyntas the little, by Derdas, because he  boasted of  having enjoyed his youth. Evagoras of

Cyprus, again, was  slain by the  eunuch to revenge an insult; for his wife had been  carried off by  Evagoras's

son. Many conspiracies have originated in  shameful attempts  made by sovereigns on the persons of their

subjects.  Such was the  attack of Crataeas upon Archelaus; he had always hated  the connection  with him, and

so, when Archelaus, having promised him  one of his two  daughters in marriage, did not give him either of

them,  but broke his  word and married the elder to the king of Elymeia,  when he was hard  pressed in a war

against Sirrhas and Arrhabaeus,  and the younger to  his own son Amyntas, under the idea that Amyntas  would

then be less  likely to quarrel with his son by Cleopatra  Crataeas made this slight  a pretext for attacking

Archelaus, though  even a less reason would  have sufficed, for the real cause of the  estrangement was the

disgust  which he felt at his connection with  the king. And from a like motive  Hellonocrates of Larissa

conspired  with him; for when Archelaus, who  was his lover, did not fulfill his  promise of restoring him to his

country, he thought that the  connection between them had originated,  not in affection, but in the  wantonness

of power. Pytho, too, and  Heracleides of Aenos, slew  Cotys in order to avenge their father, and  Adamas

revolted from  Cotys in revenge for the wanton outrage which he  had committed in  mutilating him when a

child. 

Many, too, irritated at blows inflicted on the person which they  deemed an insult, have either killed or

attempted to kill officers  of  state and royal princes by whom they have been injured. Thus, at  Mytilene,

Megacles and his friends attacked and slew the  Penthilidae,  as they were going about and striking people with

clubs. At a later  date Smerdis, who had been beaten and torn away from  his wife by  Penthilus, slew him. In

the conspiracy against  Archelaus, Decamnichus  stimulated the fury of the assassins and led  the attack; he was

enraged because Archelaus had delivered him to  Euripides to be  scourged; for the poet had been irritated at

some  remark made by  Decamnichus on the foulness of his breath. Many other  examples might  be cited of

murders and conspiracies which have  arisen from similar  causes. 

Fear is another motive which, as we have said, has caused  conspiracies as well in monarchies as in more

popular forms of  government. Thus Artapanes conspired against Xerxes and slew him,  fearing that he would

be accused of hanging Darius against his  ordershe having been under the impression that Xerxes would

forget  what he had said in the middle of a meal, and that the offense would  be forgiven. 

Another motive is contempt, as in the case of Sardanapalus, whom  some one saw carding wool with his

women, if the storytellers say  truly; and the tale may be true, if not of him, of some one else. Dion  attacked

the younger Dionysius because he despised him, and saw that  he was equally despised by his own subjects,

and that he was always  drunk. Even the friends of a tyrant will sometimes attack him out of  contempt; for the

confidence which he reposes in them breeds contempt,  and they think that they will not be found out. The

expectation of  success is likewise a sort of contempt; the assailants are ready to  strike, and think nothing of

the danger, because they seem to have the  power in their hands. Thus generals of armies attack monarchs; as,

for  example, Cyrus attacked Astyages, despising the effeminacy of his  life, and believing that his power was

worn out. Thus again, Seuthes  the Thracian conspired against Amadocus, whose general he was. 

And sometimes men are actuated by more than one motive, like  Mithridates, who conspired against

Ariobarzanes, partly out of  contempt and partly from the love of gain. 

Bold natures, placed by their sovereigns in a high military  position, are most likely to make the attempt in the

expectation of  success; for courage is emboldened by power, and the union of the  two  inspires them with the


POLITICS

X 75



Top




Page No 80


hope of an easy victory. 

Attempts of which the motive is ambition arise in a different way  as  well as in those already mentioned.

There are men who will not risk  their lives in the hope of gains and honors however great, but who

nevertheless regard the killing of a tyrant simply as an extraordinary  action which will make them famous

and honorable in the world; they  wish to acquire, not a kingdom, but a name. It is rare, however, to  find such

men; he who would kill a tyrant must be prepared to lose his  life if he fail. He must have the resolution of

Dion, who, when he  made war upon Dionysius, took with him very few troops, saying 'that  whatever measure

of success he might attain would be enough for him,  even if he were to die the moment he landed; such a

death would be  welcome to him.' this is a temper to which few can attain. 

Once more, tyrannies, like all other governments, are destroyed  from  without by some opposite and more

powerful form of government.  That  such a government will have the will to attack them is clear; for  the two

are opposed in principle; and all men, if they can, do what  they will. Democracy is antagonistic to tyranny, on

the principle of  Hesiod, 'Potter hates Potter,' because they are nearly akin, for the  extreme form of democracy

is tyranny; and royalty and aristocracy  are  both alike opposed to tyranny, because they are constitutions of a

different type. And therefore the Lacedaemonians put down most of  the  tyrannies, and so did the Syracusans

during the time when they  were  well governed. 

Again, tyrannies are destroyed from within, when the reigning  family  are divided among themselves, as that

of Gelo was, and more  recently  that of Dionysius; in the case of Gelo because Thrasybulus,  the  brother of

Hiero, flattered the son of Gelo and led him into  excesses in order that he might rule in his name. Whereupon

the family  got together a party to get rid of Thrasybulus and save the tyranny;  but those of the people who

conspired with them seized the opportunity  and drove them all out. In the case of Dionysius, Dion, his own

relative, attacked and expelled him with the assistance of the people;  he afterwards perished himself. 

There are two chief motives which induce men to attack tyrannies  hatred and contempt. Hatred of tyrants is

inevitable, and contempt  is  also a frequent cause of their destruction. Thus we see that most  of  those who

have acquired, have retained their power, but those who  have  inherited, have lost it, almost at once; for, living

in luxurious  ease, they have become contemptible, and offer many opportunities to  their assailants. Anger,

too, must be included under hatred, and  produces the same effects. It is often times even more ready to

strike the angry are more impetuous in making an attack, for they  do  not follow rational principle. And men

are very apt to give way  to  their passions when they are insulted. To this cause is to be  attributed the fall of

the Peisistratidae and of many others. Hatred  is more reasonable, for anger is accompanied by pain, which is

an  impediment to reason, whereas hatred is painless. 

In a word, all the causes which I have mentioned as destroying the  last and most unmixed form of oligarchy,

and the extreme form of  democracy, may be assumed to affect tyranny; indeed the extreme  forms  of both are

only tyrannies distributed among several persons.  Kingly  rule is little affected by external causes, and is

therefore  lasting;  it is generally destroyed from within. And there are two ways  in which  the destruction may

come about; (1) when the members of the  royal  family quarrel among themselves, and (2) when the kings

attempt to  administer the state too much after the fashion of a  tyranny, and to  extend their authority contrary

to the law.  Royalties do not now come  into existence; where such forms of  government arise, they are rather

monarchies or tyrannies. For the  rule of a king is over voluntary  subjects, and he is supreme in all  important

matters; but in our own  day men are more upon an equality,  and no one is so immeasurably  superior to others

as to represent  adequately the greatness and  dignity of the office. Hence mankind will  not, if they can help,

endure it, and any one who obtains power by  force or fraud is at once  thought to be a tyrant. In hereditary

monarchies a further cause of  destruction is the fact that kings often  fall into contempt, and,  although

possessing not tyrannical power, but  only royal dignity, are  apt to outrage others. Their overthrow is then

readily effected; for  there is an end to the king when his subjects do  not want to have him,  but the tyrant lasts,

whether they like him or  not. 


POLITICS

X 76



Top




Page No 81


The destruction of monarchies is to be attributed to these and the  like causes. 

XI

And they are preserved, to speak generally, by the opposite  causes; or, if we consider them separately, (1)

royalty is preserved  by the limitation of its powers. The more restricted the functions  of  kings, the longer

their power will last unimpaired; for then they  are  more moderate and not so despotic in their ways; and they

are less  envied by their subjects. This is the reason why the kingly office has  lasted so long among the

Molossians. And for a similar reason it has  continued among the Lacedaemonians, because there it was

always  divided between two, and afterwards further limited by Theopompus in  various respects, more

particularly by the establishment of the  Ephoralty. He diminished the power of the kings, but established on  a

more lasting basis the kingly office, which was thus made in a  certain  sense not less, but greater. There is a

story that when his  wife once  asked him whether he was not ashamed to leave to his sons  a royal  power

which was less than he had inherited from his father,  'No  indeed,' he replied, 'for the power which I leave to

them will  be more  lasting.' 

As to (2) tyrannies, they are preserved in two most opposite ways.  One of them is the old traditional method

in which most tyrants  administer their government. Of such arts Periander of Corinth is said  to have been the

great master, and many similar devices may be  gathered from the Persians in the administration of their

government.  There are firstly the prescriptions mentioned some  distance back, for  the preservation of a

tyranny, in so far as this is  possible; viz.,  that the tyrant should lop off those who are too high;  he must put to

death men of spirit; he must not allow common meals,  clubs, education,  and the like; he must be upon his

guard against  anything which is  likely to inspire either courage or confidence among  his subjects; he  must

prohibit literary assemblies or other meetings  for discussion,  and he must take every means to prevent people

from  knowing one  another (for acquaintance begets mutual confidence).  Further, he must  compel all persons

staying in the city to appear in  public and live at  his gates; then he will know what they are doing:  if they are

always  kept under, they will learn to be humble. In short,  he should practice  these and the like Persian and

barbaric arts, which  all have the same  object. A tyrant should also endeavor to know what  each of his  subjects

says or does, and should employ spies, like the  'female  detectives' at Syracuse, and the eavesdroppers whom

Hiero  was in the  habit of sending to any place of resort or meeting; for the  fear of  informers prevents people

from speaking their minds, and if  they do,  they are more easily found out. Another art of the tyrant  is to sow

quarrels among the citizens; friends should be embroiled  with friends,  the people with the notables, and the

rich with one  another. Also he  should impoverish his subjects; he thus provides  against the  maintenance of a

guard by the citizen and the people,  having to keep  hard at work, are prevented from conspiring. The

Pyramids of Egypt  afford an example of this policy; also the offerings  of the family of  Cypselus, and the

building of the temple of  Olympian Zeus by the  Peisistratidae, and the great Polycratean  monuments at

Samos; all  these works were alike intended to occupy  the people and keep them  poor. Another practice of

tyrants is to  multiply taxes, after the  manner of Dionysius at Syracuse, who  contrived that within five years

his subjects should bring into the  treasury their whole property. The  tyrant is also fond of making war  in

order that his subjects may have  something to do and be always in  want of a leader. And whereas the  power

of a king is preserved by  his friends, the characteristic of a  tyrant is to distrust his  friends, because he knows

that all men want  to overthrow him, and they  above all have the power. 

Again, the evil practices of the last and worst form of democracy  are all found in tyrannies. Such are the

power given to women in their  families in the hope that they will inform against their husbands, and  the

license which is allowed to slaves in order that they may betray  their masters; for slaves and women do not

conspire against tyrants;  and they are of course friendly to tyrannies and also to  democracies,  since under

them they have a good time. For the people  too would fain  be a monarch, and therefore by them, as well as by

the tyrant, the  flatterer is held in honor; in democracies he is the  demagogue; and  the tyrant also has those

who associate with him in a  humble spirit,  which is a work of flattery. 


POLITICS

XI 77



Top




Page No 82


Hence tyrants are always fond of bad men, because they love to be  flattered, but no man who has the spirit of

a freeman in him will  lower himself by flattery; good men love others, or at any rate do not  flatter them.

Moreover, the bad are useful for bad purposes; 'nail  knocks out nail,' as the proverb says. It is characteristic of

a  tyrant to dislike every one who has dignity or independence; he  wants  to be alone in his glory, but any one

who claims a like  dignity or  asserts his independence encroaches upon his prerogative,  and is hated  by him as

an enemy to his power. Another mark of a tyrant  is that he  likes foreigners better than citizens, and lives with

them and invites  them to his table; for the one are enemies, but the  Others enter into  no rivalry with him. 

Such are the notes of the tyrant and the arts by which he  preserves his power; there is no wickedness too great

for him. All  that we have said may be summed up under three heads, which answer  to  the three aims of the

tyrant. These are, (1) the humiliation of his  subjects; he knows that a meanspirited man will not conspire

against  anybody; (2) the creation of mistrust among them; for a tyrant  is not  overthrown until men begin to

have confidence in one another;  and this  is the reason why tyrants are at war with the good; they  are under the

idea that their power is endangered by them, not only  because they  would not be ruled despotically but also

because they are  loyal to one  another, and to other men, and do not inform against  one another or  against

other men; (3) the tyrant desires that his  subjects shall be  incapable of action, for no one attempts what is

impossible, and they  will not attempt to overthrow a tyranny, if  they are powerless. Under  these three heads

the whole policy of a  tyrant may be summed up, and  to one or other of them all his ideas may  be referred: (1)

he sows  distrust among his subjects; (2) he takes  away their power; (3) he  humbles them. 

This then is one of the two methods by which tyrannies are  preserved; and there is another which proceeds

upon an almost opposite  principle of action. The nature of this latter method may be  gathered  from a

comparison of the causes which destroy kingdoms, for  as one  mode of destroying kingly power is to make the

office of king  more  tyrannical, so the salvation of a tyranny is to make it more like  the  rule of a king. But of

one thing the tyrant must be careful; he  must  keep power enough to rule over his subjects, whether they like

him or  not, for if he once gives this up he gives up his tyranny.  But though  power must be retained as the

foundation, in all else the  tyrant  should act or appear to act in the character of a king. In  the first  place he

should pretend a care of the public revenues, and  not waste  money in making presents of a sort at which the

common  people get  excited when they see their hardwon earnings snatched from  them and  lavished on

courtesans and strangers and artists. He should  give an  account of what he receives and of what he spends (a

practice which  has been adopted by some tyrants); for then he will  seem to be a  steward of the public rather

than a tyrant; nor need he  fear that,  while he is the lord of the city, he will ever be in want  of money.  Such a

policy is at all events much more advantageous for  the tyrant  when he goes from home, than to leave behind

him a hoard,  for then the  garrison who remain in the city will be less likely to  attack his  power; and a tyrant,

when he is absent from home, has  more reason to  fear the guardians of his treasure than the citizens,  for the

one  accompany him, but the others remain behind. In the second  place, he  should be seen to collect taxes and

to require public  services only  for state purposes, and that he may form a fund in  case of war, and  generally

he ought to make himself the guardian and  treasurer of them,  as if they belonged, not to him, but to the

public.  He should appear,  not harsh, but dignified, and when men meet him they  should look upon  him with

reverence, and not with fear. Yet it is hard  for him to be  respected if he inspires no respect, and therefore

whatever virtues he  may neglect, at least he should maintain the  character of a great  soldier, and produce the

impression that he is  one. Neither he nor any  of his associates should ever be guilty of the  least offense

against  modesty towards the young of either sex who  are his subjects, and the  women of his family should

observe a like  selfcontrol towards other  women; the insolence of women has ruined  many tyrannies. In the

indulgence of pleasures he should be the  opposite of our modern  tyrants, who not only begin at dawn and

pass  whole days in sensuality,  but want other men to see them, that they  may admire their happy and  blessed

lot. In these things a tyrant  should if possible be moderate,  or at any rate should not parade his  vices to the

world; for a drunken  and drowsy tyrant is soon despised  and attacked; not so he who is  temperate and wide

awake. His conduct  should be the very reverse of  nearly everything which has been said  before about tyrants.

He ought  to adorn and improve his city, as  though he were not a tyrant, but the  guardian of the state. Also he

should appear to be particularly  earnest in the service of the Gods;  for if men think that a ruler is  religious and


POLITICS

XI 78



Top




Page No 83


has a reverence for the  Gods, they are less afraid of  suffering injustice at his hands, and  they are less disposed

to  conspire against him, because they believe  him to have the very Gods  fighting on his side. At the same

time his  religion must not be  thought foolish. And he should honor men of  merit, and make them think  that

they would not be held in more honor  by the citizens if they had  a free government. The honor he should

distribute himself, but the  punishment should be inflicted by officers  and courts of law. It is a  precaution

which is taken by all monarchs  not to make one person  great; but if one, then two or more should be  raised,

that they may  look sharply after one another. If after all  some one has to be made  great, he should not be a

man of bold  spirit; for such dispositions  are ever most inclined to strike. And if  any one is to be deprived of

his power, let it be diminished  gradually, not taken from him all at  once. The tyrant should abstain  from all

outrage; in particular from  personal violence and from wanton  conduct towards the young. He should  be

especially careful of his  behavior to men who are lovers of honor;  for as the lovers of money  are offended

when their property is  touched, so are the lovers of  honor and the virtuous when their honor  is affected.

Therefore a  tyrant ought either not to commit such acts  at all; or he should be  thought only to employ fatherly

correction,  and not to trample upon  others and his acquaintance with youth should  be supposed to arise  from

affection, and not from the insolence of  power, and in general he  should compensate the appearance of

dishonor  by the increase of honor. 

Of those who attempt assassination they are the most dangerous,  and require to be most carefully watched,

who do not care to  survive,  if they effect their purpose. Therefore special precaution  should be  taken about

any who think that either they or those for whom  they care  have been insulted; for when men are led away by

passion  to assault  others they are regardless of themselves. As Heracleitus  says, 'It is  difficult to fight against

anger; for a man will buy  revenge with his  soul.' 

And whereas states consist of two classes, of poor men and of  rich, the tyrant should lead both to imagine that

they are preserved  and prevented from harming one another by his rule, and whichever of  the two is stronger

he should attach to his government; for, having  this advantage, he has no need either to emancipate slaves or

to  disarm the citizens; either party added to the force which he  already  has, will make him stronger than his

assailants. 

But enough of these details; what should be the general policy of  the tyrant is obvious. He ought to show

himself to his subjects in the  light, not of a tyrant, but of a steward and a king. He should not  appropriate

what is theirs, but should be their guardian; he should be  moderate, not extravagant in his way of life; he

should win the  notables by companionship, and the multitude by flattery. For then his  rule will of necessity

be nobler and happier, because he will rule  over better men whose spirits are not crushed, over men to whom

he  himself is not an object of hatred, and of whom he is not afraid.  His  power too will be more lasting. His

disposition will be  virtuous, or  at least half virtuous; and he will not be wicked, but  half wicked  only. 

XII

Yet no forms of government are so shortlived as oligarchy and  tyranny. The tyranny which lasted longest

was that of Orthagoras and  his sons at Sicyon; this continued for a hundred years. The reason was  that they

treated their subjects with moderation, and to a great  extent observed the laws; and in various ways gained the

favor of  the  people by the care which they took of them. Cleisthenes, in  particular, was respected for his

military ability. If report may be  believed, he crowned the judge who decided against him in the games;  and,

as some say, the sitting statue in the Agora of Sicyon is the  likeness of this person. (A similar story is told of

Peisistratus, who  is said on one occasion to have allowed himself to be summoned and  tried before the

Areopagus.) 

Next in duration to the tyranny of Orthagoras was that of the  Cypselidae at Corinth, which lasted

seventythree years and six  months: Cypselus reigned thirty years, Periander forty and a half, and


POLITICS

XII 79



Top




Page No 84


Psammetichus the son of Gorgus three. Their continuance was due to  similar causes: Cypselus was a popular

man, who during the whole  time  of his rule never had a bodyguard; and Periander, although he was  a  tyrant,

was a great soldier. Third in duration was the rule of the  Peisistratidae at Athens, but it was interrupted; for

Peisistratus was  twice driven out, so that during three and thirty years he reigned  only seventeen; and his sons

reigned eighteenaltogether thirtyfive  years. Of other tyrannies, that of Hiero and Gelo at Syracuse was  the

most lasting. Even this, however, was short, not more than  eighteen  years in all; for Gelo continued tyrant for

seven years,  and died in  the eighth; Hiero reigned for ten years, and Thrasybulus  was driven  out in the

eleventh month. In fact, tyrannies generally  have been of  quite short duration. 

I have now gone through almost all the causes by which  constitutional governments and monarchies are

either destroyed or  preserved. 

In the Republic of Plato, Socrates treats of revolutions, but not  well, for he mentions no cause of change

which peculiarly affects  the  first, or perfect state. He only says that the cause is that  nothing  is abiding, but all

things change in a certain cycle; and that  the  origin of the change consists in those numbers 'of which 4 and  3,

married with 5, furnish two harmonies' (he means when the number of  this figure becomes solid); he

conceives that nature at certain  times  produces bad men who will not submit to education; in which  latter

particular he may very likely be not far wrong, for there may  well be  some men who cannot be educated and

made virtuous. But why  is such a  cause of change peculiar to his ideal state, and not  rather common to  all

states, nay, to everything which comes into being  at all? And is  it by the agency of time, which, as he

declares,  makes all things  change, that things which did not begin together,  change together? For  example, if

something has come into being the day  before the  completion of the cycle, will it change with things that

came into  being before? Further, why should the perfect state change  into the  Spartan? For governments more

often take an opposite form  than one  akin to them. The same remark is applicable to the other  changes; he

says that the Spartan constitution changes into an  oligarchy, and this  into a democracy, and this again into a

tyranny.  And yet the contrary  happens quite as often; for a democracy is even  more likely to change  into an

oligarchy than into a monarchy. Further,  he never says whether  tyranny is, or is not, liable to revolutions,  and

if it is, what is  the cause of them, or into what form it changes.  And the reason is,  that he could not very well

have told: for there is  no rule; according  to him it should revert to the first and best,  and then there would be  a

complete cycle. But in point of fact a  tyranny often changes into a  tyranny, as that at Sicyon changed from

the tyranny of Myron into that  of Cleisthenes; into oligarchy, as  the tyranny of Antileon did at  Chalcis; into

democracy, as that of  Gelo's family did at Syracuse;  into aristocracy, as at Carthage, and  the tyranny of

Charilaus at  Lacedaemon. Often an oligarchy changes  into a tyranny, like most of  the ancient oligarchies in

Sicily; for  example, the oligarchy at  Leontini changed into the tyranny of  Panaetius; that at Gela into the

tyranny of Cleander; that at  Rhegium into the tyranny of Anaxilaus;  the same thing has happened  in many

other states. And it is absurd to  suppose that the state  changes into oligarchy merely because the  ruling class

are lovers  and makers of money, and not because the very  rich think it unfair  that the very poor should have

an equal share in  the government with  themselves. Moreover, in many oligarchies there  are laws against

making money in trade. But at Carthage, which is a  democracy. there is  no such prohibition; and yet to this

day the  Carthaginians have  never had a revolution. It is absurd too for him to  say that an  oligarchy is two

cities, one of the rich, and the other of  the poor.  Is not this just as much the case in the Spartan  constitution,

or in  any other in which either all do not possess equal  property, or all  are not equally good men? Nobody

need be any poorer  than he was  before, and yet the oligarchy may change an the same into  a democracy,  if

the poor form the majority; and a democracy may change  into an  oligarchy, if the wealthy class are stronger

than the people,  and  the one are energetic, the other indifferent. Once more, although  the causes of the change

are very numerous, he mentions only one,  which is, that the citizens become poor through dissipation and

debt,  as though he thought that all, or the majority of them, were  originally rich. This is not true: though it is

true that when any  of  the leaders lose their property they are ripe for revolution;  but,  when anybody else, it is

no great matter, and an oligarchy does  not  even then more often pass into a democracy than into any other

form of  government. Again, if men are deprived of the honors of state,  and are  wronged, and insulted, they

make revolutions, and change forms  of  government, even although they have not wasted their substance


POLITICS

XII 80



Top




Page No 85


because  they might do what they liked of which extravagance he  declares  excessive freedom to be the

cause. 

Finally, although there are many forms of oligarchies and  democracies, Socrates speaks of their revolutions

as though there were  only one form of either of them. 

BOOK SIX

I

WE have now considered the varieties of the deliberative or  supreme power in states, and the various

arrangements of lawcourts  and state offices, and which of them are adapted to different forms of

government. We have also spoken of the destruction and preservation of  constitutions, how and from what

causes they arise. 

Of democracy and all other forms of government there are many  kinds;  and it will be well to assign to them

severally the modes of  organization which are proper and advantageous to each, adding what  remains to be

said about them. Moreover, we ought to consider the  various combinations of these modes themselves; for

such  combinations  make constitutions overlap one another, so that  aristocracies have an  oligarchical

character, and constitutional  governments incline to  democracies. 

When I speak of the combinations which remain to be considered,  and thus far have not been considered by

us, I mean such as these:  when the deliberative part of the government and the election of  officers is

constituted oligarchically, and the lawcourts  aristocratically, or when the courts and the deliberative part of

the  state are oligarchical, and the election to office aristocratical,  or  when in any other way there is a want of

harmony in the composition  of  a state. 

I have shown already what forms of democracy are suited to  particular cities, and what of oligarchy to

particular peoples, and to  whom each of the other forms of government is suited. Further, we must  not only

show which of these governments is the best for each state,  but also briefly proceed to consider how these

and other forms of  government are to be established. 

First of all let us speak of democracy, which will also bring to  light the opposite form of government

commonly called oligarchy. For  the purposes of this inquiry we need to ascertain all the elements and

characteristics of democracy, since from the combinations of these the  varieties of democratic government

arise. There are several of these  differing from each other, and the difference is due to two causes.  One (1)

has been already mentioned differences of population; for the  popular element may consist of husbandmen,

or of mechanics, or of  laborers, and if the first of these be added to the second, or the  third to the two others,

not only does the democracy become better  or  worse, but its very nature is changed. A second cause (2)

remains  to  be mentioned: the various properties and characteristics of  democracy,  when variously combined,

make a difference. For one  democracy will  have less and another will have more, and another  will have all of

these characteristics. There is an advantage in  knowing them all,  whether a man wishes to establish some new

form of  democracy, or only  to remodel an existing one. Founders of states  try to bring together  all the

elements which accord with the ideas  of the several  constitutions; but this is a mistake of theirs, as I  have

already  remarked when speaking of the destruction and  preservation of states.  We will now set forth the

principles,  characteristics, and aims of  such states. 


POLITICS

BOOK SIX 81



Top




Page No 86


II

The basis of a democratic state is liberty; which, according to  the common opinion of men, can only be

enjoyed in such a state; this  they affirm to be the great end of every democracy. One principle of  liberty is for

all to rule and be ruled in turn, and indeed democratic  justice is the application of numerical not proportionate

equality;  whence it follows that the majority must be supreme, and that whatever  the majority approve must

be the end and the just. Every citizen, it  is said, must have equality, and therefore in a democracy the poor

have more power than the rich, because there are more of them, and the  will of the majority is supreme. This,

then, is one note of liberty  which all democrats affirm to be the principle of their state. Another  is that a man

should live as he likes. This, they say, is the  privilege of a freeman, since, on the other hand, not to live as a

man  likes is the mark of a slave. This is the second characteristic of  democracy, whence has arisen the claim

of men to be ruled by none,  if  possible, or, if this is impossible, to rule and be ruled in turns;  and so it

contributes to the freedom based upon equality. 

Such being our foundation and such the principle from which we  start, the characteristics of democracy are as

follows the election of  officers by all out of all; and that all should rule over each, and  each in his turn over

all; that the appointment to all offices, or  to  all but those which require experience and skill, should be made

by  lot; that no property qualification should be required for offices, or  only a very low one; that a man should

not hold the same office twice,  or not often, or in the case of few except military offices: that  the  tenure of all

offices, or of as many as possible, should be brief,  that all men should sit in judgment, or that judges selected

out of  all should judge, in all matters, or in most and in the greatest and  most important such as the scrutiny

of accounts, the constitution,  and private contracts; that the assembly should be supreme over all  causes, or at

any rate over the most important, and the magistrates  over none or only over a very few. Of all magistracies,

a council is  the most democratic when there is not the means of paying all the  citizens, but when they are paid

even this is robbed of its power; for  the people then draw all cases to themselves, as I said in the  previous

discussion. The next characteristic of democracy is payment  for services; assembly, law courts, magistrates,

everybody receives  pay, when it is to be had; or when it is not to be had for all, then  it is given to the

lawcourts and to the stated assemblies, to the  council and to the magistrates, or at least to any of them who

are  compelled to have their meals together. And whereas oligarchy is  characterized by birth, wealth, and

education, the notes of  democracy  appear to be the opposite of these low birth, poverty, mean  employment.

Another note is that no magistracy is perpetual, but if  any such have survived some ancient change in the

constitution it  should be stripped of its power, and the holders should be elected  by  lot and no longer by vote.

These are the points common to all  democracies; but democracy and demos in their truest form are based

upon the recognized principle of democratic justice, that all should  count equally; for equality implies that the

poor should have no  more  share in the government than the rich, and should not be the only  rulers, but that all

should rule equally according to their numbers.  And in this way men think that they will secure equality and

freedom  in their state. 

III

Next comes the question, how is this equality to be obtained? Are  we  to assign to a thousand poor men the

property qualifications of  five  hundred rich men? and shall we give the thousand a power equal to  that  of the

five hundred? or, if this is not to be the mode, ought we,  still retaining the same ratio, to take equal numbers

from each and  give them the control of the elections and of the courts? Which,  according to the

democratical notion, is the juster form of the  constitution this or one based on numbers only? Democrats say

that  justice is that to which the majority agree, oligarchs that to which  the wealthier class; in their opinion the

decision should be given  according to the amount of property. In both principles there is  some  inequality and

injustice. For if justice is the will of the  few, any  one person who has more wealth than all the rest of the  rich

put  together, ought, upon the oligarchical principle, to have the  sole  power but this would be tyranny; or if

justice is the will of  the  majority, as I was before saying, they will unjustly confiscate  the  property of the


POLITICS

II 82



Top




Page No 87


wealthy minority. To find a principle of  equality  which they both agree we must inquire into their respective

ideas of  justice. 

Now they agree in saying that whatever is decided by the majority  of  the citizens is to be deemed law.

Granted: but not without some  reserve; since there are two classes out of which a state is composed  the poor

and the rich that is to be deemed law, on which both or  the  greater part of both agree; and if they disagree,

that which is  approved by the greater number, and by those who have the higher  qualification. For example,

suppose that there are ten rich and twenty  poor, and some measure is approved by six of the rich and is

disapproved by fifteen of the poor, and the remaining four of the rich  join with the party of the poor, and the

remaining five of the poor  with that of the rich; in such a case the will of those whose  qualifications, when

both sides are added up, are the greatest, should  prevail. If they turn out to be equal, there is no greater

difficulty  than at present, when, if the assembly or the courts are  divided,  recourse is had to the lot, or to some

similar expedient.  But,  although it may be difficult in theory to know what is just and  equal,  the practical

difficulty of inducing those to forbear who  can, if they  like, encroach, is far greater, for the weaker are always

asking for  equality and justice, but the stronger care for none of  these things. 

IV

Of the four kinds of democracy, as was said in the in the previous  discussion, the best is that which comes

first in order; it is also  the oldest of them all. I am speaking of them according to the natural  classification of

their inhabitants. For the best material of  democracy is an agricultural population; there is no difficulty in

forming a democracy where the mass of the people live by agriculture  or tending of cattle. Being poor, they

have no leisure, and  therefore  do not often attend the assembly, and not having the  necessaries of  life they are

always at work, and do not covet the  property of others.  Indeed, they find their employment pleasanter than

the cares of  government or office where no great gains can be made out  of them, for  the many are more

desirous of gain than of honor. A proof  is that even  the ancient tyrannies were patiently endured by them,  as

they still  endure oligarchies, if they are allowed to work and  are not deprived  of their property; for some of

them grow quickly rich  and the others  are well enough off. Moreover, they have the power of  electing the

magistrates and calling them to account; their  ambition, if they have  any, is thus satisfied; and in some

democracies, although they do not  all share in the appointment of  offices, except through  representatives

elected in turn out of the  whole people, as at  Mantinea; yet, if they have the power of  deliberating, the many

are  contented. Even this form of government may  be regarded as a  democracy, and was such at Mantinea.

Hence it is both  expedient and  customary in the aforementioned type of democracy that  all should  elect to

offices, and conduct scrutinies, and sit in the  lawcourts,  but that the great offices should be filled up by

election  and from  persons having a qualification; the greater requiring a  greater  qualification, or, if there be

no offices for which a  qualification is  required, then those who are marked out by special  ability should be

appointed. Under such a form of government the  citizens are sure to be  governed well (for the offices will

always  be held by the best  persons; the people are willing enough to elect  them and are not  jealous of the

good). The good and the notables  will then be  satisfied, for they will not be governed by men who are  their

inferiors, and the persons elected will rule justly, because  others  will call them to account. Every man should

be responsible to  others,  nor should any one be allowed to do just as he pleases; for  where  absolute freedom

is allowed, there is nothing to restrain the  evil  which is inherent in every man. But the principle of

responsibility  secures that which is the greatest good in states;  the right persons  rule and are prevented from

doing wrong, and the  people have their  due. It is evident that this is the best kind of  democracy, and why?

Because the people are drawn from a certain class.  Some of the ancient  laws of most states were, all of them,

useful with  a view to making  the people husbandmen. They provided either that no  one should possess  more

than a certain quantity of land, or that, if  he did, the land  should not be within a certain distance from the

town  or the  acropolis. Formerly in many states there was a law forbidding  any one  to sell his original

allotment of land. There is a similar law  attributed to Oxylus, which is to the effect that there should be a

certain portion of every man's land on which he could not borrow  money. A useful corrective to the evil of


POLITICS

IV 83



Top




Page No 88


which I am speaking would be  the law of the Aphytaeans, who, although they are numerous, and do not

possess much land, are all of them husbandmen. For their properties  are reckoned in the census; not entire,

but only in such small  portions that even the poor may have more than the amount required. 

Next best to an agricultural, and in many respects similar, are a  pastoral people, who live by their flocks; they

are the best trained  of any for war, robust in body and able to camp out. The people of  whom other

democracies consist are far inferior to them, for their  life is inferior; there is no room for moral excellence in

any of  their employments, whether they be mechanics or traders or laborers.  Besides, people of this class can

readily come to the assembly,  because they are continually moving about in the city and in the  agora; whereas

husbandmen are scattered over the country and do not  meet, or equally feel the want of assembling together.

Where the  territory also happens to extend to a distance from the city, there is  no difficulty in making an

excellent democracy or constitutional  government; for the people are compelled to settle in the country, and

even if there is a town population the assembly ought not to meet,  in  democracies, when the country people

cannot come. We have thus  explained how the first and best form of democracy should be  constituted; it is

clear that the other or inferior sorts will deviate  in a regular order, and the population which is excluded will

at  each  stage be of a lower kind. 

The last form of democracy, that in which all share alike, is one  which cannot be borne by all states, and will

not last long unless  well regulated by laws and customs. The more general causes which tend  to destroy this

or other kinds of government have been pretty fully  considered. In order to constitute such a democracy and

strengthen the  people, the leaders have been in the habit including as many as they  can, and making citizens

not only of those who are legitimate, but  even of the illegitimate, and of those who have only one parent a

citizen, whether father or mother; for nothing of this sort comes  amiss to such a democracy. This is the way

in which demagogues  proceed. Whereas the right thing would be to make no more additions  when the

number of the commonalty exceeds that of the notables and  of  the middle class beyond this not to go. When

in excess of this  point,  the constitution becomes disorderly, and the notables grow  excited and  impatient of

the democracy, as in the insurrection at  Cyrene; for no  notice is taken of a little evil, but when it increases  it

strikes the  eye. Measures like those which Cleisthenes passed  when he wanted to  increase the power of the

democracy at Athens, or  such as were taken  by the founders of popular government at Cyrene,  are useful in

the  extreme form of democracy. Fresh tribes and  brotherhoods should be  established; the private rites of

families  should be restricted and  converted into public ones; in short, every  contrivance should be  adopted

which will mingle the citizens with  one another and get rid of  old connections. Again, the measures  which are

taken by tyrants appear  all of them to be democratic;  such, for instance, as the license  permitted to slaves

(which may be  to a certain extent advantageous)  and also that of women and children,  and the aflowing

everybody to  live as he likes. Such a government will  have many supporters, for  most persons would rather

live in a  disorderly than in a sober manner. 

V

The mere establishment of a democracy is not the only or principal  business of the legislator, or of those who

wish to create such a  state, for any state, however badly constituted, may last one, two, or  three days; a far

greater difficulty is the preservation of it. The  legislator should therefore endeavor to have a firm foundation

according to the principles already laid down concerning the  preservation and destruction of states; he should

guard against the  destructive elements, and should make laws, whether written or  unwritten, which will

contain all the preservatives of states. He must  not think the truly democratical or oligarchical measure to be

that  which will give the greatest amount of democracy or oligarchy, but  that which will make them last

longest. The demagogues of our own  day  often get property confiscated in the lawcourts in order to  please

the people. But those who have the welfare of the state at  heart  should counteract them, and make a law that

the property of  the  condemned should not be public and go into the treasury but be  sacred.  Thus offenders

will be as much afraid, for they will be  punished all  the same, and the people, having nothing to gain, will  not


POLITICS

V 84



Top




Page No 89


be so ready  to condemn the accused. Care should also be taken that  state trials  are as few as possible, and

heavy penalties should be  inflicted on  those who bring groundless accusations; for it is the  practice to  indict,

not members of the popular party, but the  notables, although  the citizens ought to be all attached to the

constitution as well, or  at any rate should not regard their rulers as  enemies. 

Now, since in the last and worst form of democracy the citizens  are very numerous, and can hardly be made

to assemble unless they  are  paid, and to pay them when there are no revenues presses hardly  upon  the

notables (for the money must be obtained by a property tax  and  confiscations and corrupt practices of the

courts, things which  have  before now overthrown many democracies); where, I say, there  are no  revenues,

the government should hold few assemblies, and the  lawcourts should consist of many persons, but sit for a

few days  only. This system has two advantages: first, the rich do not fear  the  expense, even although they are

unpaid themselves when the poor  are  paid; and secondly, causes are better tried, for wealthy  persons,

although they do not like to be long absent from their own  affairs, do  not mind going for a few days to the

lawcourts. Where  there are  revenues the demagogues should not be allowed after their  manner to  distribute

the surplus; the poor are always receiving and  always  wanting more and more, for such help is like water

poured  into a leaky  cask. Yet the true friend of the people should see that  they be not  too poor, for extreme

poverty lowers the character of  the democracy;  measures therefore should be taken which will give them

lasting  prosperity; and as this is equally the interest of all  classes, the  proceeds of the public revenues should

be accumulated and  distributed  among its poor, if possible, in such quantities as may  enable them to  purchase

a little farm, or, at any rate, make a  beginning in trade or  husbandry. And if this benevolence cannot be

extended to all, money  should be distributed in turn according to  tribes or other divisions,  and in the

meantime the rich should pay the  fee for the attendance of  the poor at the necessary assemblies; and  should in

return be excused  from useless public services. By  administering the state in this  spirit the Carthaginians

retain the  affections of the people; their  policy is from time to time to send  some of them into their dependent

towns, where they grow rich. It is  also worthy of a generous and  sensible nobility to divide the poor  amongst

them, and give them the  means of going to work. The example of  the people of Tarentum is also  well

deserving of imitation, for, by  sharing the use of their own  property with the poor, they gain their  good will.

Moreover, they  divide all their offices into two classes,  some of them being elected  by vote, the others by lot;

the latter,  that the people may  participate in them, and the former, that the  state may be better  administered. A

like result may be gained by  dividing the same  offices, so as to have two classes of magistrates,  one chosen

by vote,  the other by lot. 

Enough has been said of the manner in which democracies ought to  be constituted. 

VI

From these considerations there will be no difficulty in seeing  what  should be the constitution of oligarchies.

We have only to reason  from  opposites and compare each form of oligarchy with the  corresponding  form of

democracy. 

The first and best attempered of oligarchies is akin to a  constitutional government. In this there ought to be

two standards  of  qualification; the one high, the other low the lower qualifying  for  the humbler yet

indispensable offices and the higher for the  superior  ones. He who acquires the prescribed qualification

should  have the  rights of citizenship. The number of those admitted should be  such as  will make the entire

governing body stronger than those who  are  excluded, and the new citizen should be always taken out of the

better  class of the people. The principle, narrowed a little, gives  another  form of oligarchy; until at length we

reach the most  cliquish and  tyrannical of them all, answering to the extreme  democracy, which,  being the

worst, requires vigilance in proportion to  its badness. For  as healthy bodies and ships well provided with

sailors may undergo  many mishaps and survive them, whereas sickly  constitutions and rotten  illmanned

ships are ruined by the very least  mistake, so do the worst  forms of government require the greatest  care. The


POLITICS

VI 85



Top




Page No 90


populousness of  democracies generally preserves them (for  e state need not be much  increased,since there is

no necessity tha  number is to democracy in  the place of justice based on proportion);  whereas the

preservation of  an oligarchy clearly depends on an  opposite principle, viz., good  order. 

VII

As there are four chief divisions of the common people  husbandmen, mechanics, retail traders, laborers; so

also there are  four kinds of military forces the cavalry, the heavy infantry, the  light armed troops, the navy.

When the country is adapted for cavalry,  then a strong oligarchy is likely to be established. For the  security  of

the inhabitants depends upon a force of this sort, and  only rich  men can afford to keep horses. The second

form of  oligarchy prevails  when the country is adapted to heavy infantry;  for this service is  better suited to

the rich than to the poor. But  the lightarmed and  the naval element are wholly democratic; and  nowadays,

where they are  numerous, if the two parties quarrel, the  oligarchy are often worsted  by them in the struggle.

A remedy for this  state of things may be  found in the practice of generals who combine a  proper contingent

of  lightarmed troops with cavalry and  heavyarmed. And this is the way  in which the poor get the better of

the rich in civil contests; being  lightly armed, they fight with  advantage against cavalry and heavy  being

lightly armed, they fight  with advantage against cavalry and  heavy infantry. An oligarchy  which raises such a

force out of the  lower classes raises a power  against itself. And therefore, since the  ages of the citizens vary

and  some are older and some younger, the  fathers should have their own  sons, while they are still young,

taught  the agile movements of  lightarmed troops; and these, when they have  been taken out of the  ranks of

the youth, should become lightarmed  warriors in reality. The  oligarchy should also yield a share in the

government to the people,  either, as I said before, to those who have  a property  qualification, or, as in the

case of Thebes, to those who  have  abstained for a certain number of years from mean employments,  or,  as at

Massalia, to men of merit who are selected for their  worthiness,  whether previously citizens or not. The

magistracies of  the highest  rank, which ought to be in the hands of the governing  body, should  have

expensive duties attached to them, and then the  people will not  desire them and will take no offense at the

privileges  of their rulers  when they see that they pay a heavy fine for their  dignity. It is  fitting also that the

magistrates on entering office  should offer  magnificent sacrifices or erect some public edifice, and  then the

people who participate in the entertainments, and see the  city  decorated with votive offerings and buildings,

will not desire an  alteration in the government, and the notables will have memorials  of  their munificence.

This, however, is anything but the fashion of  our  modern oligarchs, who are as covetous of gain as they are of

honor;  oligarchies like theirs may be well described as petty  democracies.  Enough of the manner in which

democracies and oligarchies  should be  organized. 

VIII

Next in order follows the right distribution of offices, their  number, their nature, their duties, of which indeed

we have already  spoken. No state can exist not having the necessary offices, and no  state can be well

administered not having the offices which tend to  preserve harmony and good order. In small states, as we

have already  remarked, there must not be many of them, but in larger there must  be  a larger number, and we

should carefully consider which offices may  properly be united and which separated. 

First among necessary offices is that which has the care of the  market; a magistrate should be appointed to

inspect contracts and to  maintain order. For in every state there must inevitably be buyers and  sellers who

will supply one another's wants; this is the readiest  way  to make a state selfsufficing and so fulfill the

purpose for  which  men come together into one state. A second office of a similar  kind  undertakes the

supervision and embellishment of public and  private  buildings, the maintaining and repairing of houses and

roads, the  prevention of disputes about boundaries, and other concerns  of a like  nature. This is commonly

called the office of City Warden,  and has  various departments, which, in more populous towns, are shared

among  different persons, one, for example, taking charge of the walls,  another of the fountains, a third of


POLITICS

VII 86



Top




Page No 91


harbors. There is another equally  necessary office, and of a similar kind, having to do with the same  matters

without the walls and in the country the magistrates who hold  this office are called Wardens of the country,

or Inspectors of the  woods. Besides these three there is a fourth office of receivers of  taxes, who have under

their charge the revenue which is distributed  among the various departments; these are called Receivers or

Treasurers. Another officer registers all private contracts, and  decisions of the courts, all public indictments,

and also all  preliminary proceedings. This office again is sometimes subdivided, in  which case one officer is

appointed over all the rest. These  officers  are called Recorders or Sacred Recorders, Presidents, and the  like. 

Next to these comes an office of which the duties are the most  necessary and also the most difficult, viz., that

to which is  committed the execution of punishments, or the exaction of fines  from  those who are posted up

according to the registers; and also  the  custody of prisoners. The difficulty of this office arises out  of the

odium which is attached to it; no one will undertake it  unless great  profits are to be made, and any one who

does is loath  to execute the  law. Still the office is necessary; for judicial  decisions are useless  if they take no

effect; and if society cannot  exist without them,  neither can it exist without the execution of  them. It is an

office  which, being so unpopular, should not be  entrusted to one person, but  divided among several taken

from  different courts. In like manner an  effort should be made to  distribute among different persons the

writing up of those who are  on the register of public debtors. Some  sentences should be executed  by the

magistrates also, and in  particular penalties due to the  outgoing magistrates should be exacted  by the

incoming ones; and as  regards those due to magistrates already  in office, when one court has  given

judgement, another should exact  the penalty; for example, the  wardens of the city should exact the  fines

imposed by the wardens of  the agora, and others again should  exact the fines imposed by them.  For penalties

are more likely to be  exacted when less odium attaches  to the exaction of them; but a double  odium is

incurred when the  judges who have passed also execute the  sentence, and if they are  always the executioners,

they will be the  enemies of all. 

In many places, while one magistracy executes the sentence,  another has the custody of the prisoners, as, for

example, 'the  Eleven' at Athens. It is well to separate off the jailorship also, and  try by some device to render

the office less unpopular. For it is  quite as necessary as that of the executioners; but good men do all  they can

to avoid it, and worthless persons cannot safely be trusted  with it; for they themselves require a guard, and are

not fit to guard  others. There ought not therefore to be a single or permanent  officer  set apart for this duty; but

it should be entrusted to the  young,  wherever they are organized into a band or guard, and different

magistrates acting in turn should take charge of it. 

These are the indispensable officers, and should be ranked first;  next in order follow others, equally

necessary, but of higher rank,  and requiring great experience and fidelity. Such are the officers  to  which are

committed the guard of the city, and other military  functions. Not only in time of war but of peace their duty

will be  to  defend the walls and gates, and to muster and marshal the citizens.  In  some states there are many

such offices; in others there are a  few  only, while small states are content with one; these officers  are  called

generals or commanders. Again, if a state has cavalry or  lightarmed troops or archers or a naval force, it will

sometimes  happen that each of these departments has separate officers, who are  called admirals, or generals

of cavalry or of lightarmed troops.  And  there are subordinate officers called naval captains, and captains  of

lightarmed troops and of horse; having others under them: all  these  are included in the department of war.

Thus much of military  command. 

But since many, not to say all, of these offices handle the public  money, there must of necessity be another

office which examines and  audits them, and has no other functions. Such officers are called by  various

names Scrutineers, Auditors, Accountants, Controllers.  Besides all these offices there is another which is

supreme over them,  and to this is often entrusted both the introduction and the  ratification of measures, or at

all events it presides, in a  democracy, over the assembly. For there must be a body which  convenes  the

supreme authority in the state. In some places they are  called  'probuli,' because they hold previous

deliberations, but in a  democracy more commonly 'councillors.' These are the chief political  offices. 


POLITICS

VII 87



Top




Page No 92


Another set of officers is concerned with the maintenance of  religion priests and guardians see to the

preservation and repair of  the temples of the Gods and to other matters of religion. One office  of this sort may

be enough in small places, but in larger ones there  are a great many besides the priesthood; for example,

superintendents  of public worship, guardians of shrines, treasurers of  the sacred  revenues. Nearly connected

with these there are also the  officers  appointed for the performance of the public sacrifices,  except any  which

the law assigns to the priests; such sacrifices  derive their  dignity from the public hearth of the city. They are

sometimes called  archons, sometimes kings, and sometimes prytanes. 

These, then, are the necessary offices, which may be summed up as  follows: offices concerned with matters

of religion, with war, with  the revenue and expenditure, with the market, with the city, with  the  harbors, with

the country; also with the courts of law, with the  records of contracts, with execution of sentences, with

custody of  prisoners, with audits and scrutinies and accounts of magistrates;  lastly, there are those which

preside over the public deliberations of  the state. There are likewise magistracies characteristic of states

which are peaceful and prosperous, and at the same time have a  regard  to good order: such as the offices of

guardians of women,  guardians of  the law, guardians of children, and directors of  gymnastics; also

superintendents of gymnastic and Dionysiac  contests, and of other  similar spectacles. Some of these are

clearly  not democratic offices;  for example, the guardianships of women and  children the poor, not  having

any slaves, must employ both their  women and children as  servants. 

Once more: there are three offices according to whose directions  the  highest magistrates are chosen in certain

states guardians of the  law, probuli, councillors of these, the guardians of the law are an  aristocratical, the

probuli an oligarchical, the council a  democratical institution. Enough of the different kinds of offices. 

BOOK SEVEN

I

HE who would duly inquire about the best form of a state ought  first  to determine which is the most eligible

life; while this remains  uncertain the best form of the state must also be uncertain; for, in  the natural order of

things, those may be expected to lead the best  life who are governed in the best manner of which their

circumstances  admit. We ought therefore to ascertain, first of all,  which is the  most generally eligible life, and

then whether the same  life is or is  not best for the state and for individuals. 

Assuming that enough has been already said in discussions outside  the school concerning the best life, we

will now only repeat what is  contained in them. Certainly no one will dispute the propriety of that  partition of

goods which separates them into three classes, viz.,  external goods, goods of the body, and goods of the soul,

or deny that  the happy man must have all three. For no one would maintain that he  is happy who has not in

him a particle of courage or temperance or  justice or prudence, who is afraid of every insect which flutters

past  him, and will commit any crime, however great, in order to gratify his  lust of meat or drink, who will

sacrifice his dearest friend for the  sake of halfafarthing, and is as feeble and false in mind as a child  or a

madman. These propositions are almost universally acknowledged as  soon as they are uttered, but men differ

about the degree or  relative  superiority of this or that good. Some think that a very  moderate  amount of virtue

is enough, but set no limit to their desires  of  wealth, property, power, reputation, and the like. To whom we

reply  by  an appeal to facts, which easily prove that mankind do not  acquire or  preserve virtue by the help of

external goods, but external  goods by  the help of virtue, and that happiness, whether consisting in  pleasure  or

virtue, or both, is more often found with those who are  most highly  cultivated in their mind and in their

character, and  have only a  moderate share of external goods, than among those who  possess  external goods to

a useless extent but are deficient in higher  qualities; and this is not only matter of experience, but, if  reflected

upon, will easily appear to be in accordance with reason.  For, whereas external goods have a limit, like any

other instrument,  and all things useful are of such a nature that where there is too  much of them they must


POLITICS

BOOK SEVEN 88



Top




Page No 93


either do harm, or at any rate be of no use, to  their possessors, every good of the soul, the greater it is, is also

of greater use, if the epithet useful as well as noble is  appropriate  to such subjects. No proof is required to

show that the  best state of  one thing in relation to another corresponds in degree  of excellence  to the interval

between the natures of which we say that  these very  states are states: so that, if the soul is more noble  than

our  possessions or our bodies, both absolutely and in relation to  us, it  must be admitted that the best state of

either has a similar  ratio to  the other. Again, it is for the sake of the soul that goods  external  and goods of the

body are eligible at all, and all wise men  ought to  choose them for the sake of the soul, and not the soul for

the sake of  them. 

Let us acknowledge then that each one has just so much of  happiness as he has of virtue and wisdom, and of

virtuous and wise  action. God is a witness to us of this truth, for he is happy and  blessed, not by reason of any

external good, but in himself and by  reason of his own nature. And herein of necessity lies the  difference

between good fortune and happiness; for external goods come  of  themselves, and chance is the author of

them, but no one is just or  temperate by or through chance. In like manner, and by a similar train  of argument,

the happy state may be shown to be that which is best and  which acts rightly; and rightly it cannot act without

doing right  actions, and neither individual nor state can do right actions without  virtue and wisdom. Thus the

courage, justice, and wisdom of a state  have the same form and nature as the qualities which give the

individual who possesses them the name of just, wise, or temperate. 

Thus much may suffice by way of preface: for I could not avoid  touching upon these questions, neither could

I go through all the  arguments affecting them; these are the business of another science. 

Let us assume then that the best life, both for individuals and  states, is the life of virtue, when virtue has

external goods enough  for the performance of good actions. If there are any who controvert  our assertion, we

will in this treatise pass them over, and consider  their objections hereafter. 

II

There remains to be discussed the question whether the happiness  of the individual is the same as that of the

state, or different. Here  again there can be no doubt no one denies that they are the same. For  those who

hold that the wellbeing of the individual consists in his  wealth, also think that riches make the happiness of

the whole  state,  and those who value most highly the life of a tyrant deem  that city  the happiest which rules

over the greatest number; while  they who  approve an individual for his virtue say that the more  virtuous a

city  is, the happier it is. Two points here present  themselves for  consideration: first (1), which is the more

eligible  life, that of a  citizen who is a member of a state, or that of an  alien who has no  political ties; and

again (2), which is the best form  of constitution  or the best condition of a state, either on the  supposition that

political privileges are desirable for all, or for  a majority only?  Since the good of the state and not of the

individual  is the proper  subject of political thought and speculation, and we are  engaged in a  political

discussion, while the first of these two points  has a  secondary interest for us, the latter will be the main

subject  of our  inquiry. 

Now it is evident that the form of government is best in which  every  man, whoever he is, can act best and live

happily. But even  those  who agree in thinking that the life of virtue is the most  eligible  raise a question,

whether the life of business and politics  is or is  not more eligible than one which is wholly independent of

external  goods, I mean than a contemplative life, which by some is  maintained  to be the only one worthy of a

philosopher. For these two  lives the  life of the philosopher and the life of the statesman  appear to  have

been preferred by those who have been most keen in the  pursuit of  virtue, both in our own and in other ages.

Which is the  better is a  question of no small moment; for the wise man, like the  wise state,  will necessarily

regulate his life according to the best  end. There  are some who think that while a despotic rule over others  is

the  greatest injustice, to exercise a constitutional rule over  them,  even though not unjust, is a great


POLITICS

II 89



Top




Page No 94


impediment to a man's  individual  wellbeing. Others take an opposite view; they maintain that  the true  life of

man is the practical and political, and that every  virtue  admits of being practiced, quite as much by statesmen

and  rulers as by  private individuals. Others, again, are of opinion that  arbitrary  and tyrannical rule alone

consists with happiness; indeed,  in some  states the entire aim both of the laws and of the constitution  is to

give men despotic power over their neighbors. And, therefore,  although  in most cities the laws may be said

generally to be in a  chaotic  state, still, if they aim at anything, they aim at the  maintenance  of power: thus in

Lacedaemon and Crete the system of  education and the  greater part of the of the laws are framed with a  view

to war. And  in all nations which are able to gratify their  ambition military power  is held in esteem, for

example among the  Scythians and Persians and  Thracians and Celts. 

In some nations there are even laws tending to stimulate the  warlike  virtues, as at Carthage, where we are told

that men obtain the  honor  of wearing as many armlets as they have served campaigns. There  was  once a law

in Macedonia that he who had not killed an enemy should  wear a halter, and among the Scythians no one who

had not slain his  man was allowed to drink out of the cup which was handed round at a  certain feast. Among

the Iberians, a warlike nation, the number of  enemies whom a man has slain is indicated by the number of

obelisks  which are fixed in the earth round his tomb; and there are numerous  practices among other nations of

a like kind, some of them established  by law and others by custom. Yet to a reflecting mind it must appear

very strange that the statesman should be always considering how he  can dominate and tyrannize over others,

whether they will or not.  How  can that which is not even lawful be the business of the statesman  or  the

legislator? Unlawful it certainly is to rule without regard  to  justice, for there may be might where there is no

right. The  other  arts and sciences offer no parallel a physician is not  expected to  persuade or coerce his

patients, nor a pilot the  passengers in his  ship. Yet most men appear to think that the art of  despotic

government  is statesmanship, and what men affirm to be unjust  and inexpedient in  their own case they are not

ashamed of practicing  towards others; they  demand just rule for themselves, but where  other men are

concerned  they care nothing about it. Such behavior is  irrational; unless the  one party is, and the other is not,

born to  serve, in which case men  have a right to command, not indeed all their  fellows, but only those  who

are intended to be subjects; just as we  ought not to hunt mankind,  whether for food or sacrifice, but only the

animals which may be  hunted for food or sacrifice, this is to say,  such wild animals as are  eatable. And surely

there may be a city happy  in isolation, which we  will assume to be wellgoverned (for it is  quite possible that

a city  thus isolated might be welladministered  and have good laws); but such  a city would not be constituted

with any  view to war or the conquest  of enemies all that sort of thing must be  excluded. Hence we see very

plainly that warlike pursuits, although  generally to be deemed  honorable, are not the supreme end of all

things, but only means. And  the good lawgiver should inquire how  states and races of men and  communities

may participate in a good  life, and in the happiness which  is attainable by them. His enactments  will not be

always the same; and  where there are neighbors he will  have to see what sort of studies  should be practiced in

relation to  their several characters, or how  the measures appropriate in  relation to each are to be adopted. The

end at which the best form  of government should aim may be properly  made a matter of future  consideration. 

III

Let us now address those who, while they agree that the life of  virtue is the most eligible, differ about the

manner of practicing it.  For some renounce political power, and think that the life of the  freeman is different

from the life of the statesman and the best of  all; but others think the life of the statesman best. The argument

of  the latter is that he who does nothing cannot do well, and that  virtuous activity is identical with happiness.

To both we say: 'you  are partly right and partly wrong.' first class are right in affirming  that the life of the

freeman is better than the life of the despot;  for there is nothing grand or noble in having the use of a slave, in

so far as he is a slave; or in issuing commands about necessary  things. But it is an error to suppose that every

sort of rule is  despotic like that of a master over slaves, for there is as great a  difference between the rule over

freemen and the rule over slaves as  there is between slavery by nature and freedom by nature, about  which  I

have said enough at the commencement of this treatise. And  it is  equally a mistake to place inactivity above


POLITICS

III 90



Top




Page No 95


action, for  happiness is  activity, and the actions of the just and wise are the  realization of  much that is noble. 

But perhaps some one, accepting these premises, may still maintain  that supreme power is the best of all

things, because the possessors  of it are able to perform the greatest number of noble actions. if so,  the man

who is able to rule, instead of giving up anything to his  neighbor, ought rather to take away his power; and

the father should  make no account of his son, nor the son of his father, nor friend of  friend; they should not

bestow a thought on one another in  comparison  with this higher object, for the best is the most  eligible and

'doing  eligible' and 'doing well' is the best. There  might be some truth in  such a view if we assume that

robbers and  plunderers attain the chief  good. But this can never be; their  hypothesis is false. For the  actions of

a ruler cannot really be  honorable, unless he is as much  superior to other men as a husband  is to a wife, or a

father to his  children, or a master to his  slaves. And therefore he who violates the  law can never recover by

any  success, however great, what he has  already lost in departing from  virtue. For equals the honorable and

the just consist in sharing  alike, as is just and equal. But that the  unequal should be given to  equals, and the

unlike to those who are  like, is contrary to nature,  and nothing which is contrary to nature  is good. If,

therefore,  there is any one superior in virtue and in the  power of performing the  best actions, him we ought to

follow and obey,  but he must have the  capacity for action as well as virtue. 

If we are right in our view, and happiness is assumed to be  virtuous  activity, the active life will be the best,

both for every  city  collectively, and for individuals. Not that a life of action must  necessarily have relation to

others, as some persons think, nor are  those ideas only to be regarded as practical which are pursued for the

sake of practical results, but much more the thoughts and  contemplations which are independent and

complete in themselves; since  virtuous activity, and therefore a certain kind of action, is an  end,  and even in

the case of external actions the directing mind is  most  truly said to act. Neither, again, is it necessary that

states  which  are cut off from others and choose to live alone should be  inactive;  for activity, as well as other

things, may take place by  sections;  there are many ways in which the sections of a state act  upon one  another.

The same thing is equally true of every  individual. If this  were otherwise, God and the universe, who have  no

external actions  over and above their own energies, would be far  enough from  perfection. Hence it is evident

that the same life is best  for each  individual, and for states and for mankind collectively 

IV

Thus far by way of introduction. In what has preceded I have  discussed other forms of government; in what

remains the first point  to be considered is what should be the conditions of the ideal or  perfect state; for the

perfect state cannot exist without a due supply  of the means of life. And therefore we must presuppose many

purely  imaginary conditions, but nothing impossible. There will be a  certain  number of citizens, a country in

which to place them, and  the like. As  the weaver or shipbuilder or any other artisan must  have the material

proper for his work (and in proportion as this is  better prepared, so  will the result of his art be nobler), so the

statesman or legislator  must also have the materials suited to him. 

First among the materials required by the statesman is population:  he will consider what should be the

number and character of the  citizens, and then what should be the size and character of the  country. Most

persons think that a state in order to be happy ought to  be large; but even if they are right, they have no idea

what is a  large and what a small state. For they judge of the size of the city  by the number of the inhabitants;

whereas they ought to regard, not  their number, but their power. A city too, like an individual, has a  work to

do; and that city which is best adapted to the fulfillment  of  its work is to be deemed greatest, in the same

sense of the word  great  in which Hippocrates might be called greater, not as a man,  but as a  physician, than

some one else who was taller And even if we  reckon  greatness by numbers, we ought not to include

everybody, for  there  must always be in cities a multitude of slaves and sojourners  and  foreigners; but we

should include those only who are members of  the  state, and who form an essential part of it. The number of

the  latter  is a proof of the greatness of a city; but a city which  produces  numerous artisans and comparatively


POLITICS

IV 91



Top




Page No 96


few soldiers cannot be  great, for  a great city is not to be confounded with a populous one.  Moreover,

experience shows that a very populous city can rarely, if  ever, be  well governed; since all cities which have a

reputation for  good  government have a limit of population. We may argue on grounds of  reason, and the

same result will follow. For law is order, and good  law is good order; but a very great multitude cannot be

orderly: to  introduce order into the unlimited is the work of a divine power of  such a power as holds

together the universe. Beauty is realized in  number and magnitude, and the state which combines magnitude

with good  order must necessarily be the most beautiful. To the size of states  there is a limit, as there is to

other things, plants, animals,  implements; for none of these retain their natural power when they are  too large

or too small, but they either wholly lose their nature, or  are spoiled. For example, a ship which is only a span

long will not be  a ship at all, nor a ship a quarter of a mile long; yet there may be a  ship of a certain size,

either too large or too small, which will  still be a ship, but bad for sailing. In like manner a state when

composed of too few is not, as a state ought to be, selfsufficing;  when of too many, though selfsufficing in

all mere necessaries, as  a  nation may be, it is not a state, being almost incapable of  constitutional government.

For who can be the general of such a vast  multitude, or who the herald, unless he have the voice of a Stentor? 

A state, then, only begins to exist when it has attained a  population sufficient for a good life in the political

community: it  may indeed, if it somewhat exceed this number, be a greater state.  But, as I was saying, there

must be a limit. What should be the  limit  will be easily ascertained by experience. For both governors and

governed have duties to perform; the special functions of a governor  to command and to judge. But if the

citizens of a state are to judge  and to distribute offices according to merit, then they must know each  other's

characters; where they do not possess this knowledge, both the  election to offices and the decision of lawsuits

will go wrong. When  the population is very large they are manifestly settled at haphazard,  which clearly

ought not to be. Besides, in an overpopulous state  foreigners and metics will readily acquire the rights of

citizens, for  who will find them out? Clearly then the best limit of the  population  of a state is the largest

number which suffices for the  purposes of  life, and can be taken in at a single view. Enough  concerning the

size  of a state. 

V

Much the same principle will apply to the territory of the state:  every one would agree in praising the territory

which is most entirely  selfsufficing; and that must be the territory which is allproducing,  for to have all

things and to want nothing is sufficiency. In size and  extent it should be such as may enable the inhabitants to

live at once  temperately and liberally in the enjoyment of leisure. Whether we  are  right or wrong in laying

down this limit we will inquire more  precisely hereafter, when we have occasion to consider what is the  right

use of property and wealth: a matter which is much disputed,  because men are inclined to rush into one of

two extremes, some into  meanness, others into luxury. 

It is not difficult to determine the general character of the  territory which is required (there are, however,

some points on  which  military authorities should be heard); it should be difficult of  access to the enemy, and

easy of egress to the inhabitants. Further,  we require that the land as well as the inhabitants of whom we were

just now speaking should be taken in at a single view, for a country  which is easily seen can be easily

protected. As to the position of  the city, if we could have what we wish, it should be well situated in  regard

both to sea and land. This then is one principle, that it  should be a convenient center for the protection of the

whole country:  the other is, that it should be suitable for receiving the fruits of  the soil, and also for the

bringing in of timber and any other  products that are easily transported. 

VI

Whether a communication with the sea is beneficial to a  wellordered  state or not is a question which has

often been asked. It  is argued  that the introduction of strangers brought up under other  laws, and  the increase


POLITICS

V 92



Top




Page No 97


of population, will be adverse to good order;  the  increase arises from their using the sea and having a crowd

of  merchants coming and going, and is inimical to good government.  Apart  from these considerations, it

would be undoubtedly better,  both with a  view to safety and to the provision of necessaries, that  the city and

territory should be connected with the sea; the defenders  of a  country, if they are to maintain themselves

against an enemy,  should  be easily relieved both by land and by sea; and even if they  are not  able to attack by

sea and land at once, they will have less  difficulty  in doing mischief to their assailants on one element, if  they

themselves can use both. Moreover, it is necessary that they  should  import from abroad what is not found in

their own country,  and that  they should export what they have in excess; for a city ought  to be a  market, not

indeed for others, but for herself. 

Those who make themselves a market for the world only do so for  the sake of revenue, and if a state ought

not to desire profit of this  kind it ought not to have such an emporium. Nowadays we often see in  countries

and cities dockyards and harbors very conveniently placed  outside the city, but not too far off; and they are

kept in dependence  by walls and similar fortifications. Cities thus situated manifestly  reap the benefit of

intercourse with their ports; and any harm which  is likely to accrue may be easily guarded against by the

laws, which  will pronounce and determine who may hold communication with one  another, and who may

not. 

There can be no doubt that the possession of a moderate naval  force is advantageous to a city; the city should

be formidable not  only to its own citizens but to some of its neighbors, or, if  necessary, able to assist them by

sea as well as by land. The proper  number or magnitude of this naval force is relative to the character  of the

state; for if her function is to take a leading part in  politics, her naval power should be commensurate with the

scale of her  enterprises. The population of the state need not be much increased,  since there is no necessity

that the sailors should be citizens: the  marines who have the control and command will be freemen, and

belong  also to the infantry; and wherever there is a dense population of  Perioeci and husbandmen, there will

always be sailors more than  enough. Of this we see instances at the present day. The city of  Heraclea, for

example, although small in comparison with many  others,  can man a considerable fleet. Such are our

conclusions  respecting the  territory of the state, its harbors, its towns, its  relations to the  sea, and its maritime

power. 

VII

Having spoken of the number of the citizens, we will proceed to  speak of what should be their character. This

is a subject which can  be easily understood by any one who casts his eye on the more  celebrated states of

Hellas, and generally on the distribution of  races in the habitable world. Those who live in a cold climate and

in  Europe are full of spirit, but wanting in intelligence and skill;  and  therefore they retain comparative

freedom, but have no political  organization, and are incapable of ruling over others. Whereas the  natives of

Asia are intelligent and inventive, but they are wanting in  spirit, and therefore they are always in a state of

subjection and  slavery. But the Hellenic race, which is situated between them, is  likewise intermediate in

character, being highspirited and also  intelligent. Hence it continues free, and is the bestgoverned of  any

nation, and, if it could be formed into one state, would be able  to  rule the world. There are also similar

differences in the different  tribes of Hellas; for some of them are of a onesided nature, and  are  intelligent or

courageous only, while in others there is a happy  combination of both qualities. And clearly those whom the

legislator  will most easily lead to virtue may be expected to be both intelligent  and courageous. Some say that

the guardians should be friendly towards  those whom they know, fierce towards those whom they do not

know. Now,  passion is the quality of the soul which begets friendship and enables  us to love; notably the

spirit within us is more stirred against our  friends and acquaintances than against those who are unknown to

us,  when we think that we are despised by them; for which reason  Archilochus, complaining of his friends,

very naturally addresses  his  soul in these words: 


POLITICS

VII 93



Top




Page No 98


For surely thou art plagued on account of friends. 

The power of command and the love of freedom are in all men based  upon this quality, for passion is

commanding and invincible. Nor is it  right to say that the guardians should be fierce towards those whom

they do not know, for we ought not to be out of temper with any one;  and a lofty spirit is not fierce by nature,

but only when excited  against evildoers. And this, as I was saying before, is a feeling  which men show most

strongly towards their friends if they think  they  have received a wrong at their hands: as indeed is reasonable;

for,  besides the actual injury, they seem to be deprived of a  benefit by  those who owe them one. Hence the

saying: 

Cruel is the strife of brethren,  and again: 

They who love in excess also hate in excess. 

Thus we have nearly determined the number and character of the  citizens of our state, and also the size and

nature of their  territory. I say 'nearly,' for we ought not to require the same  minuteness in theory as in the

facts given by perception. 

VIII

As in other natural compounds the conditions of a composite whole  are not necessarily organic parts of it, so

in a state or in any other  combination forming a unity not everything is a part, which is a  necessary condition.

The members of an association have necessarily  some one thing the same and common to all, in which they

share equally  or unequally for example, food or land or any other thing. But where  there are two things of

which one is a means and the other an end,  they have nothing in common except that the one receives what

the  other produces. Such, for example, is the relation which workmen and  tools stand to their work; the house

and the builder have nothing in  common, but the art of the builder is for the sake of the house. And  so states

require property, but property, even though living beings  are included in it, is no part of a state; for a state is

not a  community of living beings only, but a community of equals, aiming  at  the best life possible. Now,

whereas happiness is the highest good,  being a realization and perfect practice of virtue, which some can

attain, while others have little or none of it, the various  qualities  of men are clearly the reason why there are

various kinds of  states  and many forms of government; for different men seek after  happiness  in different

ways and by different means, and so make for  themselves  different modes of life and forms of government.

We must  see also how  many things are indispensable to the existence of a  state, for what we  call the parts of a

state will be found among the  indispensables. Let  us then enumerate the functions of a state, and we  shall

easily elicit  what we want: 

First, there must be food; secondly, arts, for life requires many  instruments; thirdly, there must be arms, for

the members of a  community have need of them, and in their own hands, too, in order  to  maintain authority

both against disobedient subjects and against  external assailants; fourthly, there must be a certain amount of

revenue, both for internal needs, and for the purposes of war;  fifthly, or rather first, there must be a care of

religion which is  commonly called worship; sixthly, and most necessary of all there must  be a power of

deciding what is for the public interest, and what is  just in men's dealings with one another. 

These are the services which every state may be said to need. For  a state is not a mere aggregate of persons,

but a union of them  sufficing for the purposes of life; and if any of these things be  wanting, it is as we

maintain impossible that the community can be  absolutely selfsufficing. A state then should be framed with

a view  to the fulfillment of these functions. There must be husbandmen to  procure food, and artisans, and a

warlike and a wealthy class, and  priests, and judges to decide what is necessary and expedient. 


POLITICS

VIII 94



Top




Page No 99


IX

Having determined these points, we have in the next place to  consider whether all ought to share in every sort

of occupation. Shall  every man be at once husbandman, artisan, councillor, judge, or  shall  we suppose the

several occupations just mentioned assigned to  different persons? or, thirdly, shall some employments be

assigned  to  individuals and others common to all? The same arrangement,  however,  does not occur in every

constitution; as we were saying,  all may be  shared by all, or not all by all, but only by some; and  hence arise

the differences of constitutions, for in democracies all  share in all,  in oligarchies the opposite practice

prevails. Now,  since we are here  speaking of the best form of government, i.e.,  that under which the  state will

be most happy (and happiness, as has  been already said,  cannot exist without virtue), it clearly follows  that in

the state  which is best governed and possesses men who are  just absolutely, and  not merely relatively to the

principle of the  constitution, the  citizens must not lead the life of mechanics or  tradesmen, for such a  life is

ignoble, and inimical to virtue. Neither  must they be  husbandmen, since leisure is necessary both for the

development of  virtue and the performance of political duties. 

Again, there is in a state a class of warriors, and another of  councillors, who advise about the expedient and

determine matters of  law, and these seem in an especial manner parts of a state. Now,  should these two

classes be distinguished, or are both functions to be  assigned to the same persons? Here again there is no

difficulty in  seeing that both functions will in one way belong to the same, in  another, to different persons. To

different persons in so far as these  i.e., the physical and the employments are suited to different  primes  of life,

for the one requires mental wisdom and the other  strength.  But on the other hand, since it is an impossible

thing  that those who  are able to use or to resist force should be willing to  remain always  in subjection, from

this point of view the persons are  the same; for  those who carry arms can always determine the fate of  the

constitution. It remains therefore that both functions should be  entrusted by the ideal constitution to the same

persons, not, however,  at the same time, but in the order prescribed by nature, who has given  to young men

strength and to older men wisdom. Such a distribution  of  duties will be expedient and also just, and is

founded upon a  principle of conformity to merit. Besides, the ruling class should  be  the owners of property,

for they are citizens, and the citizens  of a  state should be in good circumstances; whereas mechanics or any

other  class which is not a producer of virtue have no share in the  state.  This follows from our first principle,

for happiness cannot  exist  without virtue, and a city is not to be termed happy in regard  to a  portion of the

citizens, but in regard to them all. And clearly  property should be in their hands, since the husbandmen will

of  necessity be slaves or barbarian Perioeci. 

Of the classes enumerated there remain only the priests, and the  manner in which their office is to be

regulated is obvious. No  husbandman or mechanic should be appointed to it; for the Gods  should  receive

honor from the citizens only. Now since the body of the  citizen is divided into two classes, the warriors and

the  councillors  and it is beseeming that the worship of the Gods should be  duly  performed, and also a rest

provided in their service for those  who  from age have given up active life, to the old men of these two  classes

should be assigned the duties of the priesthood. 

We have shown what are the necessary conditions, and what the  parts of a state: husbandmen, craftsmen, and

laborers of an kinds  are  necessary to the existence of states, but the parts of the state  are  the warriors and

councillors. And these are distinguished  severally  from one another, the distinction being in some cases

permanent, in  others not. 

X

It is not a new or recent discovery of political philosophers that  the state ought to be divided into classes, and

that the warriors  should be separated from the husbandmen. The system has continued in  Egypt and in Crete

to this day, and was established, as tradition  says, by a law of Sesostris in Egypt and of Minos in Crete. The


POLITICS

IX 95



Top




Page No 100


institution of common tables also appears to be of ancient date, being  in Crete as old as the reign of Minos,

and in Italy far older. The  Italian historians say that there was a certain Italus, king of  Oenotria, from whom

the Oenotrians were called Italians, and who  gave  the name of Italy to the promontory of Europe lying within

the  Scylletic and Lametic Gulfs, which are distant from one another only  half a day's journey. They say that

this Italus converted the  Oenotrians from shepherds into husbandmen, and besides other laws  which he gave

them, was the founder of their common meals; even in our  day some who are derived from him retain this

institution and  certain  other laws of his. On the side of Italy towards Tyrrhenia  dwelt the  Opici, who are now,

as of old, called Ausones; and on the  side towards  Iapygia and the Ionian Gulf, in the district called  Siritis,

the  Chones, who are likewise of Oenotrian race. From this  part of the  world originally came the institution of

common tables;  the separation  into castes from Egypt, for the reign of Sesostris is  of far greater  antiquity than

that of Minos. It is true indeed that  these and many  other things have been invented several times over in  the

course of  ages, or rather times without number; for necessity  may be supposed to  have taught men the

inventions which were  absolutely required, and  when these were provided, it was natural that  other things

which would  adorn and enrich life should grow up by  degrees. And we may infer that  in political institutions

the same rule  holds. Egypt witnesses to the  antiquity of all these things, for the  Egyptians appear to be of all

people the most ancient; and they have  laws and a regular constitution  existing from time immemorial. We

should therefore make the best use  of what has been already  discovered, and try to supply defects. 

I have already remarked that the land ought to belong to those who  possess arms and have a share in the

government, and that the  husbandmen ought to be a class distinct from them; and I have  determined what

should be the extent and nature of the territory.  Let  me proceed to discuss the distribution of the land, and the

character  of the agricultural class; for I do not think that  property ought to  be common, as some maintain, but

only that by  friendly consent there  should be a common use of it; and that no  citizen should be in want of

subsistence. 

As to common meals, there is a general agreement that a well  ordered  city should have them; and we will

hereafter explain what are  our  own reasons for taking this view. They ought, however, to be open  to  all the

citizens. And yet it is not easy for the poor to contribute  the requisite sum out of their private means, and to

provide also  for  their household. The expense of religious worship should  likewise be a  public charge. The

land must therefore be divided into  two parts, one  public and the other private, and each part should be

subdivided, part  of the public land being appropriated to the  service of the Gods, and  the other part used to

defray the cost of the  common meals; while of  the private land, part should be near the  border, and the other

near  the city, so that, each citizen having  two lots, they may all of them  have land in both places; there is

justice and fairness in such a  division, and it tends to inspire  unanimity among the people in their  border

wars. Where there is not  this arrangement some of them are too  ready to come to blows with  their neighbors,

while others are so  cautious that they quite lose the  sense of honor. Wherefore there is a  law in some places

which  forbids those who dwell near the border to  take part in public  deliberations about wars with neighbors,

on the  ground that their  interests will pervert their judgment. For the  reasons already  mentioned, then, the

land should be divided in the  manner described.  The very best thing of all would be that the  husbandmen

should be  slaves taken from among men who are not all of  the same race and not  spirited, for if they have no

spirit they will  be better suited for  their work, and there will be no danger of their  making a  revolution. The

next best thing would be that they should be  Perioeci of foreign race, and of a like inferior nature; some of

them  should be the slaves of individuals, and employed in the  private  estates of men of property, the

remainder should be the  property of  the state and employed on the common land. I will  hereafter explain

what is the proper treatment of slaves, and why it  is expedient that  liberty should be always held out to them

as the  reward of their  services. 

XI

We have already said that the city should be open to the land and  to  the sea, and to the whole country as far as


POLITICS

XI 96



Top




Page No 101


possible. In respect of  the place itself our wish would be that its situation should be  fortunate in four things.

The first, health this is a necessity:  cities which lie towards the east, and are blown upon by winds  coming

from the east, are the healthiest; next in healthfulness are  those  which are sheltered from the north wind, for

they have a  milder  winter. The site of the city should likewise be convenient both  for  political administration

and for war. With a view to the latter it  should afford easy egress to the citizens, and at the same time be

inaccessible and difficult of capture to enemies. There should be a  natural abundance of springs and fountains

in the town, or, if there  is a deficiency of them, great reservoirs may be established for the  collection of

rainwater, such as will not fail when the inhabitants  are cut off from the country by by war. Special care

should be taken  of the health of the inhabitants, which will depend chiefly on the  healthiness of the locality

and of the quarter to which they are  exposed, and secondly, on the use of pure water; this latter point  is  by no

means a secondary consideration. For the elements which we  use  most and oftenest for the support of the

body contribute most to  health, and among these are water and air. Wherefore, in all wise  states, if there is a

want of pure water, and the supply is not all  equally good, the drinking water ought to be separated from that

which  is used for other purposes. 

As to strongholds, what is suitable to different forms of  government  varies: thus an acropolis is suited to an

oligarchy or a  monarchy, but  a plain to a democracy; neither to an aristocracy, but  rather a number  of strong

places. The arrangement of private houses is  considered to  be more agreeable and generally more convenient,

if the  streets are  regularly laid out after the modern fashion which  Hippodamus  introduced, but for security in

war the antiquated mode of  building,  which made it difficult for strangers to get out of a town  and for

assailants to find their way in, is preferable. A city should  therefore adopt both plans of building: it is

possible to arrange  the  houses irregularly, as husbandmen plant their vines in what are  called  'clumps.' The

whole town should not be laid out in straight  lines, but  only certain quarters and regions; thus security and

beauty  will be  combined. 

As to walls, those who say that cities making any pretension to  military virtue should not have them, are quite

out of date in their  notions; and they may see the cities which prided themselves on this  fancy confuted by

facts. True, there is little courage shown in  seeking for safety behind a rampart when an enemy is similar in

character and not much superior in number; but the superiority of  the  besiegers may be and often is too much

both for ordinary human  valor  and for that which is found only in a few; and if they are to be  saved  and to

escape defeat and outrage, the strongest wall will be the  truest soldierly precaution, more especially now that

missiles and  siege engines have been brought to such perfection. To have no walls  would be as foolish as to

choose a site for a town in an exposed  country, and to level the heights; or as if an individual were to  leave

his house unwalled, lest the inmates should become cowards.  Nor  must we forget that those who have their

cities surrounded by  walls  may either take advantage of them or not, but cities which are  unwalled have no

choice. 

If our conclusions are just, not only should cities have walls,  but care should be taken to make them

ornamental, as well as useful  for warlike purposes, and adapted to resist modern inventions. For  as  the

assailants of a city do all they can to gain an advantage, so  the  defenders should make use of any means of

defense which have  been  already discovered, and should devise and invent others, for when  men  are well

prepared no enemy even thinks of attacking them. 

XII

As the walls are to be divided by guardhouses and towers built at  suitable intervals, and the body of citizens

must be distributed at  common tables, the idea will naturally occur that we should  establish  some of the

common tables in the guardhouses. These might be  arranged  as has been suggested; while the principal

common tables of  the  magistrates will occupy a suitable place, and there also will be  the  buildings

appropriated to religious worship except in the case  of  those rites which the law or the Pythian oracle has


POLITICS

XII 97



Top




Page No 102


restricted to a  special locality. The site should be a spot seen far and wide, which  gives due elevation to virtue

and towers over the neighborhood.  Below  this spot should be established an agora, such as that which the

Thessalians call the 'freemen's agora'; from this all trade should  be  excluded, and no mechanic, husbandman,

or any such person allowed  to  enter, unless he be summoned by the magistrates. It would be a  charming use

of the place, if the gymnastic exercises of the elder men  were performed there. For in this noble practice

different ages should  be separated, and some of the magistrates should stay with the boys,  while the

grownup men remain with the magistrates; for the presence  of the magistrates is the best mode of inspiring

true modesty and  ingenuous fear. There should also be a traders' agora, distinct and  apart from the other, in a

situation which is convenient for the  reception of goods both by sea and land. 

But in speaking of the magistrates we must not forget another  section of the citizens, viz., the priests, for

whom public tables  should likewise be provided in their proper place near the temples.  The magistrates who

deal with contracts, indictments, summonses, and  the like, and those who have the care of the agora and of

the city,  respectively, ought to be established near an agora and some public  place of meeting; the

neighborhood of the traders' agora will be a  suitable spot; the upper agora we devote to the life of leisure, the

other is intended for the necessities of trade. 

The same order should prevail in the country, for there too the  magistrates, called by some 'Inspectors of

Forests' and by others  'Wardens of the Country,' must have guardhouses and common tables  while they are on

duty; temples should also be scattered throughout  the country, dedicated, some to Gods, and some to heroes. 

But it would be a waste of time for us to linger over details like  these. The difficulty is not in imagining but in

carrying them out. We  may talk about them as much as we like, but the execution of them will  depend upon

fortune. Wherefore let us say no more about these  matters  for the present. 

XIII

Returning to the constitution itself, let us seek to determine out  of what and what sort of elements the state

which is to be happy and  wellgoverned should be composed. There are two things in which all  which all

wellbeing consists: one of them is the choice of a right  end and aim of action, and the other the discovery of

the actions  which are means towards it; for the means and the end may agree or  disagree. Sometimes the right

end is set before men, but in practice  they fail to attain it; in other cases they are successful in all  the  means,

but they propose to themselves a bad end; and sometimes  they  fail in both. Take, for example, the art of

medicine;  physicians do  not always understand the nature of health, and also the  means which  they use may

not effect the desired end. In all arts and  sciences both  the end and the means should be equally within our

control. 

The happiness and wellbeing which all men manifestly desire, some  have the power of attaining, but to

others, from some accident or  defect of nature, the attainment of them is not granted; for a good  life requires

a supply of external goods, in a less degree when men  are in a good state, in a greater degree when they are in

a lower  state. Others again, who possess the conditions of happiness, go  utterly wrong from the first in the

pursuit of it. But since our  object is to discover the best form of government, that, namely, under  which a city

will be best governed, and since the city is best  governed which has the greatest opportunity of obtaining

happiness, it  is evident that we must clearly ascertain the nature of happiness. 

We maintain, and have said in the Ethics, if the arguments there  adduced are of any value, that happiness is

the realization and  perfect exercise of virtue, and this not conditional, but absolute.  And I used the term

'conditional' to express that which is  indispensable, and 'absolute' to express that which is good in itself.  Take

the case of just actions; just punishments and chastisements do  indeed spring from a good principle, but they

are good only because we  cannot do without them it would be better that neither individuals  nor states


POLITICS

XIII 98



Top




Page No 103


should need anything of the sort but actions which aim  at  honor and advantage are absolutely the best. The

conditional action  is  only the choice of a lesser evil; whereas these are the  foundation and  creation of good. A

good man may make the best even  of poverty and  disease, and the other ills of life; but he can only  attain

happiness  under the opposite conditions (for this also has been  determined in  accordance with ethical

arguments, that the good man  is he for whom,  because he is virtuous, the things that are absolutely  good are

good;  it is also plain that his use of these goods must be  virtuous and in  the absolute sense good). This makes

men fancy that  external goods are  the cause of happiness, yet we might as well say  that a brilliant

performance on the lyre was to be attributed to the  instrument and not  to the skill of the performer. 

It follows then from what has been said that some things the  legislator must find ready to his hand in a state,

others he must  provide. And therefore we can only say: May our state be constituted  in such a manner as to

be blessed with the goods of which fortune  disposes (for we acknowledge her power): whereas virtue and

goodness  in the state are not a matter of chance but the result of knowledge  and purpose. A city can be

virtuous only when the citizens who have  a  share in the government are virtuous, and in our state all the

citizens share in the government; let us then inquire how a man  becomes virtuous. For even if we could

suppose the citizen body to  be  virtuous, without each of them being so, yet the latter would be  better, for in

the virtue of each the virtue of all is involved. 

There are three things which make men good and virtuous; these are  nature, habit, rational principle. In the

first place, every one  must  be born a man and not some other animal; so, too, he must have  a  certain

character, both of body and soul. But some qualities there  is  no use in having at birth, for they are altered by

habit, and there  are some gifts which by nature are made to be turned by habit to  good  or bad. Animals lead

for the most part a life of nature, although  in  lesser particulars some are influenced by habit as well. Man has

rational principle, in addition, and man only. Wherefore nature,  habit, rational principle must be in harmony

with one another; for  they do not always agree; men do many things against habit and nature,  if rational

principle persuades them that they ought. We have  already  determined what natures are likely to be most

easily molded by  the  hands of the legislator. An else is the work of education; we  learn  some things by habit

and some by instruction. 

XIV

Since every political society is composed of rulers and subjects  let  us consider whether the relations of one to

the other should  interchange or be permanent. For the education of the citizens will  necessarily vary with the

answer given to this question. Now, if  some  men excelled others in the same degree in which gods and heroes

are  supposed to excel mankind in general (having in the first place  a  great advantage even in their bodies, and

secondly in their  minds), so  that the superiority of the governors was undisputed and  patent to  their subjects,

it would clearly be better that once for  an the one  class should rule and the other serve. But since this is

unattainable,  and kings have no marked superiority over their  subjects, such as  Scylax affirms to be found

among the Indians, it  is obviously  necessary on many grounds that all the citizens alike  should take  their turn

of governing and being governed. Equality  consists in the  same treatment of similar persons, and no

government  can stand which  is not founded upon justice. For if the government  be unjust every one  in the

country unites with the governed in the  desire to have a  revolution, and it is an impossibility that the  members

of the  government can be so numerous as to be stronger than  all their enemies  put together. Yet that

governors should excel  their subjects is  undeniable. How all this is to be effected, and in  what way they will

respectively share in the government, the  legislator has to consider.  The subject has been already mentioned.

Nature herself has provided  the distinction when she made a difference  between old and young  within the

same species, of whom she fitted  the one to govern and the  other to be governed. No one takes offense  at

being governed when he  is young, nor does he think himself better  than his governors,  especially if he will

enjoy the same privilege  when he reaches the  required age. 


POLITICS

XIV 99



Top




Page No 104


We conclude that from one point of view governors and governed are  identical, and from another different.

And therefore their education  must be the same and also different. For he who would learn to command  well

must, as men say, first of all learn to obey. As I observed in  the first part of this treatise, there is one rule

which is for the  sake of the rulers and another rule which is for the sake of the  ruled; the former is a despotic,

the latter a free government. Some  commands differ not in the thing commanded, but in the intention with

which they are imposed. Wherefore, many apparently menial offices are  an honor to the free youth by whom

they are performed; for actions do  not differ as honorable or dishonorable in themselves so much as in  the

end and intention of them. But since we say that the virtue of  the citizen and ruler is the same as that of the

good man, and that  the same person must first be a subject and then a ruler, the  legislator has to see that they

become good men, and by what means  this may be accomplished, and what is the end of the perfect life. 

Now the soul of man is divided into two parts, one of which has a  rational principle in itself, and the other,

not having a rational  principle in itself, is able to obey such a principle. And we call a  man in any way good

because he has the virtues of these two parts.  In  which of them the end is more likely to be found is no matter

of  doubt  to those who adopt our division; for in the world both of nature  and  of art the inferior always exists

for the sake of the better or  superior, and the better or superior is that which has a rational  principle. This

principle, too, in our ordinary way of speaking, is  divided into two kinds, for there is a practical and a

speculative  principle. This part, then, must evidently be similarly divided. And  there must be a corresponding

division of actions; the actions of  the  naturally better part are to be preferred by those who have it  in  their

power to attain to two out of the three or to all, for that  is  always to every one the most eligible which is the

highest  attainable  by him. The whole of life is further divided into two  parts, business  and leisure, war and

peace, and of actions some aim at  what is  necessary and useful, and some at what is honorable. And the

preference given to one or the other class of actions must necessarily  be like the preference given to one or

other part of the soul and  its  actions over the other; there must be war for the sake of peace,  business for the

sake of leisure, things useful and necessary for  the  sake of things honorable. All these points the statesman

should  keep  in view when he frames his laws; he should consider the parts  of the  soul and their functions, and

above all the better and the end;  he  should also remember the diversities of human lives and actions.  For  men

must be able to engage in business and go to war, but  leisure and  peace are better; they must do what is

necessary and  indeed what is  useful, but what is honorable is better. On such  principles children  and persons

of every age which requires  education should be trained.  Whereas even the Hellenes of the  present day who

are reputed to be  best governed, and the legislators  who gave them their constitutions,  do not appear to have

framed  their governments with a regard to the  best end, or to have given them  laws and education with a view

to all  the virtues, but in a vulgar  spirit have fallen back on those which  promised to be more useful  and

profitable. Many modern writers have  taken a similar view: they  commend the Lacedaemonian constitution,

and  praise the legislator  for making conquest and war his sole aim, a  doctrine which may be  refuted by

argument and has long ago been  refuted by facts. For most  men desire empire in the hope of  accumulating the

goods of fortune;  and on this ground Thibron and all  those who have written about the  Lacedaemonian

constitution have  praised their legislator, because  the Lacedaemonians, by being trained  to meet dangers,

gained great  power. But surely they are not a happy  people now that their empire  has passed away, nor was

their legislator  right. How ridiculous is the  result, if, when they are continuing in  the observance of his laws

and  no one interferes with them, they have  lost the better part of life!  These writers further err about the sort

of government which the  legislator should approve, for the government  of freemen is nobler and  implies

more virtue than despotic government.  Neither is a city to  be deemed happy or a legislator to be praised

because he trains his  citizens to conquer and obtain dominion over  their neighbors, for  there is great evil in

this. On a similar  principle any citizen who  could, should obviously try to obtain the  power in his own state

the crime which the Lacedaemonians accuse king  Pausanias of  attempting, although he had so great honor

already. No  such  principle and no law having this object is either statesmanlike  or  useful or right. For the

same things are best both for individuals  and  for states, and these are the things which the legislator ought to

implant in the minds of his citizens. 


POLITICS

XIV 100



Top




Page No 105


Neither should men study war with a view to the enslavement of  those  who do not deserve to be enslaved; but

first of all they should  provide against their own enslavement, and in the second place  obtain  empire for the

good of the governed, and not for the sake of  exercising a general despotism, and in the third place they

should  seek to be masters only over those who deserve to be slaves. Facts, as  well as arguments, prove that

the legislator should direct all his  military and other measures to the provision of leisure and the

establishment of peace. For most of these military states are safe  only while they are at war, but fall when

they have acquired their  empire; like unused iron they lose their temper in time of peace.  And  for this the

legislator is to blame, he never having taught them  how  to lead the life of peace. 

XV

Since the end of individuals and of states is the same, the end of  the best man and of the best constitution

must also be the same; it is  therefore evident that there ought to exist in both of them the  virtues of leisure;

for peace, as has been often repeated, is the  end  of war, and leisure of toil. But leisure and cultivation may be

promoted, not only by those virtues which are practiced in leisure,  but also by some of those which are useful

to business. For many  necessaries of life have to be supplied before we can have leisure.  Therefore a city

must be temperate and brave, and able to endure:  for  truly, as the proverb says, 'There is no leisure for slaves,'

and  those who cannot face danger like men are the slaves of any  invader.  Courage and endurance are required

for business and  philosophy for  leisure, temperance and justice for both, and more  especially in times  of

peace and leisure, for war compels men to be  just and temperate,  whereas the enjoyment of good fortune and

the  leisure which comes with  peace tend to make them insolent. Those  then who seem to be the  bestoff and

to be in the possession of  every good, have special need  of justice and temperance for  example, those (if

such there be, as  the poets say) who dwell in the  Islands of the Blest; they above all  will need philosophy and

temperance and justice, and all the more the  more leisure they have,  living in the midst of abundance. There

is no  difficulty in seeing why  the state that would be happy and good ought  to have these virtues. If  it be

disgraceful in men not to be able to  use the goods of life, it  is peculiarly disgraceful not to be able to  use them

in time of  leisure to show excellent qualities in action and  war, and when  they have peace and leisure to be

no better than slaves.  Wherefore  we should not practice virtue after the manner of the  Lacedaemonians. For

they, while agreeing with other men in their  conception of the highest goods, differ from the rest of mankind

in  thinking that they are to be obtained by the practice of a single  virtue. And since they think these goods

and the enjoyment of them  greater than the enjoyment derived from the virtues ... and that it  should be

practiced for its own sake, is evident from what has been  said; we must now consider how and by what means

it is to be attained. 

We have already determined that nature and habit and rational  principle are required, and, of these, the proper

nature of the  citizens has also been defined by us. But we have still to consider  whether the training of early

life is to be that of rational principle  or habit, for these two must accord, and when in accord they will then

form the best of harmonies. The rational principle may be mistaken and  fail in attaining the highest ideal of

life, and there may be a like  evil influence of habit. Thus much is clear in the first place,  that,  as in all other

things, birth implies an antecedent beginning,  and  that there are beginnings whose end is relative to a further

end. Now,  in men rational principle and mind are the end towards which  nature  strives, so that the birth and

moral discipline of the citizens  ought  to be ordered with a view to them. In the second place, as the  soul  and

body are two, we see also that there are two parts of the  soul,  the rational and the irrational, and two

corresponding states  reason  and appetite. And as the body is prior in order of generation  to the  soul, so the

irrational is prior to the rational. The proof  is that  anger and wishing and desire are implanted in children

from  their very  birth, but reason and understanding are developed as they  grow older.  Wherefore, the care of

the body ought to precede that of  the soul, and  the training of the appetitive part should follow:  none the less

our  care of it must be for the sake of the reason, and  our care of the  body for the sake of the soul. 


POLITICS

XV 101



Top




Page No 106


XVI

Since the legislator should begin by considering how the frames of  the children whom he is rearing may be as

good as possible, his  first  care will be about marriage at what age should his citizens  marry,  and who are fit

to marry? In legislating on this subject he  ought to  consider the persons and the length of their life, that their

procreative life may terminate at the same period, and that they may  not differ in their bodily powers, as will

be the case if the man is  still able to beget children while the woman is unable to bear them,  or the woman

able to bear while the man is unable to beget, for from  these causes arise quarrels and differences between

married persons.  Secondly, he must consider the time at which the children will succeed  to their parents;

there ought not to be too great an interval of  age,  for then the parents will be too old to derive any pleasure

from their  affection, or to be of any use to them. Nor ought they to  be too  nearly of an age; to youthful

marriages there are many  objections the  children will be wanting in respect to the parents,  who will seem to

be their contemporaries, and disputes will arise in  the management of  the household. Thirdly, and this is the

point from  which we digressed,  the legislator must mold to his will the frames of  newlyborn  children.

Almost all these objects may be secured by  attention to one  point. Since the time of generation is commonly

limited within the age  of seventy years in the case of a man, and of  fifty in the case of a  woman, the

commencement of the union should  conform to these periods.  The union of male and female when too  young

is bad for the procreation  of children; in all other animals the  offspring of the young are small  and

indeveloped, and with a tendency  to produce female children, and  therefore also in man, as is proved by  the

fact that in those cities  in which men and women are accustomed to  marry young, the people are  small and

weak; in childbirth also younger  women suffer more, and more  of them die; some persons say that this  was

the meaning of the  response once given to the Troezenians the  oracle really meant that  many died because

they married too young;  it had nothing to do with  the ingathering of the harvest. It also  conduces to

temperance not to  marry too soon; for women who marry  early are apt to be wanton; and in  men too the

bodily frame is stunted  if they marry while the seed is  growing (for there is a time when  the growth of the

seed, also,  ceases, or continues to but a slight  extent). Women should marry when  they are about eighteen

years of age,  and men at seven and thirty;  then they are in the prime of life, and  the decline in the powers of

both will coincide. Further, the  children, if their birth takes place  soon, as may reasonably be  expected, will

succeed in the beginning of  their prime, when the  fathers are already in the decline of life, and  have nearly

reached  their term of threescore years and ten. 

Thus much of the age proper for marriage: the season of the year  should also be considered; according to our

present custom, people  generally limit marriage to the season of winter, and they are right.  The precepts of

physicians and natural philosophers about generation  should also be studied by the parents themselves; the

physicians give  good advice about the favorable conditions of the body, and the  natural philosophers about

the winds; of which they prefer the north  to the south. 

What constitution in the parent is most advantageous to the  offspring is a subject which we will consider

more carefully when we  speak of the education of children, and we will only make a few  general remarks at

present. The constitution of an athlete is not  suited to the life of a citizen, or to health, or to the procreation  of

children, any more than the valetudinarian or exhausted  constitution, but one which is in a mean between

them. A man's  constitution should be inured to labor, but not to labor which is  excessive or of one sort only,

such as is practiced by athletes; he  should be capable of all the actions of a freeman. These remarks apply

equally to both parents. 

Women who are with child should be careful of themselves; they  should take exercise and have a nourishing

diet. The first of these  prescriptions the legislator will easily carry into effect by  requiring that they shall take

a walk daily to some temple, where they  can worship the gods who preside over birth. Their minds, however,

unlike their bodies, they ought to keep quiet, for the offspring  derive their natures from their mothers as

plants do from the earth. 


POLITICS

XVI 102



Top




Page No 107


As to the exposure and rearing of children, let there be a law that  no deformed child shall live, but that on the

ground of an excess in  the number of children, if the established customs of the state forbid  this (for in our

state population has a limit), no child is to be  exposed, but when couples have children in excess, let abortion

be  procured before sense and life have begun; what may or may not be  lawfully done in these cases depends

on the question of life and  sensation. 

And now, having determined at what ages men and women are to begin  their union, let us also determine how

long they shall continue to  beget and bear offspring for the state; men who are too old, like men  who are too

young, produce children who are defective in body and  mind; the children of very old men are weakly. The

limit then, should  be the age which is the prime of their intelligence, and this in most  persons, according to

the notion of some poets who measure life by  periods of seven years, is about fifty; at four or five years or

later, they should cease from having families; and from that time  forward only cohabit with one another for

the sake of health; or for  some similar reason. 

As to adultery, let it be held disgraceful, in general, for any  man or woman to be found in any way unfaithful

when they are  married,  and called husband and wife. If during the time of bearing  children  anything of the

sort occur, let the guilty person be punished  with a  loss of privileges in proportion to the offense. 

XVII

After the children have been born, the manner of rearing them may  be  supposed to have a great effect on their

bodily strength. It would  appear from the example of animals, and of those nations who desire to  create the

military habit, that the food which has most milk in it  is  best suited to human beings; but the less wine the

better, if  they  would escape diseases. Also all the motions to which children can  be  subjected at their early

age are very useful. But in order to  preserve  their tender limbs from distortion, some nations have had

recourse to  mechanical appliances which straighten their bodies. To  accustom  children to the cold from their

earliest years is also an  excellent  practice, which greatly conduces to health, and hardens them  for  military

service. Hence many barbarians have a custom of  plunging  their children at birth into a cold stream; others,

like  the Celts,  clothe them in a light wrapper only. For human nature  should be early  habituated to endure all

which by habit it can be made  to endure; but  the process must be gradual. And children, from their  natural

warmth,  may be easily trained to bear cold. Such care should  attend them in  the first stage of life. 

The next period lasts to the age of five; during this no demand  should be made upon the child for study or

labor, lest its growth be  impeded; and there should be sufficient motion to prevent the limbs  from being

inactive. This can be secured, among other ways, by  amusement, but the amusement should not be vulgar or

tiring or  effeminate. The Directors of Education, as they are termed, should  be  careful what tales or stories

the children hear, for all such  things  are designed to prepare the way for the business of later life,  and  should

be for the most part imitations of the occupations which  they  will hereafter pursue in earnest. Those are

wrong who in their  laws  attempt to check the loud crying and screaming of children, for  these  contribute

towards their growth, and, in a manner, exercise  their  bodies. Straining the voice has a strengthening effect

similar  to that  produced by the retention of the breath in violent  exertions. The  Directors of Education should

have an eye to their  bringing up, and in  particular should take care that they are left  as little as possible  with

slaves. For until they are seven years  old they must five at  home; and therefore, even at this early age,  it is to

be expected that  they should acquire a taint of meanness from  what they hear and see.  Indeed, there is nothing

which the  legislator should be more careful  to drive away than indecency of  speech; for the light utterance of

shameful words leads soon to  shameful actions. The young especially  should never be allowed to  repeat or

hear anything of the sort. A  freeman who is found saying  or doing what is forbidden, if he be too  young as

yet to have the  privilege of reclining at the public tables,  should be disgraced and  beaten, and an elder person

degraded as his  slavish conduct  deserves. And since we do not allow improper language,  clearly we  should

also banish pictures or speeches from the stage  which are  indecent. Let the rulers take care that there be no


POLITICS

XVII 103



Top




Page No 108


image or  picture  representing unseemly actions, except in the temples of those  Gods  at whose festivals the

law permits even ribaldry, and whom the  law  also permits to be worshipped by persons of mature age on

behalf  of  themselves, their children, and their wives. But the legislator  should  not allow youth to be

spectators of iambi or of comedy until  they  are of an age to sit at the public tables and to drink strong  wine;

by  that time education will have armed them against the evil  influences  of such representations. 

We have made these remarks in a cursory manner they are enough  for the present occasion; but hereafter we

will return to the  subject  and after a fuller discussion determine whether such liberty  should or  should not be

granted, and in what way granted, if at all.  Theodorus,  the tragic actor, was quite right in saying that he would

not allow  any other actor, not even if he were quite secondrate, to  enter  before himself, because the

spectators grew fond of the voices  which  they first heard. And the same principle applies universally  to

association with things as well as with persons, for we always like  best whatever comes first. And therefore

youth should be kept  strangers to all that is bad, and especially to things which suggest  vice or hate. When the

five years have passed away, during the two  following years they must look on at the pursuits which they are

hereafter to learn. There are two periods of life with reference to  which education has to be divided, from

seven to the age of puberty,  and onwards to the age of one and twenty. The poets who divide ages by  sevens

are in the main right: but we should observe the divisions  actually made by nature; for the deficiencies of

nature are what art  and education seek to fill up. 

Let us then first inquire if any regulations are to be laid down  about children, and secondly, whether the care

of them should be the  concern of the state or of private individuals, which latter is in our  own day the

common custom, and in the third place, what these  regulations should be. 

BOOK EIGHT

I

NO ONE will doubt that the legislator should direct his attention  above all to the education of youth; for the

neglect of education does  harm to the constitution The citizen should be molded to suit the form  of

government under which he lives. For each government has a peculiar  character which originally formed and

which continues to preserve  it.  The character of democracy creates democracy, and the character of  oligarchy

creates oligarchy; and always the better the character,  the  better the government. 

Again, for the exercise of any faculty or art a previous training  and habituation are required; clearly therefore

for the practice of  virtue. And since the whole city has one end, it is manifest that  education should be one

and the same for all, and that it should be  public, and not private not as at present, when every one looks

after  his own children separately, and gives them separate instruction of  the sort which he thinks best; the

training in things which are of  common interest should be the same for all. Neither must we suppose  that any

one of the citizens belongs to himself, for they all belong  to the state, and are each of them a part of the state,

and the care  of each part is inseparable from the care of the whole. In this  particular as in some others the

Lacedaemonians are to be praised, for  they take the greatest pains about their children, and make  education

the business of the state. 

II

That education should be regulated by law and should be an affair  of  state is not to be denied, but what

should be the character of this  public education, and how young persons should be educated, are  questions

which remain to be considered. As things are, there is  disagreement about the subjects. For mankind are by

no means agreed  about the things to be taught, whether we look to virtue or the best  life. Neither is it clear

whether education is more concerned with  intellectual or with moral virtue. The existing practice is


POLITICS

BOOK EIGHT 104



Top




Page No 109


perplexing; no one knows on what principle we should proceed should  the useful in life, or should virtue, or

should the higher  knowledge,  be the aim of our training; all three opinions have been  entertained.  Again,

about the means there is no agreement; for  different persons,  starting with different ideas about the nature of

virtue, naturally  disagree about the practice of it. There can be no  doubt that children  should be taught those

useful things which are  really necessary, but  not all useful things; for occupations are  divided into liberal and

illiberal; and to young children should be  imparted only such kinds of  knowledge as will be useful to them

without vulgarizing them. And any  occupation, art, or science, which  makes the body or soul or mind of  the

freeman less fit for the  practice or exercise of virtue, is  vulgar; wherefore we call those  arts vulgar which tend

to deform the  body, and likewise all paid  employments, for they absorb and degrade  the mind. There are also

some  liberal arts quite proper for a freeman  to acquire, but only in a  certain degree, and if he attend to them

too  closely, in order to  attain perfection in them, the same evil effects  will follow. The  object also which a

man sets before him makes a great  difference; if  he does or learns anything for his own sake or for the  sake of

his  friends, or with a view to excellence the action will not  appear  illiberal; but if done for the sake of others,

the very same  action  will be thought menial and servile. The received subjects of  instruction, as I have

already remarked, are partly of a liberal and  party of an illiberal character. 

III

The customary branches of education are in number four; they are  (1) reading and writing, (2) gymnastic

exercises, (3) music, to  which  is sometimes added (4) drawing. Of these, reading and writing  and  drawing are

regarded as useful for the purposes of life in a  variety  of ways, and gymnastic exercises are thought to infuse

courage.  concerning music a doubt may be raised in our own day most  men  cultivate it for the sake of

pleasure, but originally it was  included  in education, because nature herself, as has been often said,  requires

that we should be able, not only to work well, but to use  leisure  well; for, as I must repeat once again, the first

principle of  all  action is leisure. Both are required, but leisure is better than  occupation and is its end; and

therefore the question must be asked,  what ought we to do when at leisure? Clearly we ought not to be

amusing ourselves, for then amusement would be the end of life. But if  this is inconceivable, and amusement

is needed more amid serious  occupations than at other times (for he who is hard at work has need  of

relaxation, and amusement gives relaxation, whereas occupation is  always accompanied with exertion and

effort), we should introduce  amusements only at suitable times, and they should be our medicines,  for the

emotion which they create in the soul is a relaxation, and  from the pleasure we obtain rest. But leisure of

itself gives pleasure  and happiness and enjoyment of life, which are experienced, not by the  busy man, but by

those who have leisure. For he who is occupied has in  view some end which he has not attained; but

happiness is an end,  since all men deem it to be accompanied with pleasure and not with  pain. This pleasure,

however, is regarded differently by different  persons, and varies according to the habit of individuals; the

pleasure of the best man is the best, and springs from the noblest  sources. It is clear then that there are

branches of learning and  education which we must study merely with a view to leisure spent in  intellectual

activity, and these are to be valued for their own  sake;  whereas those kinds of knowledge which are useful in

business  are to  be deemed necessary, and exist for the sake of other things.  And  therefore our fathers

admitted music into education, not on the  ground  either of its necessity or utility, for it is not necessary,  nor

indeed useful in the same manner as reading and writing, which are  useful in moneymaking, in the

management of a household, in the  acquisition of knowledge and in political life, nor like drawing,  useful for

a more correct judgment of the works of artists, nor  again  like gymnastic, which gives health and strength; for

neither  of these  is to be gained from music. There remains, then, the use of  music for  intellectual enjoyment

in leisure; which is in fact  evidently the  reason of its introduction, this being one of the ways  in which it is

thought that a freeman should pass his leisure; as  Homer says, 

But he who alone should be called to the pleasant feast,  and  afterwards he speaks of others whom he

describes as inviting 


POLITICS

III 105



Top




Page No 110


The bard who would delight them all.  And in another place Odysseus  says there is no better way of passing

life than when men's hearts are  merry and 

The banqueters in the hall, sitting in order, hear the voice of  the minstrel. 

It is evident, then, that there is a sort of education in which  parents should train their sons, not as being useful

or necessary, but  because it is liberal or noble. Whether this is of one kind only, or  of more than one, and if

so, what they are, and how they are to be  imparted, must hereafter be determined. Thus much we are now in a

position to say, that the ancients witness to us; for their opinion  may be gathered from the fact that music is

one of the received and  traditional branches of education. Further, it is clear that  children  should be instructed

in some useful things for example, in  reading  and writing not only for their usefulness, but also because

many  other sorts of knowledge are acquired through them. With a like  view  they may be taught drawing, not

to prevent their making  mistakes in  their own purchases, or in order that they may not be  imposed upon in  the

buying or selling of articles, but perhaps  rather because it makes  them judges of the beauty of the human

form.  To be always seeking  after the useful does not become free and exalted  souls. Now it is  clear that in

education practice must be used  before theory, and the  body be trained before the mind; and  therefore boys

should be handed  over to the trainer, who creates in  them the roper habit of body, and  to the

wrestlingmaster, who teaches  them their exercises. 

IV

Of those states which in our own day seem to take the greatest  care of children, some aim at producing in

them an athletic habit, but  they only injure their forms and stunt their growth. Although the  Lacedaemonians

have not fallen into this mistake, yet they brutalize  their children by laborious exercises which they think will

make  them  courageous. But in truth, as we have often repeated, education  should  not be exclusively, or

principally, directed to this end. And  even if  we suppose the Lacedaemonians to be right in their end, they  do

not  attain it. For among barbarians and among animals courage is  found  associated, not with the greatest

ferocity, but with a gentle  and lion  like temper. There are many races who are ready enough to  kill and eat

men, such as the Achaeans and Heniochi, who both live  about the Black  Sea; and there are other mainland

tribes, as bad or  worse, who all  live by plunder, but have no courage. It is notorious  that the  Lacedaemonians

themselves, while they alone were assiduous in  their  laborious drill, were superior to others, but now they are

beaten both  in war and gymnastic exercises. For their ancient  superiority did not  depend on their mode of

training their youth,  but only on the  circumstance that they trained them when their only  rivals did not.  Hence

we may infer that what is noble, not what is  brutal, should have  the first place; no wolf or other wild animal

will  face a really noble  danger; such dangers are for the brave man. And  parents who devote  their children to

gymnastics while they neglect  their necessary  education, in reality vulgarize them; for they make  them useful

to the  art of statesmanship in one quality only, and  even in this the  argument proves them to be inferior to

others. We  should judge the  Lacedaemonians not from what they have been, but from  what they are;  for now

they have rivals who compete with their  education; formerly  they had none. 

It is an admitted principle, that gymnastic exercises should be  employed in education, and that for children

they should be of a  lighter kind, avoiding severe diet or painful toil, lest the growth of  the body be impaired.

The evil of excessive training in early years is  strikingly proved by the example of the Olympic victors; for

not  more  than two or three of them have gained a prize both as boys and as  men;  their early training and

severe gymnastic exercises exhausted  their  constitutions. When boyhood is over, three years should be spent

in  other studies; the period of life which follows may then be devoted  to  hard exercise and strict diet. Men

ought not to labor at the same  time  with their minds and with their bodies; for the two kinds of  labor are

opposed to one another; the labor of the body impedes the  mind, and  the labor of the mind the body. 


POLITICS

IV 106



Top




Page No 111


V

Concerning music there are some questions which we have already  raised; these we may now resume and

carry further; and our remarks  will serve as a prelude to this or any other discussion of the  subject. It is not

easy to determine the nature of music, or why any  one should have a knowledge of it. Shall we say, for the

sake of  amusement and relaxation, like sleep or drinking, which are not good  in themselves, but are pleasant,

and at the same time 'care to cease,'  as Euripides says? And for this end men also appoint music, and make

use of all three alike sleep, drinking, music to which some add  dancing. Or shall we argue that music

conduces to virtue, on the  ground that it can form our minds and habituate us to true pleasures  as our bodies

are made by gymnastic to be of a certain character? Or  shall we say that it contributes to the enjoyment of

leisure and  mental cultivation, which is a third alternative? Now obviously youths  are not to be instructed

with a view to their amusement, for  learning  is no amusement, but is accompanied with pain. Neither is

intellectual  enjoyment suitable to boys of that age, for it is the  end, and that  which is imperfect cannot attain

the perfect or end. But  perhaps it  may be said that boys learn music for the sake of the  amusement which  they

will have when they are grown up. If so, why  should they learn  themselves, and not, like the Persian and

Median  kings, enjoy the  pleasure and instruction which is derived from  hearing others? (for  surely persons

who have made music the business  and profession of  their lives will be better performers than those who

practice only  long enough to learn). If they must learn music, on  the same principle  they should learn

cookery, which is absurd. And  even granting that  music may form the character, the objection still  holds: why

should we  learn ourselves? Why cannot we attain true  pleasure and form a correct  judgment from hearing

others, like the  Lacedaemonians? for they,  without learning music, nevertheless can  correctly judge, as they

say,  of good and bad melodies. Or again, if  music should be used to promote  cheerfulness and refined

intellectual enjoyment, the objection still  remains why should we  learn ourselves instead of enjoying the

performances of others? We may  illustrate what we are saying by our  conception of the Gods; for in  the poets

Zeus does not himself sing or  play on the lyre. Nay, we call  professional performers vulgar; no  freeman

would play or sing unless  he were intoxicated or in jest. But  these matters may be left for  the present. 

The first question is whether music is or is not to be a part of  education. Of the three things mentioned in our

discussion, which does  it produce? education or amusement or intellectual enjoyment, for  it  may be

reckoned under all three, and seems to share in the nature  of  all of them. Amusement is for the sake of

relaxation, and  relaxation  is of necessity sweet, for it is the remedy of pain  caused by toil;  and intellectual

enjoyment is universally acknowledged  to contain an  element not only of the noble but of the pleasant, for

happiness is  made up of both. All men agree that music is one of the  pleasantest  things, whether with or

without songs; as Musaeus says: 

Song to mortals of all things the sweetest.  Hence and with good  reason it is introduced into social gatherings

and  entertainments,  because it makes the hearts of men glad: so that on  this ground alone  we may assume that

the young ought to be trained  in it. For innocent  pleasures are not only in harmony with the perfect  end of

life, but  they also provide relaxation. And whereas men  rarely attain the end,  but often rest by the way and

amuse themselves,  not only with a view  to a further end, but also for the pleasure's  sake, it may be well at

times to let them find a refreshment in music.  It sometimes happens  that men make amusement the end, for

the end  probably contains some  element of pleasure, though not any ordinary or  lower pleasure; but  they

mistake the lower for the higher, and in  seeking for the one find  the other, since every pleasure has a  likeness

to the end of action.  For the end is not eligible for the  sake of any future good, nor do  the pleasures which we

have  described exist for the sake of any future  good but of the past,  that is to say, they are the alleviation of

past  toils and pains.  And we may infer this to be the reason why men seek  happiness from  these pleasures. 

But music is pursued, not only as an alleviation of past toil, but  also as providing recreation. And who can

say whether, having this  use, it may not also have a nobler one? In addition to this common  pleasure, felt and

shared in by all (for the pleasure given by music  is natural, and therefore adapted to all ages and characters),


POLITICS

V 107



Top




Page No 112


may  it  not have also some influence over the character and the soul? It  must  have such an influence if

characters are affected by it. And that  they  are so affected is proved in many ways, and not least by the  power

which the songs of Olympus exercise; for beyond question they  inspire  enthusiasm, and enthusiasm is an

emotion of the ethical part  of the  soul. Besides, when men hear imitations, even apart from the  rhythms  and

tunes themselves, their feelings move in sympathy. Since  then  music is a pleasure, and virtue consists in

rejoicing and  loving and  hating aright, there is clearly nothing which we are so  much concerned  to acquire

and to cultivate as the power of forming  right judgments,  and of taking delight in good dispositions and  noble

actions. Rhythm  and melody supply imitations of anger and  gentleness, and also of  courage and temperance,

and of all the  qualities contrary to these,  and of the other qualities of  character, which hardly fall short of  the

actual affections, as we  know from our own experience, for in  listening to such strains our  souls undergo a

change. The habit of  feeling pleasure or pain at  mere representations is not far removed  from the same feeling

about  realities; for example, if any one  delights in the sight of a statue  for its beauty only, it necessarily

follows that the sight of the  original will be pleasant to him. The  objects of no other sense,  such as taste or

touch, have any  resemblance to moral qualities; in  visible objects there is only a  little, for there are figures

which  are of a moral character, but only  to a slight extent, and all do  not participate in the feeling about  them.

Again, figures and colors  are not imitations, but signs, of  moral habits, indications which  the body gives of

states of feeling.  The connection of them with  morals is slight, but in so far as there  is any, young men should

be  taught to look, not at the works of  Pauson, but at those of  Polygnotus, or any other painter or sculptor  who

expresses moral  ideas. On the other hand, even in mere melodies  there is an  imitation of character, for the

musical modes differ  essentially  from one another, and those who hear them are differently  affected  by each.

Some of them make men sad and grave, like the  socalled  Mixolydian, others enfeeble the mind, like the

relaxed  modes, another,  again, produces a moderate and settled temper, which  appears to be the  peculiar

effect of the Dorian; the Phrygian inspires  enthusiasm. The  whole subject has been well treated by

philosophical  writers on this  branch of education, and they confirm their arguments  by facts. The  same

principles apply to rhythms; some have a character  of rest,  others of motion, and of these latter again, some

have a more  vulgar, others a nobler movement. Enough has been said to show that  music has a power of

forming the character, and should therefore be  introduced into the education of the young. The study is suited

to the  stage of youth, for young persons will not, if they can help, endure  anything which is not sweetened by

pleasure, and music has a natural  sweetness. There seems to be in us a sort of affinity to musical modes  and

rhythms, which makes some philosophers say that the soul is a  tuning, others, that it possesses tuning. 

VI

And now we have to determine the question which has been already  raised, whether children should be

themselves taught to sing and  play  or not. Clearly there is a considerable difference made in the  character by

the actual practice of the art. It is difficult, if not  impossible, for those who do not perform to be good judges

of the  performance of others. Besides, children should have something to  do,  and the rattle of Archytas,

which people give to their children in  order to amuse them and prevent them from breaking anything in the

house, was a capital invention, for a young thing cannot be quiet. The  rattle is a toy suited to the infant mind,

and education is a rattle  or toy for children of a larger growth. We conclude then that they  should be taught

music in such a way as to become not only critics but  performers. 

The question what is or is not suitable for different ages may be  easily answered; nor is there any difficulty in

meeting the  objection  of those who say that the study of music is vulgar. We reply  (1) in  the first place, that

they who are to be judges must also be  performers, and that they should begin to practice early, although

when they are older they may be spared the execution; they must have  learned to appreciate what is good and

to delight in it, thanks to the  knowledge which they acquired in their youth. As to (2) the  vulgarizing effect

which music is supposed to exercise, this is a  question which we shall have no difficulty in determining,

when we  have considered to what extent freemen who are being trained to  political virtue should pursue the

art, what melodies and what rhythms  they should be allowed to use, and what instruments should be


POLITICS

VI 108



Top




Page No 113


employed  in teaching them to play; for even the instrument makes a  difference.  The answer to the objection

turns upon these distinctions;  for it is  quite possible that certain methods of teaching and learning  music do

really have a degrading effect. It is evident then that the  learning  of music ought not to impede the business of

riper years,  or to  degrade the body or render it unfit for civil or military  training,  whether for bodily exercises

at the time or for later  studies. 

The right measure will be attained if students of music stop short  of the arts which are practiced in

professional contests, and do not  seek to acquire those fantastic marvels of execution which are now the

fashion in such contests, and from these have passed into education.  Let the young practice even such music

as we have prescribed, only  until they are able to feel delight in noble melodies and rhythms, and  not merely

in that common part of music in which every slave or  child  and even some animals find pleasure. 

From these principles we may also infer what instruments should be  used. The flute, or any other instrument

which requires great skill,  as for example the harp, ought not to be admitted into education,  but  only such as

will make intelligent students of music or of the  other  parts of education. Besides, the flute is not an

instrument  which is  expressive of moral character; it is too exciting. The proper  time for  using it is when the

performance aims not at instruction, but  at the  relief of the passions. And there is a further objection; the

impediment which the flute presents to the use of the voice detracts  from its educational value. The ancients

therefore were right in  forbidding the flute to youths and freemen, although they had once  allowed it. For

when their wealth gave them a greater inclination to  leisure, and they had loftier notions of excellence, being

also elated  with their success, both before and after the Persian War, with more  zeal than discernment they

pursued every kind of knowledge, and so  they introduced the flute into education. At Lacedaemon there was

a  choragus who led the chorus with a flute, and at Athens the instrument  became so popular that most

freemen could play upon it. The popularity  is shown by the tablet which Thrasippus dedicated when he

furnished  the chorus to Ecphantides. Later experience enabled men to judge  what  was or was not really

conducive to virtue, and they rejected both  the  flute and several other oldfashioned instruments, such as the

Lydian  harp, the manystringed lyre, the 'heptagon,' 'triangle,'  'sambuca,'  the like which are intended only to

give pleasure to the  hearer, and  require extraordinary skill of hand. There is a meaning  also in the  myth of the

ancients, which tells how Athene invented  the flute and  then threw it away. It was not a bad idea of theirs,

that the Goddess  disliked the instrument because it made the face  ugly; but with still  more reason may we say

that she rejected it  because the acquirement of  fluteplaying contributes nothing to the  mind, since to Athene

we  ascribe both knowledge and art. 

Thus then we reject the professional instruments and also the  professional mode of education in music (and

by professional we mean  that which is adopted in contests), for in this the performer  practices the art, not for

the sake of his own improvement, but in  order to give pleasure, and that of a vulgar sort, to his hearers. For

this reason the execution of such music is not the part of a freeman  but of a paid performer, and the result is

that the performers are  vulgarized, for the end at which they aim is bad. The vulgarity of the  spectator tends

to lower the character of the music and therefore of  the performers; they look to him he makes them what

they are, and  fashions even their bodies by the movements which he expects them to  exhibit. 

VII

We have also to consider rhythms and modes, and their use in  education. Shall we use them all or make a

distinction? and shall  the  same distinction be made for those who practice music with a  view to  education, or

shall it be some other? Now we see that music is  produced by melody and rhythm, and we ought to know

what influence  these have respectively on education, and whether we should prefer  excellence in melody or

excellence in rhythm. But as the subject has  been very well treated by many musicians of the present day, and

also  by philosophers who have had considerable experience of musical  education, to these we would refer the

more exact student of the  subject; we shall only speak of it now after the manner of the  legislator, stating the


POLITICS

VII 109



Top




Page No 114


general principles. 

We accept the division of melodies proposed by certain  philosophers into ethical melodies, melodies of

action, and passionate  or inspiring melodies, each having, as they say, a mode  corresponding  to it. But we

maintain further that music should be  studied, not for  the sake of one, but of many benefits, that is to  say,

with a view to  (1) education, (2) purgation (the word 'purgation'  we use at present  without explanation, but

when hereafter we speak  of poetry, we will  treat the subject with more precision); music may  also serve (3)

for  for enjoyment, for relaxation, and for recreation  after exertion. It  is clear, therefore, that all the modes

must be  employed by us, but  not all of them in the same manner. In education  the most ethical  modes are to

be preferred, but in listening to the  performances of  others we may admit the modes of action and passion

also. For feelings  such as pity and fear, or, again, enthusiasm, exist  very strongly in  some souls, and have

more or less influence over all.  Some persons  fall into a religious frenzy, whom we see as a result  of the

sacred  melodies when they have used the melodies that excite  the soul to  mystic frenzy restored as though

they had found healing  and  purgation. Those who are influenced by pity or fear, and every  emotional nature,

must have a like experience, and others in so far as  each is susceptible to such emotions, and all are in a

manner purged  and their souls lightened and delighted. The purgative melodies  likewise give an innocent

pleasure to mankind. Such are the modes  and  the melodies in which those who perform music at the theater

should be  invited to compete. But since the spectators are of two  kinds the one  free and educated, and the

other a vulgar crowd  composed of mechanics,  laborers, and the like there ought to be  contests and

exhibitions  instituted for the relaxation of the second  class also. And the music  will correspond to their

minds; for as their  minds are perverted from  the natural state, so there are perverted  modes and highly strung

and  unnaturally colored melodies. A man  receives pleasure from what is  natural to him, and therefore

professional musicians may be allowed to  practice this lower sort of  music before an audience of a lower

type.  But, for the purposes of  education, as I have already said, those  modes and melodies should  be

employed which are ethical, such as the  Dorian, as we said  before; though we may include any others which

are  approved by  philosophers who have had a musical education. The  Socrates of the  Republic is wrong in

retaining only the Phrygian mode  along with the  Dorian, and the more so because he rejects the flute;  for the

Phrygian  is to the modes what the flute is to musical  instruments both of them  are exciting and emotional.

Poetry proves  this, for Bacchic frenzy and  all similar emotions are most suitably  expressed by the flute, and

are  better set to the Phrygian than to any  other mode. The dithyramb,  for example, is acknowledged to be

Phrygian, a fact of which the  connoisseurs of music offer many proofs,  saying, among other things,  that

Philoxenus, having attempted to  compose his Mysians as a  dithyramb in the Dorian mode, found it

impossible, and fell back by  the very nature of things into the more  appropriate Phrygian. All  men agree that

the Dorian music is the  gravest and manliest. And  whereas we say that the extremes should be  avoided and

the mean  followed, and whereas the Dorian is a mean  between the other modes, it  is evident that our youth

should be taught  the Dorian music. 

Two principles have to be kept in view, what is possible, what is  becoming: at these every man ought to aim.

But even these are relative  to age; the old, who have lost their powers, cannot very well sing the  highstrung

modes, and nature herself seems to suggest that their  songs should be of the more relaxed kind. Wherefore

the musicians  likewise blame Socrates, and with justice, for rejecting the relaxed  modes in education under

the idea that they are intoxicating, not in  the ordinary sense of intoxication (for wine rather tends to excite

men), but because they have no strength in them. And so, with a view  also to the time of life when men begin

to grow old, they ought to  practice the gentler modes and melodies as well as the others, and,  further, any

mode, such as the Lydian above all others appears to  be,  which is suited to children of tender age, and

possesses the  elements  both of order and of education. Thus it is clear that  education should  be based upon

three principles the mean, the  possible, the becoming,  these three. 

THE END 


POLITICS

VII 110



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. POLITICS, page = 6

   3. by Aristotle, page = 6

   4.  BOOK ONE, page = 8

   5.  I, page = 8

   6.  II, page = 9

   7.  III, page = 10

   8.  IV, page = 10

   9.  V, page = 11

   10.  VI, page = 12

   11.  VII, page = 13

   12.  VIII, page = 13

   13.  IX, page = 14

   14.  X, page = 16

   15.  XI, page = 16

   16.  XII, page = 17

   17.  XIII, page = 18

18.  BOOK TWO, page = 19

   19.  I, page = 19

   20.  II, page = 19

   21.  III, page = 20

   22.  IV, page = 21

   23.  V, page = 22

   24.  VI, page = 24

   25.  VII, page = 25

   26.  VIII, page = 27

   27.  IX, page = 29

   28.  X, page = 32

   29.  XI, page = 33

   30.  XII, page = 34

31.  BOOK THREE, page = 36

   32.  I, page = 36

   33.  II, page = 37

   34.  III, page = 37

   35.  IV, page = 38

   36.  V, page = 39

   37.  VI, page = 40

   38.  VII, page = 41

   39.  VIII, page = 41

   40.  IX, page = 42

   41.  X, page = 43

   42.  XI, page = 44

   43.  XII, page = 45

   44.  XIII, page = 46

   45.  XIV, page = 47

   46.  XV, page = 49

   47.  XVI, page = 50

   48.  XVII, page = 51

   49.  XVIII, page = 52

50.  BOOK FOUR, page = 52

   51.  I, page = 52

   52.  II, page = 53

   53.  III, page = 54

   54.  IV, page = 54

   55.  V, page = 57

   56.  VI, page = 57

   57.  VII, page = 58

   58.  VIII, page = 58

   59.  IX, page = 59

   60.  X, page = 60

   61.  XI, page = 60

   62.  XII, page = 62

   63.  XIII, page = 62

   64.  XIV, page = 63

   65.  XV, page = 65

   66.  XVI, page = 67

67.  BOOK FIVE, page = 67

   68.  I, page = 68

   69.  II, page = 69

   70.  III, page = 69

   71.  IV, page = 71

   72.  V, page = 72

   73.  VI, page = 73

   74.  VII, page = 74

   75.  VIII, page = 75

   76.  IX, page = 77

   77.  X, page = 79

   78.  XI, page = 82

   79.  XII, page = 84

80.  BOOK SIX, page = 86

   81.  I, page = 86

   82.  II, page = 87

   83.  III, page = 87

   84.  IV, page = 88

   85.  V, page = 89

   86.  VI, page = 90

   87.  VII, page = 91

   88.  VIII, page = 91

89.  BOOK SEVEN, page = 93

   90.  I, page = 93

   91.  II, page = 94

   92.  III, page = 95

   93.  IV, page = 96

   94.  V, page = 97

   95.  VI, page = 97

   96.  VII, page = 98

   97.  VIII, page = 99

   98.  IX, page = 100

   99.  X, page = 100

   100.  XI, page = 101

   101.  XII, page = 102

   102.  XIII, page = 103

   103.  XIV, page = 104

   104.  XV, page = 106

   105.  XVI, page = 107

   106.  XVII, page = 108

107.  BOOK EIGHT, page = 109

   108.  I, page = 109

   109.  II, page = 109

   110.  III, page = 110

   111.  IV, page = 111

   112.  V, page = 112

   113.  VI, page = 113

   114.  VII, page = 114