Title:   PRIOR ANALYTICS

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Page No 44

Page No 45

Page No 46

Page No 47

Page No 48

Page No 49

Page No 50

Page No 51

Page No 52

Page No 53

Page No 54

Page No 55

Page No 56

Page No 57

Page No 58

Page No 59

Page No 60

Page No 61

Page No 62

Page No 63

Bookmarks





Page No 1


PRIOR ANALYTICS

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

PRIOR ANALYTICS.........................................................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

Book I ...................................................................................................................................................................2

1..............................................................................................................................................................2

2..............................................................................................................................................................3

3..............................................................................................................................................................4

4..............................................................................................................................................................4

5..............................................................................................................................................................6

6..............................................................................................................................................................7

7..............................................................................................................................................................9

8..............................................................................................................................................................9

9............................................................................................................................................................10

10..........................................................................................................................................................10

11..........................................................................................................................................................11

12..........................................................................................................................................................12

13..........................................................................................................................................................12

14..........................................................................................................................................................13

15..........................................................................................................................................................14

16..........................................................................................................................................................16

17..........................................................................................................................................................18

18..........................................................................................................................................................19

19..........................................................................................................................................................19

20..........................................................................................................................................................20

21..........................................................................................................................................................21

22..........................................................................................................................................................21

23..........................................................................................................................................................22

24..........................................................................................................................................................23

25..........................................................................................................................................................24

26..........................................................................................................................................................25

27..........................................................................................................................................................25

28..........................................................................................................................................................26

29..........................................................................................................................................................28

30..........................................................................................................................................................29

31..........................................................................................................................................................29

32..........................................................................................................................................................30

33..........................................................................................................................................................31

34..........................................................................................................................................................31

35..........................................................................................................................................................32

36..........................................................................................................................................................32

37..........................................................................................................................................................33

38..........................................................................................................................................................33

39..........................................................................................................................................................34

40..........................................................................................................................................................34

41..........................................................................................................................................................34

42..........................................................................................................................................................34

43..........................................................................................................................................................34

44..........................................................................................................................................................35

45..........................................................................................................................................................35


PRIOR ANALYTICS

i



Top




Page No 3


Table of Contents

46..........................................................................................................................................................36

Book II...............................................................................................................................................................38

1............................................................................................................................................................38

2............................................................................................................................................................39

3............................................................................................................................................................41

4............................................................................................................................................................42

5............................................................................................................................................................44

6............................................................................................................................................................45

7............................................................................................................................................................45

8............................................................................................................................................................46

9............................................................................................................................................................46

10..........................................................................................................................................................47

11..........................................................................................................................................................48

12..........................................................................................................................................................49

13..........................................................................................................................................................50

14..........................................................................................................................................................50

15..........................................................................................................................................................51

16..........................................................................................................................................................52

17..........................................................................................................................................................53

18..........................................................................................................................................................54

19..........................................................................................................................................................54

20..........................................................................................................................................................55

22..........................................................................................................................................................56

23..........................................................................................................................................................57

24..........................................................................................................................................................58

25..........................................................................................................................................................58

26..........................................................................................................................................................58

27..........................................................................................................................................................59


PRIOR ANALYTICS

ii



Top




Page No 4


PRIOR ANALYTICS

by Aristotle

translated by A. J. Jenkinson

Book I  

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14 

15 

16 

17 

18 

19 

20 

21 

22 

23 

24 

25 

26 

27 

28 

29 

30 

31 

32 

33 

34 

35 

36 

37 

38  

PRIOR ANALYTICS 1



Top




Page No 5


39 

40 

41 

42 

43 

44 

45 

46  

Book II  

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14 

15 

16 

17 

18 

19 

20 

22 

23 

24 

25 

26 

27  

Book I

1

WE must first state the subject of our inquiry and the faculty to  which it belongs: its subject is demonstration

and the faculty that  carries it out demonstrative science. We must next define a premiss, a  term, and a

syllogism, and the nature of a perfect and of an imperfect  syllogism; and after that, the inclusion or

noninclusion of one term  in another as in a whole, and what we mean by predicating one term  of  all, or none,

of another. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

Book I 2



Top




Page No 6


A premiss then is a sentence affirming or denying one thing of  another. This is either universal or particular

or indefinite. By  universal I mean the statement that something belongs to all or none  of something else; by

particular that it belongs to some or not to  some or not to all; by indefinite that it does or does not belong,

without any mark to show whether it is universal or particular, e.g.  'contraries are subjects of the same

science', or 'pleasure is not  good'. The demonstrative premiss differs from the dialectical, because  the

demonstrative premiss is the assertion of one of two contradictory  statements (the demonstrator does not ask

for his premiss, but lays it  down), whereas the dialectical premiss depends on the adversary's  choice between

two contradictories. But this will make no difference  to the production of a syllogism in either case; for both

the  demonstrator and the dialectician argue syllogistically after  stating  that something does or does not

belong to something else.  Therefore a  syllogistic premiss without qualification will be an  affirmation or

denial of something concerning something else in the  way we have  described; it will be demonstrative, if it is

true and  obtained  through the first principles of its science; while a  dialectical  premiss is the giving of a

choice between two  contradictories, when a  man is proceeding by question, but when he  is syllogizing it is

the  assertion of that which is apparent and  generally admitted, as has  been said in the Topics. The nature then

of  a premiss and the  difference between syllogistic, demonstrative, and  dialectical  premisses, may be taken as

sufficiently defined by us in  relation to  our present need, but will be stated accurately in the  sequel. 

I call that a term into which the premiss is resolved, i.e. both  the  predicate and that of which it is predicated,

'being' being added  and 'not being' removed, or vice versa. 

A syllogism is discourse in which, certain things being stated,  something other than what is stated follows of

necessity from their  being so. I mean by the last phrase that they produce the consequence,  and by this, that

no further term is required from without in order to  make the consequence necessary. 

I call that a perfect syllogism which needs nothing other than  what has been stated to make plain what

necessarily follows; a  syllogism is imperfect, if it needs either one or more propositions,  which are indeed the

necessary consequences of the terms set down, but  have not been expressly stated as premisses. 

That one term should be included in another as in a whole is the  same as for the other to be predicated of all

of the first. And we say  that one term is predicated of all of another, whenever no instance of  the subject can

be found of which the other term cannot be asserted:  'to be predicated of none' must be understood in the

same way. 

2

Every premiss states that something either is or must be or may be  the attribute of something else; of

premisses of these three kinds  some are affirmative, others negative, in respect of each of the three  modes of

attribution; again some affirmative and negative premisses  are universal, others particular, others indefinite. It

is necessary  then that in universal attribution the terms of the negative premiss  should be convertible, e.g. if

no pleasure is good, then no good  will  be pleasure; the terms of the affirmative must be convertible,  not

however, universally, but in part, e.g. if every pleasure,is good,  some good must be pleasure; the particular

affirmative must convert in  part (for if some pleasure is good, then some good will be  pleasure);  but the

particular negative need not convert, for if some  animal is  not man, it does not follow that some man is not

animal. 

First then take a universal negative with the terms A and B. If no  B  is A, neither can any A be B. For if some

A (say C) were B, it would  not be true that no B is A; for C is a B. But if every B is A then  some A is B. For

if no A were B, then no B could be A. But we  assumed  that every B is A. Similarly too, if the premiss is

particular. For if  some B is A, then some of the As must be B. For  if none were, then no  B would be A. But if

some B is not A, there is  no necessity that some  of the As should not be B; e.g. let B stand for  animal and A


PRIOR ANALYTICS

2 3



Top




Page No 7


for man.  Not every animal is a man; but every man is an  animal. 

3

The same manner of conversion will hold good also in respect of  necessary premisses. The universal negative

converts universally; each  of the affirmatives converts into a particular. If it is necessary  that no B is A, it is

necessary also that no A is B. For if it is  possible that some A is B, it would be possible also that some B is

A.  If all or some B is A of necessity, it is necessary also that some A  is B: for if there were no necessity,

neither would some of the Bs  be  A necessarily. But the particular negative does not convert, for  the  same

reason which we have already stated. 

In respect of possible premisses, since possibility is used in  several senses (for we say that what is necessary

and what is not  necessary and what is potential is possible), affirmative statements  will all convert in a

manner similar to those described. For if it  is  possible that all or some B is A, it will be possible that some A

is  B. For if that were not possible, then no B could possibly be A.  This  has been already proved. But in

negative statements the case is  different. Whatever is said to be possible, either because B  necessarily is A, or

because B is not necessarily A, admits of  conversion like other negative statements, e.g. if one should say,  it

is possible that man is not horse, or that no garment is white. For  in  the former case the one term necessarily

does not belong to the  other;  in the latter there is no necessity that it should: and the  premiss  converts like

other negative statements. For if it is possible  for no  man to be a horse, it is also admissible for no horse to be

a  man; and  if it is admissible for no garment to be white, it is also  admissible  for nothing white to be a

garment. For if any white thing  must be a  garment, then some garment will necessarily be white. This  has

been  already proved. The particular negative also must be  treated like  those dealt with above. But if anything

is said to be  possible because  it is the general rule and natural (and it is in this  way we define  the possible),

the negative premisses can no longer be  converted like  the simple negatives; the universal negative premiss

does not convert,  and the particular does. This will be plain when  we speak about the  possible. At present we

may take this much as clear  in addition to  what has been said: the statement that it is possible  that no B is A

or some B is not A is affirmative in form: for the  expression 'is  possible' ranks along with 'is', and 'is' makes

an  affirmation always  and in every case, whatever the terms to which it  is added, in  predication, e.g. 'it is

notgood' or 'it is notwhite'  or in a word  'it is notthis'. But this also will be proved in the  sequel. In

conversion these premisses will behave like the other  affirmative  propositions. 

4

After these distinctions we now state by what means, when, and how  every syllogism is produced;

subsequently we must speak of  demonstration. Syllogism should be discussed before demonstration  because

syllogism is the general: the demonstration is a sort of  syllogism, but not every syllogism is a demonstration. 

Whenever three terms are so related to one another that the last  is contained in the middle as in a whole, and

the middle is either  contained in, or excluded from, the first as in or from a whole, the  extremes must be

related by a perfect syllogism. I call that term  middle which is itself contained in another and contains another

in  itself: in position also this comes in the middle. By extremes I  mean  both that term which is itself

contained in another and that in  which  another is contained. If A is predicated of all B, and B of  all C, A  must

be predicated of all C: we have already explained what  we mean by  'predicated of all'. Similarly also, if A is

predicated  of no B, and B  of all C, it is necessary that no C will be A. 

But if the first term belongs to all the middle, but the middle to  none of the last term, there will be no

syllogism in respect of the  extremes; for nothing necessary follows from the terms being so  related; for it is

possible that the first should belong either to all  or to none of the last, so that neither a particular nor a

universal  conclusion is necessary. But if there is no necessary consequence,  there cannot be a syllogism by


PRIOR ANALYTICS

3 4



Top




Page No 8


means of these premisses. As an example  of a universal affirmative relation between the extremes we may

take  the terms animal, man, horse; of a universal negative relation, the  terms animal, man, stone. Nor again

can syllogism be formed when  neither the first term belongs to any of the middle, nor the middle to  any of the

last. As an example of a positive relation between the  extremes take the terms science, line, medicine: of a

negative  relation science, line, unit. 

If then the terms are universally related, it is clear in this  figure when a syllogism will be possible and when

not, and that if a  syllogism is possible the terms must be related as described, and if  they are so related there

will be a syllogism. 

But if one term is related universally, the other in part only, to  its subject, there must be a perfect syllogism

whenever universality  is posited with reference to the major term either affirmatively or  negatively, and

particularity with reference to the minor term  affirmatively: but whenever the universality is posited in

relation to  the minor term, or the terms are related in any other way, a syllogism  is impossible. I call that term

the major in which the middle is  contained and that term the minor which comes under the middle. Let  all B

be A and some C be B. Then if 'predicated of all' means what was  said above, it is necessary that some C is

A. And if no B is A but  some C is B, it is necessary that some C is not A. The meaning of  'predicated of none'

has also been defined. So there will be a perfect  syllogism. This holds good also if the premiss BC should be

indefinite, provided that it is affirmative: for we shall have the  same syllogism whether the premiss is

indefinite or particular. 

But if the universality is posited with respect to the minor term  either affirmatively or negatively, a syllogism

will not be  possible,  whether the major premiss is positive or negative,  indefinite or  particular: e.g. if some B

is or is not A, and all C  is B. As an  example of a positive relation between the extremes take  the terms  good,

state, wisdom: of a negative relation, good, state,  ignorance.  Again if no C is B, but some B is or is not A or

not  every B is A,  there cannot be a syllogism. Take the terms white,  horse, swan: white,  horse, raven. The

same terms may be taken also  if the premiss BA is  indefinite. 

Nor when the major premiss is universal, whether affirmative or  negative, and the minor premiss is negative

and particular, can  there  be a syllogism, whether the minor premiss be indefinite or  particular:  e.g. if all B is

A and some C is not B, or if not all C is  B. For the  major term may be predicable both of all and of none of

the  minor, to  some of which the middle term cannot be attributed.  Suppose the terms  are animal, man, white:

next take some of the  white things of which  man is not predicatedswan and snow: animal is  predicated of all

of  the one, but of none of the other. Consequently  there cannot be a  syllogism. Again let no B be A, but let

some C not  be B. Take the  terms inanimate, man, white: then take some white  things of which man  is not

predicatedswan and snow: the term  inanimate is predicated of  all of the one, of none of the other. 

Further since it is indefinite to say some C is not B, and it is  true that some C is not B, whether no C is B, or

not all C is B, and  since if terms are assumed such that no C is B, no syllogism follows  (this has already been

stated) it is clear that this arrangement of  terms will not afford a syllogism: otherwise one would have been

possible with a universal negative minor premiss. A similar proof  may  also be given if the universal premiss

is negative. 

Nor can there in any way be a syllogism if both the relations of  subject and predicate are particular, either

positively or negatively,  or the one negative and the other affirmative, or one indefinite and  the other definite,

or both indefinite. Terms common to all the  above  are animal, white, horse: animal, white, stone. 

It is clear then from what has been said that if there is a  syllogism in this figure with a particular conclusion,

the terms  must  be related as we have stated: if they are related otherwise, no  syllogism is possible anyhow. It

is evident also that all the  syllogisms in this figure are perfect (for they are all completed by  means of the

premisses originally taken) and that all conclusions  are  proved by this figure, viz. universal and particular,


PRIOR ANALYTICS

3 5



Top




Page No 9


affirmative and  negative. Such a figure I call the first. 

5

Whenever the same thing belongs to all of one subject, and to none  of another, or to all of each subject or to

none of either, I call  such a figure the second; by middle term in it I mean that which is  predicated of both

subjects, by extremes the terms of which this is  said, by major extreme that which lies near the middle, by

minor  that  which is further away from the middle. The middle term stands  outside  the extremes, and is first in

position. A syllogism cannot  be perfect  anyhow in this figure, but it may be valid whether the  terms are

related universally or not. 

If then the terms are related universally a syllogism will be  possible, whenever the middle belongs to all of

one subject and to  none of another (it does not matter which has the negative  relation),  but in no other way.

Let M be predicated of no N, but of  all O. Since,  then, the negative relation is convertible, N will  belong to no

M: but  M was assumed to belong to all O: consequently N  will belong to no O.  This has already been proved.

Again if M  belongs to all N, but to no  O, then N will belong to no O. For if M  belongs to no O, O belongs to

no M: but M (as was said) belongs to all  N: O then will belong to no  N: for the first figure has again been

formed. But since the negative  relation is convertible, N will  belong to no O. Thus it will be the  same

syllogism that proves both  conclusions. 

It is possible to prove these results also by reductio ad  impossibile. 

It is clear then that a syllogism is formed when the terms are so  related, but not a perfect syllogism; for

necessity is not perfectly  established merely from the original premisses; others also are  needed. 

But if M is predicated of every N and O, there cannot be a  syllogism. Terms to illustrate a positive relation

between the  extremes are substance, animal, man; a negative relation, substance,  animal, numbersubstance

being the middle term. 

Nor is a syllogism possible when M is predicated neither of any N  nor of any O. Terms to illustrate a positive

relation are line,  animal, man: a negative relation, line, animal, stone. 

It is clear then that if a syllogism is formed when the terms are  universally related, the terms must be related

as we stated at the  outset: for if they are otherwise related no necessary consequence  follows. 

If the middle term is related universally to one of the extremes,  a particular negative syllogism must result

whenever the middle term  is related universally to the major whether positively or  negatively,  and

particularly to the minor and in a manner opposite  to that of the  universal statement: by 'an opposite manner' I

mean, if  the universal  statement is negative, the particular is affirmative: if  the universal  is affirmative, the

particular is negative. For if M  belongs to no N,  but to some O, it is necessary that N does not belong  to some

O. For  since the negative statement is convertible, N will  belong to no M:  but M was admitted to belong to

some O: therefore N  will not belong to  some O: for the result is reached by means of the  first figure. Again  if

M belongs to all N, but not to some O, it is  necessary that N does  not belong to some O: for if N belongs to

all O,  and M is predicated  also of all N, M must belong to all O: but we  assumed that M does not  belong to

some O. And if M belongs to all N  but not to all O, we shall  conclude that N does not belong to all O:  the

proof is the same as the  above. But if M is predicated of all O,  but not of all N, there will  be no syllogism.

Take the terms animal,  substance, raven; animal,  white, raven. Nor will there be a conclusion  when M is

predicated of  no O, but of some N. Terms to illustrate a  positive relation between  the extremes are animal,

substance, unit:  a negative relation, animal,  substance, science. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

5 6



Top




Page No 10


If then the universal statement is opposed to the particular, we  have stated when a syllogism will be possible

and when not: but if the  premisses are similar in form, I mean both negative or both  affirmative, a syllogism

will not be possible anyhow. First let them  be negative, and let the major premiss be universal, e.g. let M

belong  to no N, and not to some O. It is possible then for N to belong either  to all O or to no O. Terms to

illustrate the negative relation are  black, snow, animal. But it is not possible to find terms of which the

extremes are related positively and universally, if M belongs to  some  O, and does not belong to some O. For

if N belonged to all O, but  M to  no N, then M would belong to no O: but we assumed that it belongs  to  some

O. In this way then it is not admissible to take terms: our  point  must be proved from the indefinite nature of

the particular  statement.  For since it is true that M does not belong to some O, even  if it  belongs to no O, and

since if it belongs to no O a syllogism  is (as we  have seen) not possible, clearly it will not be possible now

either. 

Again let the premisses be affirmative, and let the major premiss  as  before be universal, e.g. let M belong to

all N and to some O. It  is  possible then for N to belong to all O or to no O. Terms to  illustrate  the negative

relation are white, swan, stone. But it is not  possible  to take terms to illustrate the universal affirmative

relation, for  the reason already stated: the point must be proved from  the  indefinite nature of the particular

statement. But if the minor  premiss is universal, and M belongs to no O, and not to some N, it  is  possible for

N to belong either to all O or to no O. Terms for  the  positive relation are white, animal, raven: for the

negative  relation,  white, stone, raven. If the premisses are affirmative, terms  for the  negative relation are

white, animal, snow; for the positive  relation,  white, animal, swan. Evidently then, whenever the  premisses

are  similar in form, and one is universal, the other  particular, a  syllogism can, not be formed anyhow. Nor is

one possible  if the middle  term belongs to some of each of the extremes, or does  not belong to  some of either,

or belongs to some of the one, not to  some of the  other, or belongs to neither universally, or is related to  them

indefinitely. Common terms for all the above are white, animal,  man:  white, animal, inanimate.  It is clear

then from what has been said  that if the terms are related  to one another in the way stated, a  syllogism results

of necessity;  and if there is a syllogism, the terms  must be so related. But it is  evident also that all the

syllogisms in  this figure are imperfect: for  all are made perfect by certain  supplementary statements, which

either  are contained in the terms of  necessity or are assumed as  hypotheses, i.e. when we prove per

impossibile. And it is evident that  an affirmative conclusion is not  attained by means of this figure, but  all are

negative, whether  universal or particular. 

6

But if one term belongs to all, and another to none, of a third,  or if both belong to all, or to none, of it, I call

such a figure  the  third; by middle term in it I mean that of which both the  predicates  are predicated, by

extremes I mean the predicates, by the  major  extreme that which is further from the middle, by the minor that

which  is nearer to it. The middle term stands outside the extremes,  and is  last in position. A syllogism cannot

be perfect in this  figure either,  but it may be valid whether the terms are related  universally or not  to the

middle term. 

If they are universal, whenever both P and R belong to S, it  follows  that P will necessarily belong to some R.

For, since the  affirmative  statement is convertible, S will belong to some R:  consequently  since P belongs to

all S, and S to some R, P must belong  to some R:  for a syllogism in the first figure is produced. It is  possible

to  demonstrate this also per impossibile and by exposition.  For if both P  and R belong to all S, should one of

the Ss, e.g. N, be  taken, both  P and R will belong to this, and thus P will belong to  some R. 

If R belongs to all S, and P to no S, there will be a syllogism to  prove that P will necessarily not belong to

some R. This may be  demonstrated in the same way as before by converting the premiss RS.  It might be

proved also per impossibile, as in the former cases. But  if R belongs to no S, P to all S, there will be no

syllogism. Terms  for the positive relation are animal, horse, man: for the negative  relation animal, inanimate,


PRIOR ANALYTICS

6 7



Top




Page No 11


man. 

Nor can there be a syllogism when both terms are asserted of no S.  Terms for the positive relation are animal,

horse, inanimate; for  the  negative relation man, horse, inanimateinanimate being the middle  term. 

It is clear then in this figure also when a syllogism will be  possible and when not, if the terms are related

universally. For  whenever both the terms are affirmative, there will be a syllogism  to  prove that one extreme

belongs to some of the other; but when  they are  negative, no syllogism will be possible. But when one is

negative, the  other affirmative, if the major is negative, the minor  affirmative,  there will be a syllogism to

prove that the one extreme  does not  belong to some of the other: but if the relation is reversed,  no  syllogism

will be possible. If one term is related universally to  the  middle, the other in part only, when both are

affirmative there  must  be a syllogism, no matter which of the premisses is universal.  For if  R belongs to all S,

P to some S, P must belong to some R. For  since  the affirmative statement is convertible S will belong to

some  P:  consequently since R belongs to all S, and S to some P, R must also  belong to some P: therefore P

must belong to some R. 

Again if R belongs to some S, and P to all S, P must belong to  some R. This may be demonstrated in the

same way as the preceding. And  it is possible to demonstrate it also per impossibile and by  exposition, as in

the former cases. But if one term is affirmative,  the other negative, and if the affirmative is universal, a

syllogism  will be possible whenever the minor term is affirmative. For if R  belongs to all S, but P does not

belong to some S, it is necessary  that P does not belong to some R. For if P belongs to all R, and R  belongs to

all S, then P will belong to all S: but we assumed that  it  did not. Proof is possible also without reduction ad

impossibile,  if  one of the Ss be taken to which P does not belong. 

But whenever the major is affirmative, no syllogism will be  possible, e.g. if P belongs to all S and R does not

belong to some  S.  Terms for the universal affirmative relation are animate, man,  animal.  For the universal

negative relation it is not possible to  get terms,  if R belongs to some S, and does not belong to some S.  For if

P  belongs to all S, and R to some S, then P will belong to some  R: but  we assumed that it belongs to no R.

We must put the matter as  before.'  Since the expression 'it does not belong to some' is  indefinite, it  may be

used truly of that also which belongs to none.  But if R belongs  to no S, no syllogism is possible, as has been

shown.  Clearly then no  syllogism will be possible here. 

But if the negative term is universal, whenever the major is  negative and the minor affirmative there will be a

syllogism. For if P  belongs to no S, and R belongs to some S, P will not belong to some R:  for we shall have

the first figure again, if the premiss RS is  converted. 

But when the minor is negative, there will be no syllogism. Terms  for the positive relation are animal, man,

wild: for the negative  relation, animal, science, wildthe middle in both being the term  wild. 

Nor is a syllogism possible when both are stated in the negative,  but one is universal, the other particular.

When the minor is  related  universally to the middle, take the terms animal, science,  wild;  animal, man, wild.

When the major is related universally to  the  middle, take as terms for a negative relation raven, snow,  white.

For  a positive relation terms cannot be found, if R belongs  to some S, and  does not belong to some S. For if P

belongs to all R,  and R to some S,  then P belongs to some S: but we assumed that it  belongs to no S. Our

point, then, must be proved from the indefinite  nature of the  particular statement. 

Nor is a syllogism possible anyhow, if each of the extremes  belongs to some of the middle or does not

belong, or one belongs and  the other does not to some of the middle, or one belongs to some of  the middle,

the other not to all, or if the premisses are  indefinite.  Common terms for all are animal, man, white: animal,

inanimate, white. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

6 8



Top




Page No 12


It is clear then in this figure also when a syllogism will be  possible, and when not; and that if the terms are as

stated, a  syllogism results of necessity, and if there is a syllogism, the terms  must be so related. It is clear also

that all the syllogisms in this  figure are imperfect (for all are made perfect by certain  supplementary

assumptions), and that it will not be possible to  reach  a universal conclusion by means of this figure, whether

negative  or  affirmative. 

7

It is evident also that in all the figures, whenever a proper  syllogism does not result, if both the terms are

affirmative or  negative nothing necessary follows at all, but if one is  affirmative,  the other negative, and if the

negative is stated  universally, a  syllogism always results relating the minor to the  major term, e.g. if  A

belongs to all or some B, and B belongs to no C:  for if the  premisses are converted it is necessary that C does

not  belong to some  A. Similarly also in the other figures: a syllogism  always results by  means of conversion.

It is evident also that the  substitution of an  indefinite for a particular affirmative will effect  the same

syllogism  in all the figures. 

It is clear too that all the imperfect syllogisms are made perfect  by means of the first figure. For all are

brought to a conclusion  either ostensively or per impossibile. In both ways the first figure  is formed: if they

are made perfect ostensively, because (as we saw)  all are brought to a conclusion by means of conversion,

and conversion  produces the first figure: if they are proved per impossibile, because  on the assumption of the

false statement the syllogism comes about  by  means of the first figure, e.g. in the last figure, if A and B

belong  to all C, it follows that A belongs to some B: for if A  belonged to no  B, and B belongs to all C, A

would belong to no C:  but (as we stated)  it belongs to all C. Similarly also with the rest. 

It is possible also to reduce all syllogisms to the universal  syllogisms in the first figure. Those in the second

figure are clearly  made perfect by these, though not all in the same way; the universal  syllogisms are made

perfect by converting the negative premiss, each  of the particular syllogisms by reductio ad impossibile. In

the  first  figure particular syllogisms are indeed made perfect by  themselves,  but it is possible also to prove

them by means of the  second figure,  reducing them ad impossibile, e.g. if A belongs to  all B, and B to  some

C, it follows that A belongs to some C. For if it  belonged to no  C, and belongs to all B, then B will belong to

no C:  this we know by  means of the second figure. Similarly also  demonstration will be  possible in the case

of the negative. For if A  belongs to no B, and B  belongs to some C, A will not belong to some C:  for if it

belonged to  all C, and belongs to no B, then B will belong  to no C: and this (as  we saw) is the middle figure.

Consequently,  since all syllogisms in  the middle figure can be reduced to  universal syllogisms in the first

figure, and since particular  syllogisms in the first figure can be  reduced to syllogisms in the  middle figure, it

is clear that  particular syllogisms can be reduced  to universal syllogisms in the  first figure. Syllogisms in the

third  figure, if the terms are  universal, are directly made perfect by means  of those syllogisms;  but, when one

of the premisses is particular,  by means of the  particular syllogisms in the first figure: and these  (we have

seen)  may be reduced to the universal syllogisms in the first  figure:  consequently also the particular

syllogisms in the third  figure may be  so reduced. It is clear then that all syllogisms may  be reduced to the

universal syllogisms in the first figure. 

We have stated then how syllogisms which prove that something  belongs or does not belong to something

else are constituted, both how  syllogisms of the same figure are constituted in themselves, and how

syllogisms of different figures are related to one another. 

8

Since there is a difference according as something belongs,  necessarily belongs, or may belong to something

else (for many  things  belong indeed, but not necessarily, others neither  necessarily nor  indeed at all, but it is


PRIOR ANALYTICS

7 9



Top




Page No 13


possible for them to belong),  it is clear  that there will be different syllogisms to prove each of  these  relations,

and syllogisms with differently related terms, one  syllogism concluding from what is necessary, another from

what is, a  third from what is possible. 

There is hardly any difference between syllogisms from necessary  premisses and syllogisms from premisses

which merely assert. When  the  terms are put in the same way, then, whether something belongs  or

necessarily belongs (or does not belong) to something else, a  syllogism will or will not result alike in both

cases, the only  difference being the addition of the expression 'necessarily' to the  terms. For the negative

statement is convertible alike in both  cases,  and we should give the same account of the expressions 'to be

contained in something as in a whole' and 'to be predicated of all  of  something'. With the exceptions to be

made below, the conclusion  will  be proved to be necessary by means of conversion, in the same  manner  as in

the case of simple predication. But in the middle  figure when  the universal statement is affirmative, and the

particular  negative,  and again in the third figure when the universal is  affirmative and  the particular negative,

the demonstration will not  take the same  form, but it is necessary by the 'exposition' of a  part of the subject  of

the particular negative proposition, to which  the predicate does  not belong, to make the syllogism in reference

to  this: with terms so  chosen the conclusion will necessarily follow. But  if the relation is  necessary in respect

of the part taken, it must  hold of some of that  term in which this part is included: for the part  taken is just

some  of that. And each of the resulting syllogisms is in  the appropriate  figure. 

9

It happens sometimes also that when one premiss is necessary the  conclusion is necessary, not however when

either premiss is necessary,  but only when the major is, e.g. if A is taken as necessarily  belonging or not

belonging to B, but B is taken as simply belonging to  C: for if the premisses are taken in this way, A will

necessarily  belong or not belong to C. For since necessarily belongs, or does  not  belong, to every B, and since

C is one of the Bs, it is clear that  for  C also the positive or the negative relation to A will hold  necessarily.

But if the major premiss is not necessary, but the  minor  is necessary, the conclusion will not be necessary.

For if it  were, it  would result both through the first figure and through the  third that  A belongs necessarily to

some B. But this is false; for B  may be such  that it is possible that A should belong to none of it.  Further, an

example also makes it clear that the conclusion not be  necessary, e.g.  if A were movement, B animal, C man:

man is an  animal necessarily, but  an animal does not move necessarily, nor  does man. Similarly also if  the

major premiss is negative; for the  proof is the same. 

In particular syllogisms, if the universal premiss is necessary,  then the conclusion will be necessary; but if the

particular, the  conclusion will not be necessary, whether the universal premiss is  negative or affirmative. First

let the universal be necessary, and let  A belong to all B necessarily, but let B simply belong to some C: it  is

necessary then that A belongs to some C necessarily: for C falls  under B, and A was assumed to belong

necessarily to all B. Similarly  also if the syllogism should be negative: for the proof will be the  same. But if

the particular premiss is necessary, the conclusion  will  not be necessary: for from the denial of such a

conclusion  nothing  impossible results, just as it does not in the universal  syllogisms.  The same is true of

negative syllogisms. Try the terms  movement,  animal, white. 

10

In the second figure, if the negative premiss is necessary, then  the  conclusion will be necessary, but if the

affirmative, not  necessary.  First let the negative be necessary; let A be possible of  no B, and  simply belong to

C. Since then the negative statement is  convertible, B is possible of no A. But A belongs to all C;

consequently B is possible of no C. For C falls under A. The same  result would be obtained if the minor

premiss were negative: for if  A  is possible be of no C, C is possible of no A: but A belongs to  all B,

consequently C is possible of none of the Bs: for again we have  obtained the first figure. Neither then is B


PRIOR ANALYTICS

9 10



Top




Page No 14


possible of C: for  conversion is possible without modifying the relation. 

But if the affirmative premiss is necessary, the conclusion will  not  be necessary. Let A belong to all B

necessarily, but to no C  simply.  If then the negative premiss is converted, the first figure  results.  But it has

been proved in the case of the first figure that  if the  negative major premiss is not necessary the conclusion

will not  be  necessary either. Therefore the same result will obtain here.  Further,  if the conclusion is

necessary, it follows that C necessarily  does not  belong to some A. For if B necessarily belongs to no C, C

will  necessarily belong to no B. But B at any rate must belong to some  A,  if it is true (as was assumed) that A

necessarily belongs to all B.  Consequently it is necessary that C does not belong to some A. But  nothing

prevents such an A being taken that it is possible for C to  belong to all of it. Further one might show by an

exposition of  terms  that the conclusion is not necessary without qualification,  though it  is a necessary

conclusion from the premisses. For example  let A be  animal, B man, C white, and let the premisses be

assumed to  correspond  to what we had before: it is possible that animal should  belong to  nothing white. Man

then will not belong to anything white,  but not  necessarily: for it is possible for man to be born white,  not

however  so long as animal belongs to nothing white. Consequently  under these  conditions the conclusion will

be necessary, but it is not  necessary  without qualification. 

Similar results will obtain also in particular syllogisms. For  whenever the negative premiss is both universal

and necessary, then  the conclusion will be necessary: but whenever the affirmative premiss  is universal, the

negative particular, the conclusion will not be  necessary. First then let the negative premiss be both universal

and  necessary: let it be possible for no B that A should belong to it, and  let A simply belong to some C. Since

the negative statement is  convertible, it will be possible for no A that B should belong to  it:  but A belongs to

some C; consequently B necessarily does not  belong to  some of the Cs. Again let the affirmative premiss be

both  universal  and necessary, and let the major premiss be affirmative.  If then A  necessarily belongs to all B,

but does not belong to some C,  it is  clear that B will not belong to some C, but not necessarily. For  the  same

terms can be used to demonstrate the point, which were used  in  the universal syllogisms. Nor again, if the

negative statement is  necessary but particular, will the conclusion be necessary. The  point  can be

demonstrated by means of the same terms. 

11

In the last figure when the terms are related universally to the  middle, and both premisses are affirmative, if

one of the two is  necessary, then the conclusion will be necessary. But if one is  negative, the other

affirmative, whenever the negative is necessary  the conclusion also will be necessary, but whenever the

affirmative is  necessary the conclusion will not be necessary. First let both the  premisses be affirmative, and

let A and B belong to all C, and let  AC  be necessary. Since then B belongs to all C, C also will belong  to

some B, because the universal is convertible into the particular:  consequently if A belongs necessarily to all

C, and C belongs to  some  B, it is necessary that A should belong to some B also. For B  is under  C. The first

figure then is formed. A similar proof will be  given also  if BC is necessary. For C is convertible with some

A:  consequently if  B belongs necessarily to all C, it will belong  necessarily also to  some A. 

Again let AC be negative, BC affirmative, and let the negative  premiss be necessary. Since then C is

convertible with some B, but A  necessarily belongs to no C, A will necessarily not belong to some B  either:

for B is under C. But if the affirmative is necessary, the  conclusion will not be necessary. For suppose BC is

affirmative and  necessary, while AC is negative and not necessary. Since then the  affirmative is convertible,

C also will belong to some B  necessarily:  consequently if A belongs to none of the Cs, while C  belongs to

some  of the Bs, A will not belong to some of the Bsbut not  of necessity;  for it has been proved, in the case

of the first figure,  that if the  negative premiss is not necessary, neither will the  conclusion be  necessary.

Further, the point may be made clear by  considering the  terms. Let the term A be 'good', let that which B

signifies be  'animal', let the term C be 'horse'. It is possible  then that the term  good should belong to no horse,


PRIOR ANALYTICS

11 11



Top




Page No 15


and it is necessary  that the term  animal should belong to every horse: but it is not  necessary that some  animal

should not be good, since it is possible  for every animal to be  good. Or if that is not possible, take as the  term

'awake' or  'asleep': for every animal can accept these. 

If, then, the premisses are universal, we have stated when the  conclusion will be necessary. But if one

premiss is universal, the  other particular, and if both are affirmative, whenever the  universal  is necessary the

conclusion also must be necessary. The  demonstration  is the same as before; for the particular affirmative

also is  convertible. If then it is necessary that B should belong to  all C,  and A falls under C, it is necessary

that B should belong to  some A.  But if B must belong to some A, then A must belong to some  B: for

conversion is possible. Similarly also if AC should be  necessary and  universal: for B falls under C. But if the

particular  premiss is  necessary, the conclusion will not be necessary. Let the  premiss BC be  both particular

and necessary, and let A belong to all  C, not however  necessarily. If the proposition BC is converted the  first

figure is  formed, and the universal premiss is not necessary,  but the particular  is necessary. But when the

premisses were thus, the  conclusion (as we  proved was not necessary: consequently it is not  here either.

Further,  the point is clear if we look at the terms.  Let A be waking, B biped,  and C animal. It is necessary that

B  should belong to some C, but it  is possible for A to belong to C,  and that A should belong to B is not

necessary. For there is no  necessity that some biped should be asleep  or awake. Similarly and  by means of the

same terms proof can be made,  should the proposition  AC be both particular and necessary. 

But if one premiss is affirmative, the other negative, whenever  the universal is both negative and necessary

the conclusion also  will  be necessary. For if it is not possible that A should belong to  any C,  but B belongs to

some C, it is necessary that A should not  belong to  some B. But whenever the affirmative proposition is

necessary, whether  universal or particular, or the negative is  particular, the conclusion  will not be necessary.

The proof of this by  reduction will be the same  as before; but if terms are wanted, when  the universal

affirmative is  necessary, take the terms  'waking''animal''man', 'man' being middle,  and when the

affirmative is particular and necessary, take the terms  'waking''animal''white': for it is necessary that animal

should  belong to some white thing, but it is possible that waking should  belong to none, and it is not

necessary that waking should not  belong  to some animal. But when the negative proposition being  particular

is  necessary, take the terms 'biped', 'moving', 'animal',  'animal' being  middle. 

12

It is clear then that a simple conclusion is not reached unless  both  premisses are simple assertions, but a

necessary conclusion is  possible although one only of the premisses is necessary. But in  both  cases, whether

the syllogisms are affirmative or negative, it  is  necessary that one premiss should be similar to the

conclusion. I  mean  by 'similar', if the conclusion is a simple assertion, the  premiss  must be simple; if the

conclusion is necessary, the premiss  must be  necessary. Consequently this also is clear, that the  conclusion

will  be neither necessary nor simple unless a necessary  or simple premiss  is assumed. 

13

Perhaps enough has been said about the proof of necessity, how it  comes about and how it differs from the

proof of a simple statement.  We proceed to discuss that which is possible, when and how and by what  means

it can be proved. I use the terms 'to be possible' and 'the  possible' of that which is not necessary but, being

assumed, results  in nothing impossible. We say indeed ambiguously of the necessary that  it is possible. But

that my definition of the possible is correct is  clear from the phrases by which we deny or on the contrary

affirm  possibility. For the expressions 'it is not possible to belong', 'it  is impossible to belong', and 'it is

necessary not to belong' are  either identical or follow from one another; consequently their  opposites also, 'it

is possible to belong', 'it is not impossible to  belong', and 'it is not necessary not to belong', will either be

identical or follow from one another. For of everything the  affirmation or the denial holds good. That which


PRIOR ANALYTICS

12 12



Top




Page No 16


is possible then will  be not necessary and that which is not necessary will be possible.  It  results that all

premisses in the mode of possibility are  convertible  into one another. I mean not that the affirmative are

convertible into  the negative, but that those which are affirmative in  form admit of  conversion by opposition,

e.g. 'it is possible to  belong' may be  converted into 'it is possible not to belong', and  'it is possible for  A to

belong to all B' into 'it is possible for A  to belong to no B' or  'not to all B', and 'it is possible for A to  belong

to some B' into  'it is possible for A not to belong to some B'.  And similarly the  other propositions in this

mode can be converted.  For since that which  is possible is not necessary, and that which is  not necessary may

possibly not belong, it is clear that if it is  possible that A should  belong to B, it is possible also that it should

not belong to B: and  if it is possible that it should belong to all,  it is also possible  that it should not belong to

all. The same holds  good in the case of  particular affirmations: for the proof is  identical. And such  premisses

are affirmative and not negative; for  'to be possible' is in  the same rank as 'to be', as was said above. 

Having made these distinctions we next point out that the  expression  'to be possible' is used in two ways. In

one it means to  happen  generally and fall short of necessity, e.g. man's turning grey  or  growing or decaying,

or generally what naturally belongs to a thing  (for this has not its necessity unbroken, since man's existence is

not  continuous for ever, although if a man does exist, it comes about  either necessarily or generally). In

another sense the expression  means the indefinite, which can be both thus and not thus, e.g. an  animal's

walking or an earthquake's taking place while it is  walking,  or generally what happens by chance: for none of

these  inclines by  nature in the one way more than in the opposite. 

That which is possible in each of its two senses is convertible  into  its opposite, not however in the same way:

but what is natural is  convertible because it does not necessarily belong (for in this  sense  it is possible that a

man should not grow grey) and what is  indefinite  is convertible because it inclines this way no more than

that. Science  and demonstrative syllogism are not concerned with  things which are  indefinite, because the

middle term is uncertain; but  they are  concerned with things that are natural, and as a rule  arguments and

inquiries are made about things which are possible in  this sense.  Syllogisms indeed can be made about the

former, but it  is unusual at  any rate to inquire about them. 

These matters will be treated more definitely in the sequel; our  business at present is to state the moods and

nature of the  syllogism  made from possible premisses. The expression 'it is possible  for this  to belong to that'

may be understood in two senses: 'that'  may mean  either that to which 'that' belongs or that to which it may

belong;  for the expression 'A is possible of the subject of B' means  that it  is possible either of that of which B

is stated or of that  of which B  may possibly be stated. It makes no difference whether we  say, A is  possible of

the subject of B, or all B admits of A. It is  clear then  that the expression 'A may possibly belong to all B'

might be used in  two senses. First then we must state the nature and  characteristics of  the syllogism which

arises if B is possible of  the subject of C, and A  is possible of the subject of B. For thus both  premisses are

assumed  in the mode of possibility; but whenever A is  possible of that of  which B is true, one premiss is a

simple  assertion, the other a  problematic. Consequently we must start from  premisses which are  similar in

form, as in the other cases. 

14

Whenever A may possibly belong to all B, and B to all C, there  will be a perfect syllogism to prove that A

may possibly belong to all  C. This is clear from the definition: for it was in this way that we  explained 'to be

possible for one term to belong to all of another'.  Similarly if it is possible for A to belong no B, and for B to

belong  to all C, then it is possible for A to belong to no C. For  the  statement that it is possible for A not to

belong to that of which  B  may be true means (as we saw) that none of those things which can  possibly fall

under the term B is left out of account. But whenever  A  may belong to all B, and B may belong to no C, then

indeed no  syllogism results from the premisses assumed, but if the premiss BC is  converted after the manner

of problematic propositions, the same  syllogism results as before. For since it is possible that B should  belong


PRIOR ANALYTICS

14 13



Top




Page No 17


to no C, it is possible also that it should belong to all C.  This has been stated above. Consequently if B is

possible for all C,  and A is possible for all B, the same syllogism again results.  Similarly if in both the

premisses the negative is joined with 'it  is  possible': e.g. if A may belong to none of the Bs, and B to none of

the Cs. No syllogism results from the assumed premisses, but if they  are converted we shall have the same

syllogism as before. It is  clear  then that if the minor premiss is negative, or if both premisses  are  negative,

either no syllogism results, or if one it is not  perfect.  For the necessity results from the conversion. 

But if one of the premisses is universal, the other particular,  when  the major premiss is universal there will be

a perfect syllogism.  For if A is possible for all B, and B for some C, then A is possible  for some C. This is

clear from the definition of being possible. Again  if A may belong to no B, and B may belong to some of the

Cs, it is  necessary that A may possibly not belong to some of the Cs. The  proof  is the same as above. But if

the particular premiss is negative,  and  the universal is affirmative, the major still being universal  and the

minor particular, e.g. A is possible for all B, B may possibly  not  belong to some C, then a clear syllogism

does not result from  the  assumed premisses, but if the particular premiss is converted  and it  is laid down that

B possibly may belong to some C, we shall  have the  same conclusion as before, as in the cases given at the

beginning. 

But if the major premiss is the minor universal, whether both are  affirmative, or negative, or different in

quality, or if both are  indefinite or particular, in no way will a syllogism be possible.  For  nothing prevents B

from reaching beyond A, so that as predicates  cover  unequal areas. Let C be that by which B extends beyond

A. To C  it is  not possible that A should belongeither to all or to none or to  some  or not to some, since

premisses in the mode of possibility are  convertible and it is possible for B to belong to more things than A

can. Further, this is obvious if we take terms; for if the premisses  are as assumed, the major term is both

possible for none of the  minor  and must belong to all of it. Take as terms common to all the  cases  under

consideration 'animal''white''man', where the major  belongs  necessarily to the minor;

'animal''white''garment', where it  is not  possible that the major should belong to the minor. It is clear  then

that if the terms are related in this manner, no syllogism  results.  For every syllogism proves that something

belongs either  simply or  necessarily or possibly. It is clear that there is no  proof of the  first or of the second.

For the affirmative is  destroyed by the  negative, and the negative by the affirmative.  There remains the proof

of possibility. But this is impossible. For it  has been proved that if  the terms are related in this manner it is

both necessary that the  major should belong to all the minor and not  possible that it should  belong to any.

Consequently there cannot be  a syllogism to prove the  possibility; for the necessary (as we stated)  is not

possible. 

It is clear that if the terms are universal in possible premisses  a syllogism always results in the first figure,

whether they are  affirmative or negative, only a perfect syllogism results in the first  case, an imperfect in the

second. But possibility must be understood  according to the definition laid down, not as covering necessity.

This  is sometimes forgotten. 

15

If one premiss is a simple proposition, the other a problematic,  whenever the major premiss indicates

possibility all the syllogisms  will be perfect and establish possibility in the sense defined; but  whenever the

minor premiss indicates possibility all the syllogisms  will be imperfect, and those which are negative will

establish not  possibility according to the definition, but that the major does not  necessarily belong to any, or

to all, of the minor. For if this is so,  we say it is possible that it should belong to none or not to all. Let  A be

possible for all B, and let B belong to all C. Since C falls  under B, and A is possible for all B, clearly it is

possible for all C  also. So a perfect syllogism results. Likewise if the premiss AB is  negative, and the premiss

BC is affirmative, the former stating  possible, the latter simple attribution, a perfect syllogism results  proving

that A possibly belongs to no C. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

15 14



Top




Page No 18


It is clear that perfect syllogisms result if the minor premiss  states simple belonging: but that syllogisms will

result if the  modality of the premisses is reversed, must be proved per impossibile.  At the same time it will be

evident that they are imperfect: for the  proof proceeds not from the premisses assumed. First we must state

that if B's being follows necessarily from A's being, B's  possibility  will follow necessarily from A's

possibility. Suppose, the  terms being  so related, that A is possible, and B is impossible. If  then that  which is

possible, when it is possible for it to be, might  happen, and  if that which is impossible, when it is impossible,

could not happen,  and if at the same time A is possible and B  impossible, it would be  possible for A to

happen without B, and if  to happen, then to be. For  that which has happened, when it has  happened, is. But

we must take  the impossible and the possible not  only in the sphere of becoming,  but also in the spheres of

truth and  predicability, and the various  other spheres in which we speak of  the possible: for it will be alike  in

all. Further we must  understand the statement that B's being  depends on A's being, not as  meaning that if

some single thing A is, B  will be: for nothing follows  of necessity from the being of some one  thing, but from

two at  least, i.e. when the premisses are related in  the manner stated to  be that of the syllogism. For if C is

predicated  of D, and D of F,  then C is necessarily predicated of F. And if each  is possible, the  conclusion also

is possible. If then, for example,  one should indicate  the premisses by A, and the conclusion by B, it  would

not only  result that if A is necessary B is necessary, but also  that if A is  possible, B is possible. 

Since this is proved it is evident that if a false and not  impossible assumption is made, the consequence of the

assumption  will  also be false and not impossible: e.g. if A is false, but not  impossible, and if B is the

consequence of A, B also will be false but  not impossible. For since it has been proved that if B's being is  the

consequence of A's being, then B's possibility will follow from  A's  possibility (and A is assumed to be

possible), consequently B will  be  possible: for if it were impossible, the same thing would at the  same  time

be possible and impossible. 

Since we have defined these points, let A belong to all B, and B  be possible for all C: it is necessary then that

should be a  possible  attribute for all C. Suppose that it is not possible, but  assume that  B belongs to all C: this

is false but not impossible. If  then A is not  possible for C but B belongs to all C, then A is not  possible for all

B: for a syllogism is formed in the third degree. But  it was assumed  that A is a possible attribute for all B. It

is  necessary then that A  is possible for all C. For though the assumption  we made is false and  not impossible,

the conclusion is impossible.  It is possible also in  the first figure to bring about the  impossibility, by

assuming that B  belongs to C. For if B belongs to  all C, and A is possible for all B,  then A would be possible

for all  C. But the assumption was made that A  is not possible for all C. 

We must understand 'that which belongs to all' with no limitation  in  respect of time, e.g. to the present or to a

particular period, but  simply without qualification. For it is by the help of such  premisses  that we make

syllogisms, since if the premiss is  understood with  reference to the present moment, there cannot be a

syllogism. For  nothing perhaps prevents 'man' belonging at a  particular time to  everything that is moving, i.e.

if nothing else  were moving: but  'moving' is possible for every horse; yet 'man' is  possible for no  horse.

Further let the major term be 'animal', the  middle 'moving',  the the minor 'man'. The premisses then will be as

before, but the  conclusion necessary, not possible. For man is  necessarily animal. It  is clear then that the

universal must be  understood simply, without  limitation in respect of time. 

Again let the premiss AB be universal and negative, and assume  that A belongs to no B, but B possibly

belongs to all C. These  propositions being laid down, it is necessary that A possibly  belongs  to no C. Suppose

that it cannot belong, and that B belongs  to C, as  above. It is necessary then that A belongs to some B: for  we

have a  syllogism in the third figure: but this is impossible.  Thus it will be  possible for A to belong to no C;

for if at is  supposed false, the  consequence is an impossible one. This syllogism  then does not  establish that

which is possible according to the  definition, but that  which does not necessarily belong to any part  of the

subject (for this  is the contradictory of the assumption  which was made: for it was  supposed that A

necessarily belongs to some  C, but the syllogism per  impossibile establishes the contradictory  which is

opposed to this).  Further, it is clear also from an example  that the conclusion will not  establish possibility.


PRIOR ANALYTICS

15 15



Top




Page No 19


Let A be  'raven', B 'intelligent', and C 'man'.  A then belongs to no B: for  no intelligent thing is a raven. But B

is  possible for all C: for  every man may possibly be intelligent. But A  necessarily belongs to no  C: so the

conclusion does not establish  possibility. But neither is it  always necessary. Let A be 'moving', B  'science', C

'man'. A then will  belong to no B; but B is possible for  all C. And the conclusion will  not be necessary. For it

is not  necessary that no man should move;  rather it is not necessary that any  man should move. Clearly then

the conclusion establishes that one term  does not necessarily belong  to any instance of another term. But we

must take our terms better. 

If the minor premiss is negative and indicates possibility, from  the  actual premisses taken there can be no

syllogism, but if the  problematic premiss is converted, a syllogism will be possible, as  before. Let A belong

to all B, and let B possibly belong to no C. If  the terms are arranged thus, nothing necessarily follows: but if

the  proposition BC is converted and it is assumed that B is possible for  all C, a syllogism results as before:

for the terms are in the same  relative positions. Likewise if both the relations are negative, if  the major

premiss states that A does not belong to B, and the minor  premiss indicates that B may possibly belong to no

C. Through the  premisses actually taken nothing necessary results in any way; but  if  the problematic premiss

is converted, we shall have a syllogism.  Suppose that A belongs to no B, and B may possibly belong to no C.

Through these comes nothing necessary. But if B is assumed to be  possible for all C (and this is true) and if

the premiss AB remains as  before, we shall again have the same syllogism. But if it be assumed  that B does

not belong to any C, instead of possibly not belonging,  there cannot be a syllogism anyhow, whether the

premiss AB is negative  or affirmative. As common instances of a necessary and positive  relation we may take

the terms whiteanimalsnow: of a necessary and  negative relation, whiteanimalpitch. Clearly then if the

terms are  universal, and one of the premisses is assertoric, the other  problematic, whenever the minor premiss

is problematic a syllogism  always results, only sometimes it results from the premisses that  are  taken,

sometimes it requires the conversion of one premiss. We  have  stated when each of these happens and the

reason why. But if  one of  the relations is universal, the other particular, then whenever  the  major premiss is

universal and problematic, whether affirmative or  negative, and the particular is affirmative and assertoric,

there will  be a perfect syllogism, just as when the terms are universal. The  demonstration is the same as

before. But whenever the major premiss is  universal, but assertoric, not problematic, and the minor is

particular and problematic, whether both premisses are negative or  affirmative, or one is negative, the other

affirmative, in all cases  there will be an imperfect syllogism. Only some of them will be proved  per

impossibile, others by the conversion of the problematic  premiss,  as has been shown above. And a syllogism

will be possible  by means of  conversion when the major premiss is universal and  assertoric, whether  positive

or negative, and the minor particular,  negative, and  problematic, e.g. if A belongs to all B or to no B,  and B

may possibly  not belong to some C. For if the premiss BC is  converted in respect of  possibility, a syllogism

results. But whenever  the particular premiss  is assertoric and negative, there cannot be a  syllogism. As

instances  of the positive relation we may take the terms  whiteanimalsnow; of  the negative,

whiteanimalpitch. For the  demonstration must be made  through the indefinite nature of the  particular

premiss. But if the  minor premiss is universal, and the  major particular, whether either  premiss is negative or

affirmative,  problematic or assertoric, nohow  is a syllogism possible. Nor is a  syllogism possible when the

premisses are particular or indefinite,  whether problematic or  assertoric, or the one problematic, the other

assertoric. The  demonstration is the same as above. As instances of  the necessary and  positive relation we

may take the terms  animalwhiteman; of the  necessary and negative relation,  animalwhitegarment. It is

evident  then that if the major premiss  is universal, a syllogism always  results, but if the minor is  universal

nothing at all can ever be  proved. 

16

Whenever one premiss is necessary, the other problematic, there  will  be a syllogism when the terms are

related as before; and a  perfect  syllogism when the minor premiss is necessary. If the  premisses are

affirmative the conclusion will be problematic, not  assertoric,  whether the premisses are universal or not: but


PRIOR ANALYTICS

16 16



Top




Page No 20


if one is  affirmative,  the other negative, when the affirmative is necessary the  conclusion  will be problematic,

not negative assertoric; but when the  negative is  necessary the conclusion will be problematic negative, and

assertoric negative, whether the premisses are universal or not.  Possibility in the conclusion must be

understood in the same manner as  before. There cannot be an inference to the necessary negative  proposition:

for 'not necessarily to belong' is different from  'necessarily not to belong'. 

If the premisses are affirmative, clearly the conclusion which  follows is not necessary. Suppose A necessarily

belongs to all B,  and  let B be possible for all C. We shall have an imperfect  syllogism to  prove that A may

belong to all C. That it is imperfect is  clear from  the proof: for it will be proved in the same manner as  above.

Again,  let A be possible for all B, and let B necessarily  belong to all C. We  shall then have a syllogism to

prove that A may  belong to all C, not  that A does belong to all C: and it is perfect,  not imperfect: for it  is

completed directly through the original  premisses. 

But if the premisses are not similar in quality, suppose first  that the negative premiss is necessary, and let

necessarily A not be  possible for any B, but let B be possible for all C. It is necessary  then that A belongs to

no C. For suppose A to belong to all C or to  some C. Now we assumed that A is not possible for any B. Since

then  the negative proposition is convertible, B is not possible for any  A.  But A is supposed to belong to all C

or to some C. Consequently B  will  not be possible for any C or for all C. But it was originally  laid  down that

B is possible for all C. And it is clear that the  possibility of belonging can be inferred, since the fact of not

belonging is inferred. Again, let the affirmative premiss be  necessary, and let A possibly not belong to any B,

and let B  necessarily belong to all C. The syllogism will be perfect, but it  will establish a problematic

negative, not an assertoric negative. For  the major premiss was problematic, and further it is not possible to

prove the assertoric conclusion per impossibile. For if it were  supposed that A belongs to some C, and it is

laid down that A possibly  does not belong to any B, no impossible relation between B and C  follows from

these premisses. But if the minor premiss is negative,  when it is problematic a syllogism is possible by

conversion, as  above; but when it is necessary no syllogism can be formed. Nor  again  when both premisses

are negative, and the minor is necessary.  The same  terms as before serve both for the positive

relationwhiteanimalsnow, and for the negative  relationwhiteanimalpitch. 

The same relation will obtain in particular syllogisms. Whenever  the  negative proposition is necessary, the

conclusion will be negative  assertoric: e.g. if it is not possible that A should belong to any  B,  but B may

belong to some of the Cs, it is necessary that A should  not  belong to some of the Cs. For if A belongs to all C,

but cannot  belong  to any B, neither can B belong to any A. So if A belongs to all  C, to  none of the Cs can B

belong. But it was laid down that B may  belong to  some C. But when the particular affirmative in the

negative syllogism,  e.g. BC the minor premiss, or the universal  proposition in the  affirmative syllogism, e.g.

AB the major premiss,  is necessary, there  will not be an assertoric conclusion. The  demonstration is the same

as  before. But if the minor premiss is  universal, and problematic,  whether affirmative or negative, and the

major premiss is particular  and necessary, there cannot be a  syllogism. Premisses of this kind are  possible

both where the relation  is positive and necessary, e.g.  animalwhiteman, and where it is  necessary and

negative, e.g.  animalwhitegarment. But when the  universal is necessary, the  particular problematic, if the

universal  is negative we may take the  terms animalwhiteraven to illustrate the  positive relation, or

animalwhitepitch to illustrate the negative;  and if the universal is  affirmative we may take the terms

animalwhiteswan to illustrate the  positive relation, and  animalwhitesnow to illustrate the negative  and

necessary relation.  Nor again is a syllogism possible when the  premisses are indefinite,  or both particular.

Terms applicable in  either case to illustrate  the positive relation are animalwhiteman:  to illustrate the

negative, animalwhiteinanimate. For the relation  of animal to some  white, and of white to some inanimate,

is both  necessary and  positive and necessary and negative. Similarly if the  relation is  problematic: so the

terms may be used for all cases. 

Clearly then from what has been said a syllogism results or not  from  similar relations of the terms whether we

are dealing with simple  existence or necessity, with this exception, that if the negative  premiss is assertoric


PRIOR ANALYTICS

16 17



Top




Page No 21


the conclusion is problematic, but if the  negative premiss is necessary the conclusion is both problematic and

negative assertoric. [It is clear also that all the syllogisms are  imperfect and are perfected by means of the

figures above mentioned.] 

17

In the second figure whenever both premisses are problematic, no  syllogism is possible, whether the

premisses are affirmative or  negative, universal or particular. But when one premiss is assertoric,  the other

problematic, if the affirmative is assertoric no syllogism  is possible, but if the universal negative is assertoric

a  conclusion  can always be drawn. Similarly when one premiss is  necessary, the  other problematic. Here also

we must understand the  term 'possible' in  the conclusion, in the same sense as before. 

First we must point out that the negative problematic proposition  is  not convertible, e.g. if A may belong to

no B, it does not follow  that  B may belong to no A. For suppose it to follow and assume that B  may  belong to

no A. Since then problematic affirmations are  convertible  with negations, whether they are contraries or

contradictories, and  since B may belong to no A, it is clear that B  may belong to all A.  But this is false: for if

all this can be that,  it does not follow  that all that can be this: consequently the  negative proposition is  not

convertible. Further, these propositions  are not incompatible,  'A may belong to no B', 'B necessarily does not

belong to some of  the As'; e.g. it is possible that no man should be  white (for it is  also possible that every

man should be white), but it  is not true to  say that it is possible that no white thing should be a  man: for  many

white things are necessarily not men, and the necessary  (as we  saw) other than the possible. 

Moreover it is not possible to prove the convertibility of these  propositions by a reductio ad absurdum, i.e. by

claiming assent to the  following argument: 'since it is false that B may belong to no A, it  is true that it cannot

belong to no A, for the one statement is the  contradictory of the other. But if this is so, it is true that B

necessarily belongs to some of the As: consequently A necessarily  belongs to some of the Bs. But this is

impossible.' The argument  cannot be admitted, for it does not follow that some A is  necessarily  B, if it is not

possible that no A should be B. For the  latter  expression is used in two senses, one if A some is  necessarily B,

another if some A is necessarily not B. For it is not  true to say that  that which necessarily does not belong to

some of the  As may possibly  not belong to any A, just as it is not true to say  that what  necessarily belongs to

some A may possibly belong to all  A. If any one  then should claim that because it is not possible for  C to

belong to  all D, it necessarily does not belong to some D, he  would make a false  assumption: for it does

belong to all D, but  because in some cases it  belongs necessarily, therefore we say that it  is not possible for it

to belong to all. Hence both the propositions  'A necessarily belongs  to some B' and 'A necessarily does not

belong  to some B' are opposed  to the proposition 'A belongs to all B'.  Similarly also they are  opposed to the

proposition 'A may belong to no  B'. It is clear then  that in relation to what is possible and not  possible, in the

sense  originally defined, we must assume, not that  A necessarily belongs to  some B, but that A necessarily

does not  belong to some B. But if this  is assumed, no absurdity results:  consequently no syllogism. It is  clear

from what has been said that  the negative proposition is not  convertible. 

This being proved, suppose it possible that A may belong to no B  and  to all C. By means of conversion no

syllogism will result: for the  major premiss, as has been said, is not convertible. Nor can a proof  be obtained

by a reductio ad absurdum: for if it is assumed that B can  belong to all C, no false consequence results: for A

may belong both  to all C and to no C. In general, if there is a syllogism, it is clear  that its conclusion will be

problematic because neither of the  premisses is assertoric; and this must be either affirmative or  negative. But

neither is possible. Suppose the conclusion is  affirmative: it will be proved by an example that the predicate

cannot  belong to the subject. Suppose the conclusion is negative: it will  be  proved that it is not problematic

but necessary. Let A be white,  B  man, C horse. It is possible then for A to belong to all of the  one  and to none

of the other. But it is not possible for B to belong  nor  not to belong to C. That it is not possible for it to

belong, is  clear. For no horse is a man. Neither is it possible for it not to  belong. For it is necessary that no


PRIOR ANALYTICS

17 18



Top




Page No 22


horse should be a man, but the  necessary we found to be different from the possible. No syllogism  then

results. A similar proof can be given if the major premiss is  negative, the minor affirmative, or if both are

affirmative or  negative. The demonstration can be made by means of the same terms.  And whenever one

premiss is universal, the other particular, or both  are particular or indefinite, or in whatever other way the

premisses  can be altered, the proof will always proceed through the same  terms.  Clearly then, if both the

premisses are problematic, no  syllogism  results. 

18

But if one premiss is assertoric, the other problematic, if the  affirmative is assertoric and the negative

problematic no syllogism  will be possible, whether the premisses are universal or particular.  The proof is the

same as above, and by means of the same terms. But  when the affirmative premiss is problematic, and the

negative  assertoric, we shall have a syllogism. Suppose A belongs to no B,  but  can belong to all C. If the

negative proposition is converted, B  will  belong to no A. But ex hypothesi can belong to all C: so a  syllogism

is made, proving by means of the first figure that B may  belong to no  C. Similarly also if the minor premiss is

negative. But  if both  premisses are negative, one being assertoric, the other  problematic,  nothing follows

necessarily from these premisses as  they stand, but if  the problematic premiss is converted into its

complementary  affirmative a syllogism is formed to prove that B may  belong to no C,  as before: for we shall

again have the first figure.  But if both  premisses are affirmative, no syllogism will be  possible. This

arrangement of terms is possible both when the relation  is positive,  e.g. health, animal, man, and when it is

negative, e.g.  health, horse,  man. 

The same will hold good if the syllogisms are particular. Whenever  the affirmative proposition is assertoric,

whether universal or  particular, no syllogism is possible (this is proved similarly and  by  the same examples as

above), but when the negative proposition is  assertoric, a conclusion can be drawn by means of conversion,

as  before. Again if both the relations are negative, and the assertoric  proposition is universal, although no

conclusion follows from the  actual premisses, a syllogism can be obtained by converting the  problematic

premiss into its complementary affirmative as before.  But  if the negative proposition is assertoric, but

particular, no  syllogism is possible, whether the other premiss is affirmative or  negative. Nor can a

conclusion be drawn when both premisses are  indefinite, whether affirmative or negative, or particular. The

proof  is the same and by the same terms. 

19

If one of the premisses is necessary, the other problematic, then  if  the negative is necessary a syllogistic

conclusion can be drawn,  not  merely a negative problematic but also a negative assertoric  conclusion; but if

the affirmative premiss is necessary, no conclusion  is possible. Suppose that A necessarily belongs to no B,

but may  belong to all C. If the negative premiss is converted B will belong to  no A: but A ex hypothesi is

capable of belonging to all C: so once  more a conclusion is drawn by the first figure that B may belong to no

C. But at the same time it is clear that B will not belong to any C.  For assume that it does: then if A cannot

belong to any B, and B  belongs to some of the Cs, A cannot belong to some of the Cs: but ex  hypothesi it

may belong to all. A similar proof can be given if the  minor premiss is negative. Again let the affirmative

proposition be  necessary, and the other problematic; i.e. suppose that A may belong  to no B, but necessarily

belongs to all C. When the terms are arranged  in this way, no syllogism is possible. For (1) it sometimes turns

out  that B necessarily does not belong to C. Let A be white, B man,  C  swan. White then necessarily belongs

to swan, but may belong to no  man; and man necessarily belongs to no swan; Clearly then we cannot  draw a

problematic conclusion; for that which is necessary is  admittedly distinct from that which is possible. (2) Nor

again can  we  draw a necessary conclusion: for that presupposes that both  premisses  are necessary, or at any

rate the negative premiss. (3)  Further it is  possible also, when the terms are so arranged, that B  should belong

to  C: for nothing prevents C falling under B, A being  possible for all B,  and necessarily belonging to C; e.g.


PRIOR ANALYTICS

18 19



Top




Page No 23


if C stands  for 'awake', B for  'animal', A for 'motion'. For motion necessarily  belongs to what is  awake, and is

possible for every animal: and  everything that is awake  is animal. Clearly then the conclusion cannot  be the

negative  assertion, if the relation must be positive when the  terms are related  as above. Nor can the opposite

affirmations be  established:  consequently no syllogism is possible. A similar proof is  possible if  the major

premiss is affirmative. 

But if the premisses are similar in quality, when they are  negative a syllogism can always be formed by

converting the  problematic premiss into its complementary affirmative as before.  Suppose A necessarily does

not belong to B, and possibly may not  belong to C: if the premisses are converted B belongs to no A, and A

may possibly belong to all C: thus we have the first figure. Similarly  if the minor premiss is negative. But if

the premisses are affirmative  there cannot be a syllogism. Clearly the conclusion cannot be a  negative

assertoric or a negative necessary proposition because no  negative premiss has been laid down either in the

assertoric or in the  necessary mode. Nor can the conclusion be a problematic negative  proposition. For if the

terms are so related, there are cases in which  B necessarily will not belong to C; e.g. suppose that A is white,

B  swan, C man. Nor can the opposite affirmations be established, since  we have shown a case in which B

necessarily does not belong to C. A  syllogism then is not possible at all. 

Similar relations will obtain in particular syllogisms. For  whenever  the negative proposition is universal and

necessary, a  syllogism  will always be possible to prove both a problematic and a  negative  assertoric

proposition (the proof proceeds by conversion);  but when  the affirmative proposition is universal and

necessary, no  syllogistic  conclusion can be drawn. This can be proved in the same  way as for  universal

propositions, and by the same terms. Nor is a  syllogistic  conclusion possible when both premisses are

affirmative:  this also may  be proved as above. But when both premisses are  negative, and the  premiss that

definitely disconnects two terms is  universal and  necessary, though nothing follows necessarily from the

premisses as  they are stated, a conclusion can be drawn as above if  the problematic  premiss is converted into

its complementary  affirmative. But if both  are indefinite or particular, no syllogism  can be formed. The same

proof will serve, and the same terms. 

It is clear then from what has been said that if the universal and  negative premiss is necessary, a syllogism is

always possible, proving  not merely a negative problematic, but also a negative assertoric  proposition; but if

the affirmative premiss is necessary no conclusion  can be drawn. It is clear too that a syllogism is possible or

not  under the same conditions whether the mode of the premisses is  assertoric or necessary. And it is clear

that all the syllogisms are  imperfect, and are completed by means of the figures mentioned. 

20

In the last figure a syllogism is possible whether both or only  one of the premisses is problematic. When the

premisses are  problematic the conclusion will be problematic; and also when one  premiss is problematic, the

other assertoric. But when the other  premiss is necessary, if it is affirmative the conclusion will be  neither

necessary or assertoric; but if it is negative the syllogism  will result in a negative assertoric proposition, as

above. In these  also we must understand the expression 'possible' in the conclusion in  the same way as before. 

First let the premisses be problematic and suppose that both A and  B  may possibly belong to every C. Since

then the affirmative  proposition  is convertible into a particular, and B may possibly  belong to every  C, it

follows that C may possibly belong to some B.  So, if A is  possible for every C, and C is possible for some of

the  Bs, then A  is possible for some of the Bs. For we have got the first  figure.  And A if may possibly belong

to no C, but B may possibly  belong to all  C, it follows that A may possibly not belong to some B:  for we shall

have the first figure again by conversion. But if both  premisses  should be negative no necessary consequence

will follow from  them as  they are stated, but if the premisses are converted into their  corresponding

affirmatives there will be a syllogism as before. For if  A and B may possibly not belong to C, if 'may possibly


PRIOR ANALYTICS

20 20



Top




Page No 24


belong' is  substituted we shall again have the first figure by means of  conversion. But if one of the premisses

is universal, the other  particular, a syllogism will be possible, or not, under the  arrangement of the terms as in

the case of assertoric propositions.  Suppose that A may possibly belong to all C, and B to some C. We shall

have the first figure again if the particular premiss is converted.  For if A is possible for all C, and C for some

of the Bs, then A is  possible for some of the Bs. Similarly if the proposition BC is  universal. Likewise also if

the proposition AC is negative, and the  proposition BC affirmative: for we shall again have the first figure  by

conversion. But if both premisses should be negativethe one  universal and the other particularalthough no

syllogistic  conclusion  will follow from the premisses as they are put, it will  follow if they  are converted, as

above. But when both premisses are  indefinite or  particular, no syllogism can be formed: for A must  belong

sometimes to  all B and sometimes to no B. To illustrate the  affirmative relation  take the terms

animalmanwhite; to illustrate  the negative, take the  terms horsemanwhitewhite being the middle

term. 

21

If one premiss is pure, the other problematic, the conclusion will  be problematic, not pure; and a syllogism

will be possible under the  same arrangement of the terms as before. First let the premisses be  affirmative:

suppose that A belongs to all C, and B may possibly  belong to all C. If the proposition BC is converted, we

shall have the  first figure, and the conclusion that A may possibly belong to some of  the Bs. For when one of

the premisses in the first figure is  problematic, the conclusion also (as we saw) is problematic. Similarly  if the

proposition BC is pure, AC problematic; or if AC is negative,  BC affirmative, no matter which of the two is

pure; in both cases  the  conclusion will be problematic: for the first figure is obtained  once  more, and it has

been proved that if one premiss is problematic  in  that figure the conclusion also will be problematic. But if

the  minor  premiss BC is negative, or if both premisses are negative, no  syllogistic conclusion can be drawn

from the premisses as they  stand,  but if they are converted a syllogism is obtained as before. 

If one of the premisses is universal, the other particular, then  when both are affirmative, or when the universal

is negative, the  particular affirmative, we shall have the same sort of syllogisms: for  all are completed by

means of the first figure. So it is clear that we  shall have not a pure but a problematic syllogistic conclusion.

But if  the affirmative premiss is universal, the negative particular, the  proof will proceed by a reductio ad

impossibile. Suppose that B  belongs to all C, and A may possibly not belong to some C: it  follows  that may

possibly not belong to some B. For if A necessarily  belongs  to all B, and B (as has been assumed) belongs to

all C, A will  necessarily belong to all C: for this has been proved before. But it  was assumed at the outset that

A may possibly not belong to some C. 

Whenever both premisses are indefinite or particular, no syllogism  will be possible. The demonstration is the

same as was given in the  case of universal premisses, and proceeds by means of the same terms. 

22

If one of the premisses is necessary, the other problematic, when  the premisses are affirmative a problematic

affirmative conclusion can  always be drawn; when one proposition is affirmative, the other  negative, if the

affirmative is necessary a problematic negative can  be inferred; but if the negative proposition is necessary

both a  problematic and a pure negative conclusion are possible. But a  necessary negative conclusion will not

be possible, any more than in  the other figures. Suppose first that the premisses are affirmative,  i.e. that A

necessarily belongs to all C, and B may possibly belong to  all C. Since then A must belong to all C, and C

may belong to some  B,  it follows that A may (not does) belong to some B: for so it  resulted  in the first figure.

A similar proof may be given if the  proposition  BC is necessary, and AC is problematic. Again suppose  one

proposition  is affirmative, the other negative, the affirmative  being necessary:  i.e. suppose A may possibly

belong to no C, but B  necessarily belongs  to all C. We shall have the first figure once  more: andsince the


PRIOR ANALYTICS

21 21



Top




Page No 25


negative premiss is problematicit is clear that  the conclusion will  be problematic: for when the premisses

stand  thus in the first figure,  the conclusion (as we found) is problematic.  But if the negative  premiss is

necessary, the conclusion will be not  only that A may  possibly not belong to some B but also that it does  not

belong to some  B. For suppose that A necessarily does not belong  to C, but B may  belong to all C. If the

affirmative proposition BC  is converted, we  shall have the first figure, and the negative premiss  is necessary.

But when the premisses stood thus, it resulted that A  might possibly  not belong to some C, and that it did not

belong to  some C;  consequently here it follows that A does not belong to some B.  But  when the minor

premiss is negative, if it is problematic we  shall have  a syllogism by altering the premiss into its

complementary  affirmative, as before; but if it is necessary no  syllogism can be  formed. For A sometimes

necessarily belongs to all B,  and sometimes  cannot possibly belong to any B. To illustrate the  former take the

terms sleepsleeping horseman; to illustrate the  latter take the  terms sleepwaking horseman. 

Similar results will obtain if one of the terms is related  universally to the middle, the other in part. If both

premisses are  affirmative, the conclusion will be problematic, not pure; and also  when one premiss is

negative, the other affirmative, the latter  being  necessary. But when the negative premiss is necessary, the

conclusion  also will be a pure negative proposition; for the same kind  of proof  can be given whether the

terms are universal or not. For  the  syllogisms must be made perfect by means of the first figure, so  that  a

result which follows in the first figure follows also in the  third.  But when the minor premiss is negative and

universal, if it  is  problematic a syllogism can be formed by means of conversion; but  if  it is necessary a

syllogism is not possible. The proof will  follow the  same course as where the premisses are universal; and the

same terms  may be used. 

It is clear then in this figure also when and how a syllogism can  be  formed, and when the conclusion is

problematic, and when it is  pure.  It is evident also that all syllogisms in this figure are  imperfect,  and that

they are made perfect by means of the first  figure. 

23

It is clear from what has been said that the syllogisms in these  figures are made perfect by means of universal

syllogisms in the first  figure and are reduced to them. That every syllogism without  qualification can be so

treated, will be clear presently, when it  has  been proved that every syllogism is formed through one or other

of  these figures. 

It is necessary that every demonstration and every syllogism  should prove either that something belongs or

that it does not, and  this either universally or in part, and further either ostensively  or  hypothetically. One sort

of hypothetical proof is the reductio ad  impossibile. Let us speak first of ostensive syllogisms: for after  these

have been pointed out the truth of our contention will be  clear  with regard to those which are proved per

impossibile, and in  general  hypothetically. 

If then one wants to prove syllogistically A of B, either as an  attribute of it or as not an attribute of it, one

must assert  something of something else. If now A should be asserted of B, the  proposition originally in

question will have been assumed. But if A  should be asserted of C, but C should not be asserted of anything,

nor  anything of it, nor anything else of A, no syllogism will be possible.  For nothing necessarily follows from

the assertion of some one thing  concerning some other single thing. Thus we must take another  premiss  as

well. If then A be asserted of something else, or something  else of  A, or something different of C, nothing

prevents a syllogism  being  formed, but it will not be in relation to B through the  premisses  taken. Nor when

C belongs to something else, and that to  something  else and so on, no connexion however being made with B,

will  a  syllogism be possible concerning A in its relation to B. For in  general we stated that no syllogism can

establish the attribution of  one thing to another, unless some middle term is taken, which is  somehow related

to each by way of predication. For the syllogism in  general is made out of premisses, and a syllogism


PRIOR ANALYTICS

23 22



Top




Page No 26


referring to this  out of premisses with the same reference, and a syllogism relating  this to that proceeds

through premisses which relate this to that. But  it is impossible to take a premiss in reference to B, if we

neither  affirm nor deny anything of it; or again to take a premiss relating  A  to B, if we take nothing common,

but affirm or deny peculiar  attributes of each. So we must take something midway between the  two,  which

will connect the predications, if we are to have a  syllogism  relating this to that. If then we must take

something common  in  relation to both, and this is possible in three ways (either by  predicating A of C, and C

of B, or C of both, or both of C), and these  are the figures of which we have spoken, it is clear that every

syllogism must be made in one or other of these figures. The  argument  is the same if several middle terms

should be necessary to  establish  the relation to B; for the figure will be the same whether  there is  one middle

term or many. 

It is clear then that the ostensive syllogisms are effected by  means  of the aforesaid figures; these

considerations will show that  reductiones ad also are effected in the same way. For all who effect  an

argument per impossibile infer syllogistically what is false, and  prove the original conclusion hypothetically

when something impossible  results from the assumption of its contradictory; e.g. that the  diagonal of the

square is incommensurate with the side, because odd  numbers are equal to evens if it is supposed to be

commensurate. One  infers syllogistically that odd numbers come out equal to evens, and  one proves

hypothetically the incommensurability of the diagonal,  since a falsehood results through contradicting this.

For this we  found to be reasoning per impossibile, viz. proving something  impossible by means of an

hypothesis conceded at the beginning.  Consequently, since the falsehood is established in reductions ad

impossibile by an ostensive syllogism, and the original conclusion  is  proved hypothetically, and we have

already stated that ostensive  syllogisms are effected by means of these figures, it is evident  that  syllogisms

per impossibile also will be made through these  figures.  Likewise all the other hypothetical syllogisms: for in

every case the  syllogism leads up to the proposition that is  substituted for the  original thesis; but the original

thesis is  reached by means of a  concession or some other hypothesis. But if this  is true, every  demonstration

and every syllogism must be formed by  means of the three  figures mentioned above. But when this has been

shown it is clear that  every syllogism is perfected by means of the  first figure and is  reducible to the universal

syllogisms in this  figure. 

24

Further in every syllogism one of the premisses must be  affirmative,  and universality must be present: unless

one of the  premisses is  universal either a syllogism will not be possible, or it  will not  refer to the subject

proposed, or the original position will  be  begged. Suppose we have to prove that pleasure in music is good. If

one should claim as a premiss that pleasure is good without adding  'all', no syllogism will be possible; if one

should claim that some  pleasure is good, then if it is different from pleasure in music, it  is not relevant to the

subject proposed; if it is this very  pleasure,  one is assuming that which was proposed at the outset to  be

proved.  This is more obvious in geometrical proofs, e.g. that the  angles at  the base of an isosceles triangle are

equal. Suppose the  lines A and B  have been drawn to the centre. If then one should assume  that the  angle AC

is equal to the angle BD, without claiming generally  that  angles of semicircles are equal; and again if one

should assume  that  the angle C is equal to the angle D, without the additional  assumption  that every angle of

a segment is equal to every other angle  of the  same segment; and further if one should assume that when

equal angles  are taken from the whole angles, which are themselves  equal, the  remainders E and F are equal,

he will beg the thing to be  proved,  unless he also states that when equals are taken from equals  the  remainders

are equal. 

It is clear then that in every syllogism there must be a universal  premiss, and that a universal statement is

proved only when all the  premisses are universal, while a particular statement is proved both  from two

universal premisses and from one only: consequently if the  conclusion is universal, the premisses also must

be universal, but  if  the premisses are universal it is possible that the conclusion  may not  be universal. And it


PRIOR ANALYTICS

24 23



Top




Page No 27


is clear also that in every syllogism  either both  or one of the premisses must be like the conclusion. I  mean

not only  in being affirmative or negative, but also in being  necessary, pure,  problematic. We must consider

also the other forms of  predication. 

It is clear also when a syllogism in general can be made and when  it  cannot; and when a valid, when a perfect

syllogism can be formed;  and that if a syllogism is formed the terms must be arranged in one of  the ways that

have been mentioned. 

25

It is clear too that every demonstration will proceed through  three terms and no more, unless the same

conclusion is established  by  different pairs of propositions; e.g. the conclusion E may be  established through

the propositions A and B, and through the  propositions C and D, or through the propositions A and B, or A

and C,  or B and C. For nothing prevents there being several middles for the  same terms. But in that case there

is not one but several  syllogisms.  Or again when each of the propositions A and B is obtained  by  syllogistic

inference, e.g. by means of D and E, and again B by  means  of F and G. Or one may be obtained by

syllogistic, the other  by  inductive inference. But thus also the syllogisms are many; for the  conclusions are

many, e.g. A and B and C. But if this can be called  one syllogism, not many, the same conclusion may be

reached by more  than three terms in this way, but it cannot be reached as C is  established by means of A and

B. Suppose that the proposition E is  inferred from the premisses A, B, C, and D. It is necessary then  that  of

these one should be related to another as whole to part: for  it has  already been proved that if a syllogism is

formed some of its  terms  must be related in this way. Suppose then that A stands in  this  relation to B. Some

conclusion then follows from them. It must  either  be E or one or other of C and D, or something other than

these. 

(1) If it is E the syllogism will have A and B for its sole  premisses. But if C and D are so related that one is

whole, the  other  part, some conclusion will follow from them also; and it must be  either E, or one or other of

the propositions A and B, or something  other than these. And if it is (i) E, or (ii) A or B, either (i) the

syllogisms will be more than one, or (ii) the same thing happens to be  inferred by means of several terms only

in the sense which we saw to  be possible. But if (iii) the conclusion is other than E or A or B,  the syllogisms

will be many, and unconnected with one another. But  if  C is not so related to D as to make a syllogism, the

propositions  will  have been assumed to no purpose, unless for the sake of induction  or  of obscuring the

argument or something of the sort. 

(2) But if from the propositions A and B there follows not E but  some other conclusion, and if from C and D

either A or B follows or  something else, then there are several syllogisms, and they do not  establish the

conclusion proposed: for we assumed that the syllogism  proved E. And if no conclusion follows from C and

D, it turns out that  these propositions have been assumed to no purpose, and the  syllogism  does not prove the

original proposition. 

So it is clear that every demonstration and every syllogism will  proceed through three terms only. 

This being evident, it is clear that a syllogistic conclusion  follows from two premisses and not from more

than two. For the three  terms make two premisses, unless a new premiss is assumed, as was said  at the

beginning, to perfect the syllogisms. It is clear therefore  that in whatever syllogistic argument the premisses

through which  the  main conclusion follows (for some of the preceding conclusions  must be  premisses) are

not even in number, this argument either has  not been  drawn syllogistically or it has assumed more than was

necessary to  establish its thesis. 

If then syllogisms are taken with respect to their main premisses,  every syllogism will consist of an even


PRIOR ANALYTICS

25 24



Top




Page No 28


number of premisses and an odd  number of terms (for the terms exceed the premisses by one), and the

conclusions will be half the number of the premisses. But whenever a  conclusion is reached by means of

prosyllogisms or by means of several  continuous middle terms, e.g. the proposition AB by means of the

middle terms C and D, the number of the terms will similarly exceed  that of the premisses by one (for the

extra term must either be  added  outside or inserted: but in either case it follows that the  relations  of

predication are one fewer than the terms related), and  the  premisses will be equal in number to the relations

of predication.  The  premisses however will not always be even, the terms odd; but they  will alternatewhen

the premisses are even, the terms must be odd;  when the terms are even, the premisses must be odd: for along

with one  term one premiss is added, if a term is added from any quarter.  Consequently since the premisses

were (as we saw) even, and the  terms  odd, we must make them alternately even and odd at each  addition. But

the conclusions will not follow the same arrangement  either in respect  to the terms or to the premisses. For if

one term is  added,  conclusions will be added less by one than the preexisting  terms: for  the conclusion is

drawn not in relation to the single  term last added,  but in relation to all the rest, e.g. if to ABC the  term D is

added,  two conclusions are thereby added, one in relation to  A, the other in  relation to B. Similarly with any

further additions.  And similarly too  if the term is inserted in the middle: for in  relation to one term  only, a

syllogism will not be constructed.  Consequently the  conclusions will be much more numerous than the terms

or the  premisses. 

26

Since we understand the subjects with which syllogisms are  concerned, what sort of conclusion is established

in each figure,  and  in how many moods this is done, it is evident to us both what sort  of  problem is difficult

and what sort is easy to prove. For that which  is  concluded in many figures and through many moods is

easier; that  which  is concluded in few figures and through few moods is more  difficult to  attempt. The

universal affirmative is proved by means  of the first  figure only and by this in only one mood; the universal

negative is  proved both through the first figure and through the  second, through  the first in one mood,

through the second in two.  The particular  affirmative is proved through the first and through the  last figure,  in

one mood through the first, in three moods through the  last. The  particular negative is proved in all the

figures, but once  in the  first, in two moods in the second, in three moods in the third.  It is  clear then that the

universal affirmative is most difficult to  establish, most easy to overthrow. In general, universals are easier

game for the destroyer than particulars: for whether the predicate  belongs to none or not to some, they are

destroyed: and the particular  negative is proved in all the figures, the universal negative in  two.  Similarly

with universal negatives: the original statement is  destroyed, whether the predicate belongs to all or to some:

and this  we found possible in two figures. But particular statements can be  refuted in one way onlyby

proving that the predicate belongs either  to all or to none. But particular statements are easier to  establish:  for

proof is possible in more figures and through more  moods. And in  general we must not forget that it is

possible to refute  statements by  means of one another, I mean, universal statements by  means of  particular,

and particular statements by means of  universal: but it is  not possible to establish universal statements by

means of particular,  though it is possible to establish particular  statements by means of  universal. At the same

time it is evident  that it is easier to refute  than to establish. 

The manner in which every syllogism is produced, the number of the  terms and premisses through which it

proceeds, the relation of the  premisses to one another, the character of the problem proved in  each  figure, and

the number of the figures appropriate to each  problem, all  these matters are clear from what has been said. 

27

We must now state how we may ourselves always have a supply of  syllogisms in reference to the problem

proposed and by what road we  may reach the principles relative to the problem: for perhaps we ought  not

only to investigate the construction of syllogisms, but also to  have the power of making them. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

26 25



Top




Page No 29


Of all the things which exist some are such that they cannot be  predicated of anything else truly and

universally, e.g. Cleon and  Callias, i.e. the individual and sensible, but other things may be  predicated of

them (for each of these is both man and animal); and  some things are themselves predicated of others, but

nothing prior  is  predicated of them; and some are predicated of others, and yet  others  of them, e.g. man of

Callias and animal of man. It is clear  then that  some things are naturally not stated of anything: for as a  rule

each  sensible thing is such that it cannot be predicated of  anything, save  incidentally: for we sometimes say

that that white  object is Socrates,  or that that which approaches is Callias. We shall  explain in another  place

that there is an upward limit also to the  process of  predicating: for the present we must assume this. Of  these

ultimate  predicates it is not possible to demonstrate another  predicate, save  as a matter of opinion, but these

may be predicated of  other things.  Neither can individuals be predicated of other things,  though other  things

can be predicated of them. Whatever lies between  these limits  can be spoken of in both ways: they may be

stated of  others, and  others stated of them. And as a rule arguments and  inquiries are  concerned with these

things. We must select the  premisses suitable to  each problem in this manner: first we must lay  down the

subject and  the definitions and the properties of the  thing; next we must lay down  those attributes which

follow the  thing, and again those which the  thing follows, and those which cannot  belong to it. But those to

which  it cannot belong need not be  selected, because the negative statement  implied above is convertible.  Of

the attributes which follow we must  distinguish those which fall  within the definition, those which are

predicated as properties, and  those which are predicated as accidents,  and of the latter those which  apparently

and those which really  belong. The larger the supply a  man has of these, the more quickly  will he reach a

conclusion; and  in proportion as he apprehends those  which are truer, the more  cogently will he demonstrate.

But he must  select not those which  follow some particular but those which follow  the thing as a whole,  e.g.

not what follows a particular man but what  follows every man: for  the syllogism proceeds through universal

premisses. If the statement  is indefinite, it is uncertain whether the  premiss is universal, but  if the statement is

definite, the matter is  clear. Similarly one  must select those attributes which the subject  follows as wholes,  for

the reason given. But that which follows one  must not suppose to  follow as a whole, e.g. that every animal

follows  man or every science  music, but only that it follows, without  qualification, and indeed  we state it in a

proposition: for the other  statement is useless and  impossible, e.g. that every man is every  animal or justice is

all  good. But that which something follows  receives the mark 'every'.  Whenever the subject, for which we

must  obtain the attributes that  follow, is contained by something else,  what follows or does not  follow the

highest term universally must not  be selected in dealing  with the subordinate term (for these attributes  have

been taken in  dealing with the superior term; for what follows  animal also follows  man, and what does not

belong to animal does not  belong to man); but  we must choose those attributes which are peculiar  to each

subject.  For some things are peculiar to the species as  distinct from the  genus; for species being distinct there

must be  attributes peculiar to  each. Nor must we take as things which the  superior term follows,  those things

which the inferior term follows,  e.g. take as subjects of  the predicate 'animal' what are really  subjects of the

predicate  'man'. It is necessary indeed, if animal  follows man, that it should  follow all these also. But these

belong  more properly to the choice of  what concerns man. One must apprehend  also normal consequents and

normal antecedents, for propositions  which obtain normally are  established syllogistically from premisses

which obtain normally, some  if not all of them having this character  of normality. For the  conclusion of each

syllogism resembles its  principles. We must not  however choose attributes which are consequent  upon all the

terms: for  no syllogism can be made out of such  premisses. The reason why this is  so will be clear in the

sequel. 

28

If men wish to establish something about some whole, they must  look to the subjects of that which is being

established (the  subjects  of which it happens to be asserted), and the attributes which  follow  that of which it

is to be predicated. For if any of these  subjects is  the same as any of these attributes, the attribute  originally in

question must belong to the subject originally in  question. But if the  purpose is to establish not a universal but

a  particular proposition,  they must look for the terms of which the  terms in question are  predicable: for if any


PRIOR ANALYTICS

28 26



Top




Page No 30


of these are identical,  the attribute in  question must belong to some of the subject in  question. Whenever the

one term has to belong to none of the other,  one must look to the  consequents of the subject, and to those

attributes which cannot  possibly be present in the predicate in  question: or conversely to the  attributes which

cannot possibly be  present in the subject, and to the  consequents of the predicate. If  any members of these

groups are  identical, one of the terms in  question cannot possibly belong to any  of the other. For sometimes a

syllogism in the first figure results,  sometimes a syllogism in the  second. But if the object is to establish  a

particular negative  proposition, we must find antecedents of the  subject in question and  attributes which

cannot possibly belong to the  predicate in  question. If any members of these two groups are  identical, it

follows  that one of the terms in question does not  belong to some of the  other. Perhaps each of these

statements will  become clearer in the  following way. Suppose the consequents of A are  designated by B, the

antecedents of A by C, attributes which cannot  possibly belong to A by  D. Suppose again that the attributes

of E are  designated by F, the  antecedents of E by G, and attributes which  cannot belong to E by H.  If then one

of the Cs should be identical  with one of the Fs, A must  belong to all E: for F belongs to all E,  and A to all C,

consequently A belongs to all E. If C and G are  identical, A must  belong to some of the Es: for A follows C,

and E  follows all G. If F  and D are identical, A will belong to none of the  Es by a  prosyllogism: for since the

negative proposition is  convertible, and F  is identical with D, A will belong to none of the  Fs, but F belongs

to  all E. Again, if B and H are identical, A will  belong to none of the  Es: for B will belong to all A, but to no

E: for  it was assumed to  be identical with H, and H belonged to none of the  Es. If D and G  are identical, A

will not belong to some of the Es: for  it will not  belong to G, because it does not belong to D: but G falls

under E:  consequently A will not belong to some of the Es. If B is  identical  with G, there will be a converted

syllogism: for E will  belong to  all A since B belongs to A and E to B (for B was found to be  identical  with

G): but that A should belong to all E is not necessary,  but it  must belong to some E because it is possible to

convert the  universal statement into a particular. 

It is clear then that in every proposition which requires proof we  must look to the aforesaid relations of the

subject and predicate in  question: for all syllogisms proceed through these. But if we are  seeking consequents

and antecedents we must look for those which are  primary and most universal, e.g. in reference to E we must

look to  KF  rather than to F alone, and in reference to A we must look to KC  rather than to C alone. For if A

belongs to KF, it belongs both to F  and to E: but if it does not follow KF, it may yet follow F. Similarly  we

must consider the antecedents of A itself: for if a term follows  the primary antecedents, it will follow those

also which are  subordinate, but if it does not follow the former, it may yet follow  the latter. 

It is clear too that the inquiry proceeds through the three terms  and the two premisses, and that all the

syllogisms proceed through the  aforesaid figures. For it is proved that A belongs to all E,  whenever  an

identical term is found among the Cs and Fs. This will  be the  middle term; A and E will be the extremes. So

the first  figure is  formed. And A will belong to some E, whenever C and G are  apprehended  to be the same.

This is the last figure: for G becomes the  middle  term. And A will belong to no E, when D and F are

identical.  Thus we  have both the first figure and the middle figure; the first,  because A  belongs to no F, since

the negative statement is  convertible, and F  belongs to all E: the middle figure because D  belongs to no A,

and to  all E. And A will not belong to some E,  whenever D and G are  identical. This is the last figure: for A

will  belong to no G, and E  will belong to all G. Clearly then all  syllogisms proceed through the  aforesaid

figures, and we must not  select consequents of all the  terms, because no syllogism is  produced from them.

For (as we saw) it  is not possible at all to  establish a proposition from consequents,  and it is not possible to

refute by means of a consequent of both the  terms in question: for the  middle term must belong to the one,

and not  belong to the other. 

It is clear too that other methods of inquiry by selection of  middle  terms are useless to produce a syllogism,

e.g. if the  consequents of  the terms in question are identical, or if the  antecedents of A are  identical with those

attributes which cannot  possibly belong to E,  or if those attributes are identical which  cannot belong to either

term: for no syllogism is produced by means of  these. For if the  consequents are identical, e.g. B and F, we

have the  middle figure  with both premisses affirmative: if the antecedents of A  are identical  with attributes


PRIOR ANALYTICS

28 27



Top




Page No 31


which cannot belong to E, e.g. C with H,  we have the  first figure with its minor premiss negative. If  attributes

which  cannot belong to either term are identical, e.g. C  and H, both  premisses are negative, either in the first

or in the  middle figure.  But no syllogism is possible in this way. 

It is evident too that we must find out which terms in this  inquiry are identical, not which are different or

contrary, first  because the object of our investigation is the middle term, and the  middle term must be not

diverse but identical. Secondly, wherever it  happens that a syllogism results from taking contraries or terms

which  cannot belong to the same thing, all arguments can be reduced to the  aforesaid moods, e.g. if B and F

are contraries or cannot belong to  the same thing. For if these are taken, a syllogism will be formed  to  prove

that A belongs to none of the Es, not however from the  premisses  taken but in the aforesaid mood. For B will

belong to all  A and to no  E. Consequently B must be identical with one of the Hs.  Again, if B  and G cannot

belong to the same thing, it follows that A  will not  belong to some of the Es: for then too we shall have the

middle  figure: for B will belong to all A and to no G. Consequently  B must be  identical with some of the Hs.

For the fact that B and G  cannot belong  to the same thing differs in no way from the fact that B  is identical

with some of the Hs: for that includes everything which  cannot belong  to E. 

It is clear then that from the inquiries taken by themselves no  syllogism results; but if B and F are contraries

B must be identical  with one of the Hs, and the syllogism results through these terms.  It  turns out then that

those who inquire in this manner are looking  gratuitously for some other way than the necessary way because

they  have failed to observe the identity of the Bs with the Hs. 

29

Syllogisms which lead to impossible conclusions are similar to  ostensive syllogisms; they also are formed by

means of the consequents  and antecedents of the terms in question. In both cases the same  inquiry is

involved. For what is proved ostensively may also be  concluded syllogistically per impossibile by means of

the same  terms;  and what is proved per impossibile may also be proved  ostensively,  e.g. that A belongs to

none of the Es. For suppose A to  belong to some  E: then since B belongs to all A and A to some of the  Es, B

will  belong to some of the Es: but it was assumed that it  belongs to none.  Again we may prove that A belongs

to some E: for if A  belonged to none  of the Es, and E belongs to all G, A will belong to  none of the Gs:  but it

was assumed to belong to all. Similarly with  the other  propositions requiring proof. The proof per impossibile

will  always  and in all cases be from the consequents and antecedents of the  terms  in question. Whatever the

problem the same inquiry is  necessary  whether one wishes to use an ostensive syllogism or a  reduction to

impossibility. For both the demonstrations start from the  same terms,  e.g. suppose it has been proved that A

belongs to no E,  because it  turns out that otherwise B belongs to some of the Es and  this is  impossibleif now

it is assumed that B belongs to no E and  to all A,  it is clear that A will belong to no E. Again if it has been

proved by  an ostensive syllogism that A belongs to no E, assume that A  belongs  to some E and it will be

proved per impossibile to belong to  no E.  Similarly with the rest. In all cases it is necessary to find  some

common term other than the subjects of inquiry, to which the  syllogism  establishing the false conclusion may

relate, so that if  this premiss  is converted, and the other remains as it is, the  syllogism will be  ostensive by

means of the same terms. For the  ostensive syllogism  differs from the reductio ad impossibile in  this: in the

ostensive  syllogism both remisses are laid down in  accordance with the truth, in  the reductio ad impossibile

one of the  premisses is assumed falsely. 

These points will be made clearer by the sequel, when we discuss  the  reduction to impossibility: at present

this much must be clear,  that  we must look to terms of the kinds mentioned whether we wish to  use an

ostensive syllogism or a reduction to impossibility. In the  other  hypothetical syllogisms, I mean those which

proceed by  substitution,  or by positing a certain quality, the inquiry will be  directed to  the terms of the

problem to be provednot the terms of the  original  problem, but the new terms introduced; and the method of

the  inquiry  will be the same as before. But we must consider and determine  in  how many ways hypothetical


PRIOR ANALYTICS

29 28



Top




Page No 32


syllogisms are possible. 

Each of the problems then can be proved in the manner described;  but  it is possible to establish some of them

syllogistically in  another  way, e.g. universal problems by the inquiry which leads up to  a  particular

conclusion, with the addition of an hypothesis. For if  the Cs and the Gs should be identical, but E should be

assumed to  belong to the Gs only, then A would belong to every E: and again if  the Ds and the Gs should be

identical, but E should be predicated of  the Gs only, it follows that A will belong to none of the Es.  Clearly

then we must consider the matter in this way also. The  method is the  same whether the relation is necessary

or possible.  For the inquiry  will be the same, and the syllogism will proceed  through terms  arranged in the

same order whether a possible or a  pure proposition is  proved. We must find in the case of possible  relations,

as well as  terms that belong, terms which can belong though  they actually do not:  for we have proved that the

syllogism which  establishes a possible  relation proceeds through these terms as  well. Similarly also with the

other modes of predication. 

It is clear then from what has been said not only that all  syllogisms can be formed in this way, but also that

they cannot be  formed in any other. For every syllogism has been proved to be  formed  through one of the

aforementioned figures, and these cannot  be  composed through other terms than the consequents and

antecedents  of  the terms in question: for from these we obtain the premisses and  find  the middle term.

Consequently a syllogism cannot be formed by  means of  other terms. 

30

The method is the same in all cases, in philosophy, in any art or  study. We must look for the attributes and

the subjects of both our  terms, and we must supply ourselves with as many of these as possible,  and consider

them by means of the three terms, refuting statements  in  one way, confirming them in another, in the pursuit

of truth  starting  from premisses in which the arrangement of the terms is in  accordance  with truth, while if we

look for dialectical syllogisms  we must start  from probable premisses. The principles of syllogisms  have been

stated  in general terms, both how they are characterized and  how we must hunt  for them, so as not to look to

everything that is  said about the terms  of the problem or to the same points whether we  are confirming or

refuting, or again whether we are confirming of  all or of some, and  whether we are refuting of all or some. we

must  look to fewer points  and they must be definite. We have also stated  how we must select with  reference

to everything that is, e.g. about  good or knowledge. But in  each science the principles which are  peculiar are

the most numerous.  Consequently it is the business of  experience to give the principles  which belong to each

subject. I mean  for example that astronomical  experience supplies the principles of  astronomical science: for

once  the phenomena were adequately  apprehended, the demonstrations of  astronomy were discovered.

Similarly with any other art or science.  Consequently, if the  attributes of the thing are apprehended, our

business will then be  to exhibit readily the demonstrations. For if  none of the true  attributes of things had

been omitted in the  historical survey, we  should be able to discover the proof and  demonstrate everything

which admitted of proof, and to make that  clear, whose nature does not  admit of proof. 

In general then we have explained fairly well how we must select  premisses: we have discussed the matter

accurately in the treatise  concerning dialectic. 

31

It is easy to see that division into classes is a small part of  the method we have described: for division is, so to

speak, a weak  syllogism; for what it ought to prove, it begs, and it always  establishes something more general

than the attribute in question.  First, this very point had escaped all those who used the method of  division;

and they attempted to persuade men that it was possible to  make a demonstration of substance and essence.

Consequently they did  not understand what it is possible to prove syllogistically by  division, nor did they


PRIOR ANALYTICS

30 29



Top




Page No 33


understand that it was possible to prove  syllogistically in the manner we have described. In demonstrations,

when there is a need to prove a positive statement, the middle term  through which the syllogism is formed

must always be inferior to and  not comprehend the first of the extremes. But division has a  contrary  intention:

for it takes the universal as middle. Let animal  be the  term signified by A, mortal by B, and immortal by C,

and let  man,  whose definition is to be got, be signified by D. The man who  divides  assumes that every animal

is either mortal or immortal: i.e.  whatever  is A is all either B or C. Again, always dividing, he lays it  down

that man is an animal, so he assumes A of D as belonging to it.  Now  the true conclusion is that every D is

either B or C, consequently  man  must be either mortal or immortal, but it is not necessary that  man  should be

a mortal animalthis is begged: and this is what ought  to  have been proved syllogistically. And again, taking

A as mortal  animal, B as footed, C as footless, and D as man, he assumes in the  same way that A inheres

either in B or in C (for every mortal animal  is either footed or footless), and he assumes A of D (for he

assumed  man, as we saw, to be a mortal animal); consequently it is necessary  that man should be either a

footed or a footless animal; but it is not  necessary that man should be footed: this he assumes: and it is just

this again which he ought to have demonstrated. Always dividing then  in this way it turns out that these

logicians assume as middle the  universal term, and as extremes that which ought to have been the  subject of

demonstration and the differentiae. In conclusion, they  do  not make it clear, and show it to be necessary, that

this is man or  whatever the subject of inquiry may be: for they pursue the other  method altogether, never even

suspecting the presence of the rich  supply of evidence which might be used. It is clear that it is neither

possible to refute a statement by this method of division, nor to draw  a conclusion about an accident or

property of a thing, nor about its  genus, nor in cases in which it is unknown whether it is thus or thus,  e.g.

whether the diagonal is incommensurate. For if he assumes that  every length is either commensurate or

incommensurate, and the  diagonal is a length, he has proved that the diagonal is either  incommensurate or

commensurate. But if he should assume that it is  incommensurate, he will have assumed what he ought to

have proved.  He  cannot then prove it: for this is his method, but proof is not  possible by this method. Let A

stand for 'incommensurate or  commensurate', B for 'length', C for 'diagonal'. It is clear then that  this method

of investigation is not suitable for every inquiry, nor is  it useful in those cases in which it is thought to be

most suitable. 

From what has been said it is clear from what elements  demonstrations are formed and in what manner, and

to what points we  must look in each problem. 

32

Our next business is to state how we can reduce syllogisms to the  aforementioned figures: for this part of the

inquiry still remains. If  we should investigate the production of the syllogisms and had the  power of

discovering them, and further if we could resolve the  syllogisms produced into the aforementioned figures,

our original  problem would be brought to a conclusion. It will happen at the same  time that what has been

already said will be confirmed and its truth  made clearer by what we are about to say. For everything that is

true  must in every respect agree with itself First then we must  attempt to  select the two premisses of the

syllogism (for it is easier  to divide  into large parts than into small, and the composite parts  are larger  than the

elements out of which they are made); next we must  inquire  which are universal and which particular, and if

both  premisses have  not been stated, we must ourselves assume the one which  is missing.  For sometimes men

put forward the universal premiss, but  do not posit  the premiss which is contained in it, either in writing  or in

discussion: or men put forward the premisses of the principal  syllogism, but omit those through which they

are inferred, and  invite  the concession of others to no purpose. We must inquire then  whether  anything

unnecessary has been assumed, or anything necessary  has been  omitted, and we must posit the one and take

away the other,  until we  have reached the two premisses: for unless we have these,  we cannot  reduce

arguments put forward in the way described. In some  arguments  it is easy to see what is wanting, but some

escape us, and  appear to  be syllogisms, because something necessary results from what  has been  laid down,

e.g. if the assumptions were made that substance  is not  annihilated by the annihilation of what is not


PRIOR ANALYTICS

32 30



Top




Page No 34


substance, and  that if  the elements out of which a thing is made are annihilated,  then that  which is made out

of them is destroyed: these propositions  being laid  down, it is necessary that any part of substance is

substance; this  has not however been drawn by syllogism from the  propositions assumed,  but premisses are

wanting. Again if it is  necessary that animal should  exist, if man does, and that substance  should exist, if

animal does,  it is necessary that substance should  exist if man does: but as yet  the conclusion has not been

drawn  syllogistically: for the premisses  are not in the shape we required.  We are deceived in such cases

because something necessary results from  what is assumed, since the  syllogism also is necessary. But that

which  is necessary is wider than  the syllogism: for every syllogism is  necessary, but not everything  which is

necessary is a syllogism.  Consequently, though something  results when certain propositions are  assumed, we

must not try to  reduce it directly, but must first state  the two premisses, then  divide them into their terms. We

must take  that term as middle which  is stated in both the remisses: for it is  necessary that the middle  should

be found in both premisses in all the  figures. 

If then the middle term is a predicate and a subject of  predication,  or if it is a predicate, and something else is

denied of  it, we  shall have the first figure: if it both is a predicate and is  denied  of something, the middle

figure: if other things are predicated  of it,  or one is denied, the other predicated, the last figure. For it  was  thus

that we found the middle term placed in each figure. It is  placed  similarly too if the premisses are not

universal: for the  middle  term is determined in the same way. Clearly then, if the same  term  is not stated

more than once in the course of an argument, a  syllogism  cannot be made: for a middle term has not been

taken. Since  we know  what sort of thesis is established in each figure, and in  which the  universal, in what sort

the particular is described, clearly  we must  not look for all the figures, but for that which is  appropriate to the

thesis in hand. If the thesis is established in  more figures than one,  we shall recognize the figure by the

position  of the middle term. 

33

Men are frequently deceived about syllogisms because the inference  is necessary, as has been said above;

sometimes they are deceived by  the similarity in the positing of the terms; and this ought not to  escape our

notice. E.g. if A is stated of B, and B of C: it would seem  that a syllogism is possible since the terms stand

thus: but nothing  necessary results, nor does a syllogism. Let A represent the term  'being eternal', B

'Aristomenes as an object of thought', C  'Aristomenes'. It is true then that A belongs to B. For Aristomenes as

an object of thought is eternal. But B also belongs to C: for  Aristomenes is Aristomenes as an object of

thought. But A does not  belong to C: for Aristomenes is perishable. For no syllogism was  made  although the

terms stood thus: that required that the premiss  AB  should be stated universally. But this is false, that every

Aristomenes who is an object of thought is eternal, since  Aristomenes  is perishable. Again let C stand for

'Miccalus', B for  'musical  Miccalus', A for 'perishing tomorrow'. It is true to  predicate B of  C: for Miccalus

is musical Miccalus. Also A can be  predicated of B:  for musical Miccalus might perish tomorrow. But to

state A of C is  false at any rate. This argument then is identical  with the former;  for it is not true universally

that musical  Miccalus perishes  tomorrow: but unless this is assumed, no  syllogism (as we have shown)  is

possible. 

This deception then arises through ignoring a small distinction.  For  if we accept the conclusion as though it

made no difference  whether we  said 'This belong to that' or 'This belongs to all of  that'. 

34

Men will frequently fall into fallacies through not setting out  the terms of the premiss well, e.g. suppose A to

be health, B disease,  C man. It is true to say that A cannot belong to any B (for health  belongs to no disease)

and again that B belongs to every C (for  every  man is capable of disease). It would seem to follow that  health

cannot  belong to any man. The reason for this is that the terms  are not set  out well in the statement, since if


PRIOR ANALYTICS

33 31



Top




Page No 35


the things which are  in the  conditions are substituted, no syllogism can be made, e.g. if  'healthy' is substituted

for 'health' and 'diseased' for 'disease'.  For it is not true to say that being healthy cannot belong to one  who  is

diseased. But unless this is assumed no conclusion results,  save in  respect of possibility: but such a

conclusion is not  impossible: for  it is possible that health should belong to no man.  Again the fallacy  may

occur in a similar way in the middle figure: 'it  is not possible  that health should belong to any disease, but it is

possible that  health should belong to every man, consequently it is  not possible  that disease should belong to

any man'. In the third  figure the  fallacy results in reference to possibility. For health and  diseae and

knowledge and ignorance, and in general contraries, may  possibly  belong to the same thing, but cannot

belong to one another.  This is  not in agreement with what was said before: for we stated that  when  several

things could belong to the same thing, they could  belong to  one another. 

It is evident then that in all these cases the fallacy arises from  the setting out of the terms: for if the things that

are in the  conditions are substituted, no fallacy arises. It is clear then that  in such premisses what possesses

the condition ought always to be  substituted for the condition and taken as the term. 

35

We must not always seek to set out the terms a single word: for we  shall often have complexes of words to

which a single name is not  given. Hence it is difficult to reduce syllogisms with such terms.  Sometimes too

fallacies will result from such a search, e.g. the  belief that syllogism can establish that which has no mean.

Let A  stand for two right angles, B for triangle, C for isosceles  triangle.  A then belongs to C because of B:

but A belongs to B without  the  mediation of another term: for the triangle in virtue of its own  nature contains

two right angles, consequently there will be no middle  term for the proposition AB, although it is

demonstrable. For it is  clear that the middle must not always be assumed to be an individual  thing, but

sometimes a complex of words, as happens in the case  mentioned. 

36

That the first term belongs to the middle, and the middle to the  extreme, must not be understood in the sense

that they can always be  predicated of one another or that the first term will be predicated of  the middle in the

same way as the middle is predicated of the last  term. The same holds if the premisses are negative. But we

must  suppose the verb 'to belong' to have as many meanings as the senses in  which the verb 'to be' is used,

and in which the assertion that a  thing 'is' may be said to be true. Take for example the statement that  there is

a single science of contraries. Let A stand for 'there  being  a single science', and B for things which are

contrary to one  another.  Then A belongs to B, not in the sense that contraries are the  fact of  there being a

single science of them, but in the sense that it  is true  to say of the contraries that there is a single science of

them. 

It happens sometimes that the first term is stated of the middle,  but the middle is not stated of the third term,

e.g. if wisdom is  knowledge, and wisdom is of the good, the conclusion is that there  is  knowledge of the

good. The good then is not knowledge, though  wisdom  is knowledge. Sometimes the middle term is stated of

the third,  but  the first is not stated of the middle, e.g. if there is a  science of  everything that has a quality, or is

a contrary, and the  good both is  a contrary and has a quality, the conclusion is that  there is a  science of the

good, but the good is not science, nor is  that which  has a quality or is a contrary, though the good is both  of

these.  Sometimes neither the first term is stated of the middle,  nor the  middle of the third, while the first is

sometimes stated of  the third,  and sometimes not: e.g. if there is a genus of that of  which there is  a science,

and if there is a science of the good, we  conclude that  there is a genus of the good. But nothing is  predicated

of anything.  And if that of which there is a science is a  genus, and if there is a  science of the good, we

conclude that the  good is a genus. The first  term then is predicated of the extreme, but  in the premisses one

thing  is not stated of another. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

35 32



Top




Page No 36


The same holds good where the relation is negative. For 'that does  not belong to this' does not always mean

that 'this is not that',  but  sometimes that 'this is not of that' or 'for that', e.g. 'there is  not  a motion of a motion

or a becoming of a becoming, but there is a  becoming of pleasure: so pleasure is not a becoming.' Or again it

may  be said that there is a sign of laughter, but there is not a  sign of a  sign, consequently laughter is not a

sign. This holds in the  other  cases too, in which the thesis is refuted because the genus is  asserted in a

particular way, in relation to the terms of the  thesis.  Again take the inference 'opportunity is not the right

time:  for  opportunity belongs to God, but the right time does not, since  nothing  is useful to God'. We must

take as terms opportunityright  timeGod:  but the premiss must be understood according to the case  of the

noun.  For we state this universally without qualification, that  the terms  ought always to be stated in the

nominative, e.g. man, good,  contraries, not in oblique cases, e.g. of man, of a good, of  contraries, but the

premisses ought to be understood with reference to  the cases of each termeither the dative, e.g. 'equal to

this', or the  genitive, e.g. 'double of this', or the accusative, e.g. 'that which  strikes or sees this', or the

nominative, e.g. 'man is an animal',  or  in whatever other way the word falls in the premiss. 

37

The expressions 'this belongs to that' and 'this holds true of  that'  must be understood in as many ways as there

are different  categories, and these categories must be taken either with or  without  qualification, and further as

simple or compound: the same  holds good  of the corresponding negative expressions. We must consider

these  points and define them better. 

38

A term which is repeated in the premisses ought to be joined to  the first extreme, not to the middle. I mean

for example that if a  syllogism should be made proving that there is knowledge of justice,  that it is good, the

expression 'that it is good' (or 'qua good')  should be joined to the first term. Let A stand for 'knowledge that it

is good', B for good, C for justice. It is true to predicate A of B.  For of the good there is knowledge that it is

good. Also it is true to  predicate B of C. For justice is identical with a good. In this way an  analysis of the

argument can be made. But if the expression 'that it  is good' were added to B, the conclusion will not follow:

for A will  be true of B, but B will not be true of C. For to predicate of justice  the term 'good that it is good' is

false and not intelligible.  Similarly if it should be proved that the healthy is an object of  knowledge qua good,

of goatstag an object of knowledge qua not  existing, or man perishable qua an object of sense: in every case

in  which an addition is made to the predicate, the addition must be  joined to the extreme. 

The position of the terms is not the same when something is  established without qualification and when it is

qualified by some  attribute or condition, e.g. when the good is proved to be an object  of knowledge and when

it is proved to be an object of knowledge that  it is good. If it has been proved to be an object of knowledge

without  qualification, we must put as middle term 'that which is', but if we  add the qualification 'that it is

good', the middle term must be 'that  which is something'. Let A stand for 'knowledge that it is something',  B

stand for 'something', and C stand for 'good'. It is true to  predicate A of B: for ex hypothesi there is a science

of that which is  something, that it is something. B too is true of C: for that which  C  represents is something.

Consequently A is true of C: there will  then  be knowledge of the good, that it is good: for ex hypothesi the

term  'something' indicates the thing's special nature. But if  'being' were  taken as middle and 'being' simply

were joined to the  extreme, not  'being something', we should not have had a syllogism  proving that  there is

knowledge of the good, that it is good, but that  it is; e.g.  let A stand for knowledge that it is, B for being, C

for  good. Clearly  then in syllogisms which are thus limited we must take  the terms in  the way stated. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

37 33



Top




Page No 37


39

We ought also to exchange terms which have the same value, word  for word, and phrase for phrase, and word

and phrase, and always  take  a word in preference to a phrase: for thus the setting out of the  terms will be

easier. For example if it makes no difference whether we  say that the supposable is not the genus of the

opinable or that the  opinable is not identical with a particular kind of supposable (for  what is meant is the

same in both statements), it is better to take as  the terms the supposable and the opinable in preference to the

phrase  suggested. 

40

Since the expressions 'pleasure is good' and 'pleasure is the  good' are not identical, we must not set out the

terms in the same  way; but if the syllogism is to prove that pleasure is the good, the  term must be 'the good',

but if the object is to prove that pleasure  is good, the term will be 'good'. Similarly in all other cases. 

41

It is not the same, either in fact or in speech, that A belongs to  all of that to which B belongs, and that A

belongs to all of that to  all of which B belongs: for nothing prevents B from belonging to C,  though not to all

C: e.g. let B stand for beautiful, and C for  white.  If beauty belongs to something white, it is true to say that

beauty  belongs to that which is white; but not perhaps to everything  that is  white. If then A belongs to B, but

not to everything of  which B is  predicated, then whether B belongs to all C or merely  belongs to C, it  is not

necessary that A should belong, I do not say  to all C, but even  to C at all. But if A belongs to everything of

which B is truly  stated, it will follow that A can be said of all of  that of all of  which B is said. If however A is

said of that of all of  which B may be  said, nothing prevents B belonging to C, and yet A  not belonging to  all

C or to any C at all. If then we take three terms  it is clear that  the expression 'A is said of all of which B is

said' means this, 'A is  said of all the things of which B is said'.  And if B is said of all of  a third term, so also is

A: but if B is not  said of all of the third  term, there is no necessity that A should  be said of all of it. 

We must not suppose that something absurd results through setting  out the terms: for we do not use the

existence of this particular  thing, but imitate the geometrician who says that 'this line a foot  long' or 'this

straight line' or 'this line without breadth' exists  although it does not, but does not use the diagrams in the

sense  that  he reasons from them. For in general, if two things are not  related as  whole to part and part to

whole, the prover does not  prove from them,  and so no syllogism a is formed. We (I mean the  learner) use the

process of setting out terms like perception by  sense, not as though  it were impossible to demonstrate without

these  illustrative terms, as  it is to demonstrate without the premisses of  the syllogism. 

42

We should not forget that in the same syllogism not all  conclusions are reached through one figure, but one

through one  figure, another through another. Clearly then we must analyse  arguments in accordance with this.

Since not every problem is proved  in every figure, but certain problems in each figure, it is clear from  the

conclusion in what figure the premisses should be sought. 

43

In reference to those arguments aiming at a definition which have  been directed to prove some part of the

definition, we must take as  a  term the point to which the argument has been directed, not the  whole

definition: for so we shall be less likely to be disturbed by  the  length of the term: e.g. if a man proves that


PRIOR ANALYTICS

39 34



Top




Page No 38


water is a drinkable  liquid, we must take as terms drinkable and water. 

44

Further we must not try to reduce hypothetical syllogisms; for  with the given premisses it is not possible to

reduce them. For they  have not been proved by syllogism, but assented to by agreement. For  instance if a

man should suppose that unless there is one faculty of  contraries, there cannot be one science, and should

then argue that  not every faculty is of contraries, e.g. of what is healthy and what  is sickly: for the same thing

will then be at the same time healthy  and sickly. He has shown that there is not one faculty of all  contraries,

but he has not proved that there is not a science. And yet  one must agree. But the agreement does not come

from a syllogism,  but  from an hypothesis. This argument cannot be reduced: but the proof  that there is not a

single faculty can. The latter argument perhaps  was a syllogism: but the former was an hypothesis. 

The same holds good of arguments which are brought to a conclusion  per impossibile. These cannot be

analysed either; but the reduction to  what is impossible can be analysed since it is proved by syllogism,

though the rest of the argument cannot, because the conclusion is  reached from an hypothesis. But these

differ from the previous  arguments: for in the former a preliminary agreement must be reached  if one is to

accept the conclusion; e.g. an agreement that if there is  proved to be one faculty of contraries, then contraries

fall under the  same science; whereas in the latter, even if no preliminary  agreement  has been made, men still

accept the reasoning, because the  falsity is  patent, e.g. the falsity of what follows from the  assumption that

the  diagonal is commensurate, viz. that then odd  numbers are equal to  evens. 

Many other arguments are brought to a conclusion by the help of an  hypothesis; these we ought to consider

and mark out clearly. We  shall  describe in the sequel their differences, and the various ways  in  which

hypothetical arguments are formed: but at present this much  must  be clear, that it is not possible to resolve

such arguments  into the  figures. And we have explained the reason. 

45

Whatever problems are proved in more than one figure, if they have  been established in one figure by

syllogism, can be reduced to another  figure, e.g. a negative syllogism in the first figure can be reduced  to the

second, and a syllogism in the middle figure to the first,  not  all however but some only. The point will be

clear in the  sequel. If A  belongs to no B, and B to all C, then A belongs to no  C. Thus the  first figure; but if

the negative statement is  converted, we shall  have the middle figure. For B belongs to no A, and  to all C.

Similarly  if the syllogism is not universal but  particular, e.g. if A belongs to  no B, and B to some C. Convert

the  negative statement and you will  have the middle figure. 

The universal syllogisms in the second figure can be reduced to  the first, but only one of the two particular

syllogisms. Let A belong  to no B and to all C. Convert the negative statement, and you will  have the first

figure. For B will belong to no A and A to all C. But  if the affirmative statement concerns B, and the negative

C, C must be  made first term. For C belongs to no A, and A to all B: therefore C  belongs to no B. B then

belongs to no C: for the negative statement is  convertible. 

But if the syllogism is particular, whenever the negative  statement concerns the major extreme, reduction to

the first figure  will be possible, e.g. if A belongs to no B and to some C: convert the  negative statement and

you will have the first figure. For B will  belong to no A and A to some C. But when the affirmative statement

concerns the major extreme, no resolution will be possible, e.g. if  A  belongs to all B, but not to all C: for the

statement AB does not  admit of conversion, nor would there be a syllogism if it did. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

44 35



Top




Page No 39


Again syllogisms in the third figure cannot all be resolved into  the  first, though all syllogisms in the first

figure can be resolved  into the third. Let A belong to all B and B to some C. Since the  particular affirmative

is convertible, C will belong to some B: but  A  belonged to all B: so that the third figure is formed. Similarly

if  the syllogism is negative: for the particular affirmative is  convertible: therefore A will belong to no B, and

to some C. 

Of the syllogisms in the last figure one only cannot be resolved  into the first, viz. when the negative

statement is not universal: all  the rest can be resolved. Let A and B be affirmed of all C: then C can  be

converted partially with either A or B: C then belongs to some B.  Consequently we shall get the first figure, if

A belongs to all C, and  C to some of the Bs. If A belongs to all C and B to some C, the  argument is the same:

for B is convertible in reference to C. But if B  belongs to all C and A to some C, the first term must be B: for

B  belongs to all C, and C to some A, therefore B belongs to some A.  But  since the particular statement is

convertible, A will belong to  some  B. If the syllogism is negative, when the terms are universal  we must  take

them in a similar way. Let B belong to all C, and A to no  C: then  C will belong to some B, and A to no C;

and so C will be  middle term.  Similarly if the negative statement is universal, the  affirmative  particular: for A

will belong to no C, and C to some of  the Bs. But if  the negative statement is particular, no resolution  will be

possible,  e.g. if B belongs to all C, and A not belong to some  C: convert the  statement BC and both premisses

will be particular. 

It is clear that in order to resolve the figures into one another  the premiss which concerns the minor extreme

must be converted in both  the figures: for when this premiss is altered, the transition to the  other figure is

made. 

One of the syllogisms in the middle figure can, the other cannot,  be  resolved into the third figure. Whenever

the universal statement is  negative, resolution is possible. For if A belongs to no B and to some  C, both B and

C alike are convertible in relation to A, so that B  belongs to no A and C to some A. A therefore is middle

term. But  when  A belongs to all B, and not to some C, resolution will not be  possible: for neither of the

premisses is universal after conversion. 

Syllogisms in the third figure can be resolved into the middle  figure, whenever the negative statement is

universal, e.g. if A  belongs to no C, and B to some or all C. For C then will belong to  no  A and to some B.

But if the negative statement is particular, no  resolution will be possible: for the particular negative does not

admit of conversion. 

It is clear then that the same syllogisms cannot be resolved in  these figures which could not be resolved into

the first figure, and  that when syllogisms are reduced to the first figure these alone are  confirmed by

reduction to what is impossible. 

It is clear from what we have said how we ought to reduce  syllogisms, and that the figures may be resolved

into one another. 

46

In establishing or refuting, it makes some difference whether we  suppose the expressions 'not to be this' and

'to be notthis' are  identical or different in meaning, e.g. 'not to be white' and 'to be  notwhite'. For they do

not mean the same thing, nor is 'to be  notwhite' the negation of 'to be white', but 'not to be white'. The  reason

for this is as follows. The relation of 'he can walk' to 'he  can notwalk' is similar to the relation of 'it is white'

to 'it is  notwhite'; so is that of 'he knows what is good' to 'he knows what is  notgood'. For there is no

difference between the expressions 'he  knows what is good' and 'he is knowing what is good', or 'he can walk'

and 'he is able to walk': therefore there is no difference between  their contraries 'he cannot walk''he is not


PRIOR ANALYTICS

46 36



Top




Page No 40


able to walk'. If then  'he is not able to walk' means the same as 'he is able not to walk',  capacity to walk and

incapacity to walk will belong at the same time  to the same person (for the same man can both walk and

notwalk, and  is possessed of knowledge of what is good and of what is notgood),  but an affirmation and a

denial which are opposed to one another do  not belong at the same time to the same thing. As then 'not to

know  what is good' is not the same as 'to know what is not good', so 'to be  notgood' is not the same as 'not to

be good'. For when two pairs  correspond, if the one pair are different from one another, the  other  pair also

must be different. Nor is 'to be notequal' the same  as 'not  to be equal': for there is something underlying the

one,  viz. that  which is notequal, and this is the unequal, but there is  nothing  underlying the other. Wherefore

not everything is either equal  or  unequal, but everything is equal or is not equal. Further the  expressions 'it is

a notwhite log' and 'it is not a white log' do not  imply one another's truth. For if 'it is a notwhite log', it

must  be  a log: but that which is not a white log need not be a log at  all.  Therefore it is clear that 'it is

notgood' is not the denial  of 'it  is good'. If then every single statement may truly be said to  be  either an

affirmation or a negation, if it is not a negation  clearly  it must in a sense be an affirmation. But every

affirmation  has a  corresponding negation. The negation then of 'it is notgood' is  'it  is not notgood'. The

relation of these statements to one  another is  as follows. Let A stand for 'to be good', B for 'not to  be good', let

C stand for 'to be notgood' and be placed under B,  and let D stand  for not to be notgood' and be placed

under A. Then  either A or B will  belong to everything, but they will never belong to  the same thing;  and

either C or D will belong to everything, but  they will never  belong to the same thing. And B must belong to

everything to which C  belongs. For if it is true to say 'it is a  notwhite', it is true also  to say 'it is not white':

for it is  impossible that a thing should  simultaneously be white and be  notwhite, or be a notwhite log and

be  a white log; consequently if  the affirmation does not belong, the  denial must belong. But C does  not

always belong to B: for what is not  a log at all, cannot be a  notwhite log either. On the other hand D  belongs

to everything to  which A belongs. For either C or D belongs to  everything to which A  belongs. But since a

thing cannot be  simultaneously notwhite and  white, D must belong to everything to  which A belongs. For of

that  which is white it is true to say that it  is not notwhite. But A is  not true of all D. For of that which is not

a log at all it is not  true to say A, viz. that it is a white log.  Consequently D is true,  but A is not true, i.e. that it

is a white  log. It is clear also  that A and C cannot together belong to the same  thing, and that B  and D may

possibly belong to the same thing. 

Privative terms are similarly related positive ter terms respect  of this arrangement. Let A stand for 'equal', B

for 'not equal', C for  'unequal', D for 'not unequal'. 

In many things also, to some of which something belongs which does  not belong to others, the negation may

be true in a similar way,  viz.  that all are not white or that each is not white, while that each  is  notwhite or all

are notwhite is false. Similarly also 'every  animal  is notwhite' is not the negation of 'every animal is white'

(for both  are false): the proper negation is 'every animal is not  white'. Since  it is clear that 'it is notwhite' and

'it is not white'  mean  different things, and one is an affirmation, the other a  denial, it is  evident that the

method of proving each cannot be the  same, e.g. that  whatever is an animal is not white or may not be  white,

and that it is  true to call it notwhite; for this means that  it is notwhite. But we  may prove that it is true to

call it white  or notwhite in the same  way for both are proved constructively by  means of the first figure.  For

the expression 'it is true' stands on a  similar footing to 'it  is'. For the negation of 'it is true to call it  white' is

not 'it is  true to call it notwhite' but 'it is not true to  call it white'. If  then it is to be true to say that whatever

is a man  is musical or is  notmusical, we must assume that whatever is an  animal either is  musical or is

notmusical; and the proof has been  made. That whatever  is a man is not musical is proved destructively in

the three ways  mentioned. 

In general whenever A and B are such that they cannot belong at  the same time to the same thing, and one of

the two necessarily  belongs to everything, and again C and D are related in the same  way,  and A follows C

but the relation cannot be reversed, then D  must  follow B and the relation cannot be reversed. And A and D

may  belong  to the same thing, but B and C cannot. First it is clear from  the  following consideration that D

follows B. For since either C or  D  necessarily belongs to everything; and since C cannot belong to that  to


PRIOR ANALYTICS

46 37



Top




Page No 41


which B belongs, because it carries A along with it and A and B  cannot belong to the same thing; it is clear

that D must follow B.  Again since C does not reciprocate with but A, but C or D belongs to  everything, it is

possible that A and D should belong to the same  thing. But B and C cannot belong to the same thing, because

A  follows  C; and so something impossible results. It is clear then  that B does  not reciprocate with D either,

since it is possible that D  and A  should belong at the same time to the same thing. 

It results sometimes even in such an arrangement of terms that one  is deceived through not apprehending the

opposites rightly, one of  which must belong to everything, e.g. we may reason that 'if A and B  cannot belong

at the same time to the same thing, but it is  necessary  that one of them should belong to whatever the other

does  not belong  to: and again C and D are related in the same way, and  follows  everything which C follows:

it will result that B belongs  necessarily  to everything to which D belongs': but this is false.  'Assume that F

stands for the negation of A and B, and again that H  stands for the  negation of C and D. It is necessary then

that either A  or F should  belong to everything: for either the affirmation or the  denial must  belong. And again

either C or H must belong to everything:  for they  are related as affirmation and denial. And ex hypothesi A

belongs to  everything ever thing to which C belongs. Therefore H  belongs to  everything to which F belongs.

Again since either F or B  belongs to  everything, and similarly either H or D, and since H  follows F, B must

follow D: for we know this. If then A follows C, B  must follow D'. But  this is false: for as we proved the

sequence is  reversed in terms so  constituted. The fallacy arises because perhaps  it is not necessary  that A or F

should belong to everything, or that F  or B should belong  to everything: for F is not the denial of A. For  not

good is the  negation of good: and notgood is not identical with  'neither good nor  notgood'. Similarly also

with C and D. For two  negations have been  assumed in respect to one term. 

Book II

1

WE have already explained the number of the figures, the character  and number of the premisses, when and

how a syllogism is formed;  further what we must look for when a refuting and establishing  propositions, and

how we should investigate a given problem in any  branch of inquiry, also by what means we shall obtain

principles  appropriate to each subject. Since some syllogisms are universal,  others particular, all the universal

syllogisms give more than one  result, and of particular syllogisms the affirmative yield more than  one, the

negative yield only the stated conclusion. For all  propositions are convertible save only the particular

negative: and  the conclusion states one definite thing about another definite thing.  Consequently all

syllogisms save the particular negative yield more  than one conclusion, e.g. if A has been proved to to all or

to some B,  then B must belong to some A: and if A has been proved to belong to no  B, then B belongs to no

A. This is a different conclusion from the  former. But if A does not belong to some B, it is not necessary that

B  should not belong to some A: for it may possibly belong to all A. 

This then is the reason common to all syllogisms whether universal  or particular. But it is possible to give

another reason concerning  those which are universal. For all the things that are subordinate  to  the middle

term or to the conclusion may be proved by the same  syllogism, if the former are placed in the middle, the

latter in the  conclusion; e.g. if the conclusion AB is proved through C, whatever is  subordinate to B or C

must accept the predicate A: for if D is  included in B as in a whole, and B is included in A, then D will be

included in A. Again if E is included in C as in a whole, and C is  included in A, then E will be included in A.

Similarly if the  syllogism is negative. In the second figure it will be possible to  infer only that which is

subordinate to the conclusion, e.g. if A  belongs to no B and to all C; we conclude that B belongs to no C. If

then D is subordinate to C, clearly B does not belong to it. But  that  B does not belong to what is subordinate

to A is not clear by  means of  the syllogism. And yet B does not belong to E, if E is  subordinate to  A. But

while it has been proved through the syllogism  that B belongs  to no C, it has been assumed without proof that

B  does not belong to  A, consequently it does not result through the  syllogism that B does  not belong to E. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

Book II 38



Top




Page No 42


But in particular syllogisms there will be no necessity of  inferring  what is subordinate to the conclusion (for a

syllogism does  not result  when this premiss is particular), but whatever is  subordinate to the  middle term may

be inferred, not however through  the syllogism, e.g.  if A belongs to all B and B to some C. Nothing can  be

inferred about  that which is subordinate to C; something can be  inferred about that  which is subordinate to B,

but not through the  preceding syllogism.  Similarly in the other figures. That which is  subordinate to the

conclusion cannot be proved; the other subordinate  can be proved, only  not through the syllogism, just as in

the  universal syllogisms what is  subordinate to the middle term is proved  (as we saw) from a premiss  which

is not demonstrated: consequently  either a conclusion is not  possible in the case of universal  syllogisms or

else it is possible  also in the case of particular  syllogisms. 

2

It is possible for the premisses of the syllogism to be true, or  to be false, or to be the one true, the other false.

The conclusion is  either true or false necessarily. From true premisses it is not  possible to draw a false

conclusion, but a true conclusion may be  drawn from false premisses, true however only in respect to the  fact,

not to the reason. The reason cannot be established from false  premisses: why this is so will be explained in

the sequel. 

First then that it is not possible to draw a false conclusion from  true premisses, is made clear by this

consideration. If it is  necessary that B should be when A is, it is necessary that A should  not be when B is not.

If then A is true, B must be true: otherwise  it  will turn out that the same thing both is and is not at the same

time.  But this is impossible. Let it not, because A is laid down as  a single  term, be supposed that it is

possible, when a single fact  is given,  that something should necessarily result. For that is not  possible.  For

what results necessarily is the conclusion, and the  means by which  this comes about are at the least three

terms, and  two relations of  subject and predicate or premisses. If then it is  true that A belongs  to all that to

which B belongs, and that B belongs  to all that to  which C belongs, it is necessary that A should belong  to all

that to  which C belongs, and this cannot be false: for then the  same thing  will belong and not belong at the

same time. So A is  posited as one  thing, being two premisses taken together. The same  holds good of

negative syllogisms: it is not possible to prove a false  conclusion  from true premisses. 

But from what is false a true conclusion may be drawn, whether  both the premisses are false or only one,

provided that this is not  either of the premisses indifferently, if it is taken as wholly false:  but if the premiss is

not taken as wholly false, it does not matter  which of the two is false. (1) Let A belong to the whole of C, but

to  none of the Bs, neither let B belong to C. This is possible, e.g.  animal belongs to no stone, nor stone to any

man. If then A is taken  to belong to all B and B to all C, A will belong to all C;  consequently though both the

premisses are false the conclusion is  true: for every man is an animal. Similarly with the negative. For  it  is

possible that neither A nor B should belong to any C, although A  belongs to all B, e.g. if the same terms are

taken and man is put as  middle: for neither animal nor man belongs to any stone, but animal  belongs to every

man. Consequently if one term is taken to belong to  none of that to which it does belong, and the other term

is taken to  belong to all of that to which it does not belong, though both the  premisses are false the conclusion

will be true. (2) A similar proof  may be given if each premiss is partially false. 

(3) But if one only of the premisses is false, when the first  premiss is wholly false, e.g. AB, the conclusion

will not be true, but  if the premiss BC is wholly false, a true conclusion will be possible.  I mean by 'wholly

false' the contrary of the truth, e.g. if what  belongs to none is assumed to belong to all, or if what belongs to

all  is assumed to belong to none. Let A belong to no B, and B to all C. If  then the premiss BC which I take is

true, and the premiss AB is wholly  false, viz. that A belongs to all B, it is impossible that the  conclusion

should be true: for A belonged to none of the Cs, since A  belonged to nothing to which B belonged, and B

belonged to all C.  Similarly there cannot be a true conclusion if A belongs to all B, and  B to all C, but while

the true premiss BC is assumed, the wholly false  premiss AB is also assumed, viz. that A belongs to nothing


PRIOR ANALYTICS

2 39



Top




Page No 43


to which  B  belongs: here the conclusion must be false. For A will belong to all  C, since A belongs to

everything to which B belongs, and B to all C.  It is clear then that when the first premiss is wholly false,

whether  affirmative or negative, and the other premiss is true, the  conclusion  cannot be true. 

(4) But if the premiss is not wholly false, a true conclusion is  possible. For if A belongs to all C and to some

B, and if B belongs to  all C, e.g. animal to every swan and to some white thing, and white to  every swan, then

if we take as premisses that A belongs to all B,  and  B to all C, A will belong to all C truly: for every swan is

an  animal.  Similarly if the statement AB is negative. For it is  possible that A  should belong to some B and to

no C, and that B should  belong to all  C, e.g. animal to some white thing, but to no snow,  and white to all

snow. If then one should assume that A belongs to  no B, and B to all  C, then will belong to no C. 

(5) But if the premiss AB, which is assumed, is wholly true, and  the  premiss BC is wholly false, a true

syllogism will be possible: for  nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to all C, though B belongs  to no C,

e.g. these being species of the same genus which are not  subordinate one to the other: for animal belongs both

to horse and  to  man, but horse to no man. If then it is assumed that A belongs to  all  B and B to all C, the

conclusion will be true, although the  premiss BC  is wholly false. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative.  For

it is  possible that A should belong neither to any B nor to any C,  and that  B should not belong to any C, e.g. a

genus to species of  another  genus: for animal belongs neither to music nor to the art of  healing,  nor does

music belong to the art of healing. If then it is  assumed  that A belongs to no B, and B to all C, the conclusion

will be  true. 

(6) And if the premiss BC is not wholly false but in part only,  even  so the conclusion may be true. For

nothing prevents A belonging  to the  whole of B and of C, while B belongs to some C, e.g. a genus to  its

species and difference: for animal belongs to every man and to  every  footed thing, and man to some footed

things though not to all.  If then  it is assumed that A belongs to all B, and B to all C, A will  belong  to all C:

and this ex hypothesi is true. Similarly if the  premiss AB  is negative. For it is possible that A should neither

belong to any  B nor to any C, though B belongs to some C, e.g. a genus  to the  species of another genus and

its difference: for animal neither  belongs to any wisdom nor to any instance of 'speculative', but wisdom

belongs to some instance of 'speculative'. If then it should be  assumed that A belongs to no B, and B to all C,

will belong to no C:  and this ex hypothesi is true. 

In particular syllogisms it is possible when the first premiss is  wholly false, and the other true, that the

conclusion should be  true;  also when the first premiss is false in part, and the other  true; and  when the first is

true, and the particular is false; and  when both are  false. (7) For nothing prevents A belonging to no B, but  to

some C,  and B to some C, e.g. animal belongs to no snow, but to  some white  thing, and snow to some white

thing. If then snow is  taken as middle,  and animal as first term, and it is assumed that A  belongs to the  whole

of B, and B to some C, then the premiss BC is  wholly false, the  premiss BC true, and the conclusion true.

Similarly if the premiss AB  is negative: for it is possible that A  should belong to the whole of  B, but not to

some C, although B belongs  to some C, e.g. animal  belongs to every man, but does not follow  some white,

but man belongs  to some white; consequently if man be  taken as middle term and it is  assumed that A

belongs to no B but B  belongs to some C, the conclusion  will be true although the premiss AB  is wholly

false. (If the premiss  AB is false in part, the conclusion  may be true. For nothing prevents  A belonging both

to B and to some C,  and B belonging to some C, e.g.  animal to something beautiful and to  something great,

and beautiful  belonging to something great. If then A  is assumed to belong to all B,  and B to some C, the a

premiss AB  will be partially false, the premiss  BC will be true, and the  conclusion true. Similarly if the

premiss AB  is negative. For the same  terms will serve, and in the same positions,  to prove the point. 

(9) Again if the premiss AB is true, and the premiss BC is false,  the conclusion may be true. For nothing

prevents A belonging to the  whole of B and to some C, while B belongs to no C, e.g. animal to  every swan

and to some black things, though swan belongs to no black  thing. Consequently if it should be assumed that

A belongs to all B,  and B to some C, the conclusion will be true, although the statement  BC is false. Similarly


PRIOR ANALYTICS

2 40



Top




Page No 44


if the premiss AB is negative. For it is  possible that A should belong to no B, and not to some C, while B

belongs to no C, e.g. a genus to the species of another genus and to  the accident of its own species: for animal

belongs to no number and  not to some white things, and number belongs to nothing white. If then  number is

taken as middle, and it is assumed that A belongs to no B,  and B to some C, then A will not belong to some

C, which ex  hypothesi  is true. And the premiss AB is true, the premiss BC false. 

(10) Also if the premiss AB is partially false, and the premiss BC  is false too, the conclusion may be true. For

nothing prevents A  belonging to some B and to some C, though B belongs to no C, e.g. if B  is the contrary of

C, and both are accidents of the same genus: for  animal belongs to some white things and to some black

things, but  white belongs to no black thing. If then it is assumed that A  belongs  to all B, and B to some C, the

conclusion will be true.  Similarly if  the premiss AB is negative: for the same terms arranged  in the same  way

will serve for the proof. 

(11) Also though both premisses are false the conclusion may be  true. For it is possible that A may belong to

no B and to some C,  while B belongs to no C, e.g. a genus in relation to the species of  another genus, and to

the accident of its own species: for animal  belongs to no number, but to some white things, and number to

nothing  white. If then it is assumed that A belongs to all B and B  to some C,  the conclusion will be true,

though both premisses are  false.  Similarly also if the premiss AB is negative. For nothing  prevents A

belonging to the whole of B, and not to some C, while B  belongs to no  C, e.g. animal belongs to every swan,

and not to some  black things,  and swan belongs to nothing black. Consequently if it is  assumed that  A

belongs to no B, and B to some C, then A does not  belong to some C.  The conclusion then is true, but the

premisses arc  false. 

3

In the middle figure it is possible in every way to reach a true  conclusion through false premisses, whether

the syllogisms are  universal or particular, viz. when both premisses are wholly false;  when each is partially

false; when one is true, the other wholly false  (it does not matter which of the two premisses is false); if both

premisses are partially false; if one is quite true, the other  partially false; if one is wholly false, the other

partially true. For  (1) if A belongs to no B and to all C, e.g. animal to no stone and  to  every horse, then if the

premisses are stated contrariwise and it  is  assumed that A belongs to all B and to no C, though the premisses

are  wholly false they will yield a true conclusion. Similarly if A  belongs  to all B and to no C: for we shall

have the same syllogism. 

(2) Again if one premiss is wholly false, the other wholly true:  for  nothing prevents A belonging to all B and

to all C, though B  belongs  to no C, e.g. a genus to its coordinate species. For animal  belongs  to every horse

and man, and no man is a horse. If then it is  assumed  that animal belongs to all of the one, and none of the

other,  the  one premiss will be wholly false, the other wholly true, and the  conclusion will be true whichever

term the negative statement  concerns. 

(3) Also if one premiss is partially false, the other wholly true.  For it is possible that A should belong to some

B and to all C, though  B belongs to no C, e.g. animal to some white things and to every  raven, though white

belongs to no raven. If then it is assumed that  A  belongs to no B, but to the whole of C, the premiss AB is

partially  false, the premiss AC wholly true, and the conclusion  true. Similarly  if the negative statement is

transposed: the proof can  be made by  means of the same terms. Also if the affirmative premiss is  partially

false, the negative wholly true, a true conclusion is  possible. For  nothing prevents A belonging to some B, but

not to C  as a whole, while  B belongs to no C, e.g. animal belongs to some white  things, but to no  pitch, and

white belongs to no pitch. Consequently  if it is assumed  that A belongs to the whole of B, but to no C, the

premiss AB is  partially false, the premiss AC is wholly true, and  the conclusion is  true. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

3 41



Top




Page No 45


(4) And if both the premisses are partially false, the conclusion  may be true. For it is possible that A should

belong to some B and  to  some C, and B to no C, e.g. animal to some white things and to some  black things,

though white belongs to nothing black. If then it is  assumed that A belongs to all B and to no C, both

premisses are  partially false, but the conclusion is true. Similarly, if the  negative premiss is transposed, the

proof can be made by means of  the  same terms. 

It is clear also that our thesis holds in particular syllogisms.  For  (5) nothing prevents A belonging to all B and

to some C, though B  does  not belong to some C, e.g. animal to every man and to some white  things, though

man will not belong to some white things. If then it is  stated that A belongs to no B and to some C, the

universal premiss  is  wholly false, the particular premiss is true, and the conclusion is  true. Similarly if the

premiss AB is affirmative: for it is possible  that A should belong to no B, and not to some C, though B does

not  belong to some C, e.g. animal belongs to nothing lifeless, and does  not belong to some white things, and

lifeless will not belong to  some  white things. If then it is stated that A belongs to all B and  not to  some C, the

premiss AB which is universal is wholly false,  the premiss  AC is true, and the conclusion is true. Also a true

conclusion is  possible when the universal premiss is true, and the  particular is  false. For nothing prevents A

following neither B nor  C at all, while  B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal belongs to no  number nor to

anything lifeless, and number does not follow some  lifeless things. If  then it is stated that A belongs to no B

and to  some C, the conclusion  will be true, and the universal premiss true,  but the particular  false. Similarly if

the premiss which is stated  universally is  affirmative. For it is possible that should A belong  both to B and to

C as wholes, though B does not follow some C, e.g.  a genus in relation  to its species and difference: for

animal  follows every man and footed  things as a whole, but man does not  follow every footed thing.

Consequently if it is assumed that A  belongs to the whole of B, but  does not belong to some C, the  universal

premiss is true, the  particular false, and the conclusion  true. 

(6) It is clear too that though both premisses are false they may  yield a true conclusion, since it is possible

that A should belong  both to B and to C as wholes, though B does not follow some C. For  if  it is assumed that

A belongs to no B and to some C, the premisses  are  both false, but the conclusion is true. Similarly if the

universal  premiss is affirmative and the particular negative. For it is possible  that A should follow no B and

all C, though B does not belong to  some  C, e.g. animal follows no science but every man, though science

does  not follow every man. If then A is assumed to belong to the whole  of  B, and not to follow some C, the

premisses are false but the  conclusion is true. 

4

In the last figure a true conclusion may come through what is  false,  alike when both premisses are wholly

false, when each is partly  false,  when one premiss is wholly true, the other false, when one  premiss  is partly

false, the other wholly true, and vice versa, and in  every  other way in which it is possible to alter the

premisses. For  (1)  nothing prevents neither A nor B from belonging to any C, while A  belongs to some B,

e.g. neither man nor footed follows anything  lifeless, though man belongs to some footed things. If then it is

assumed that A and B belong to all C, the premisses will be wholly  false, but the conclusion true. Similarly if

one premiss is  negative,  the other affirmative. For it is possible that B should  belong to no  C, but A to all C,

and that should not belong to some  B, e.g. black  belongs to no swan, animal to every swan, and animal not  to

everything  black. Consequently if it is assumed that B belongs to  all C, and A to  no C, A will not belong to

some B: and the  conclusion is true, though  the premisses are false. 

(2) Also if each premiss is partly false, the conclusion may be  true. For nothing prevents both A and B from

belonging to some C while  A belongs to some B, e.g. white and beautiful belong to some  animals,  and white

to some beautiful things. If then it is stated that  A and B  belong to all C, the premisses are partially false, but

the  conclusion  is true. Similarly if the premiss AC is stated as negative.  For  nothing prevents A from not

belonging, and B from belonging, to  some  C, while A does not belong to all B, e.g. white does not belong  to


PRIOR ANALYTICS

4 42



Top




Page No 46


some animals, beautiful belongs to some animals, and white does not  belong to everything beautiful.

Consequently if it is assumed that A  belongs to no C, and B to all C, both premisses are partly false,  but  the

conclusion is true. 

(3) Similarly if one of the premisses assumed is wholly false, the  other wholly true. For it is possible that both

A and B should  follow  all C, though A does not belong to some B, e.g. animal and  white  follow every swan,

though animal does not belong to everything  white.  Taking these then as terms, if one assumes that B belongs

to  the whole  of C, but A does not belong to C at all, the premiss BC will  be wholly  true, the premiss AC

wholly false, and the conclusion  true. Similarly  if the statement BC is false, the statement AC true,  the

conclusion  may be true. The same terms will serve for the proof.  Also if both the  premisses assumed are

affirmative, the conclusion may  be true. For  nothing prevents B from following all C, and A from not

belonging to C  at all, though A belongs to some B, e.g. animal belongs  to every swan,  black to no swan, and

black to some animals.  Consequently if it is  assumed that A and B belong to every C, the  premiss BC is

wholly true,  the premiss AC is wholly false, and the  conclusion is true. Similarly  if the premiss AC which is

assumed is  true: the proof can be made  through the same terms. 

(4) Again if one premiss is wholly true, the other partly false,  the  conclusion may be true. For it is possible

that B should belong to  all  C, and A to some C, while A belongs to some B, e.g. biped belongs  to  every man,

beautiful not to every man, and beautiful to some  bipeds.  If then it is assumed that both A and B belong to the

whole of  C,  the premiss BC is wholly true, the premiss AC partly false, the  conclusion true. Similarly if of

the premisses assumed AC is true  and  BC partly false, a true conclusion is possible: this can be  proved, if  the

same terms as before are transposed. Also the  conclusion may be  true if one premiss is negative, the other

affirmative. For since it  is possible that B should belong to the  whole of C, and A to some C,  and, when they

are so, that A should  not belong to all B, therefore it  is assumed that B belongs to the  whole of C, and A to no

C, the  negative premiss is partly false, the  other premiss wholly true, and  the conclusion is true. Again since

it has been proved that if A  belongs to no C and B to some C, it is  possible that A should not  belong to some

C, it is clear that if the  premiss AC is wholly true,  and the premiss BC partly false, it is  possible that the

conclusion  should be true. For if it is assumed that  A belongs to no C, and B to  all C, the premiss AC is

wholly true,  and the premiss BC is partly  false. 

(5) It is clear also in the case of particular syllogisms that a  true conclusion may come through what is false,

in every possible way.  For the same terms must be taken as have been taken when the premisses  are

universal, positive terms in positive syllogisms, negative terms  in negative. For it makes no difference to the

setting out of the  terms, whether one assumes that what belongs to none belongs to all or  that what belongs to

some belongs to all. The same applies to negative  statements. 

It is clear then that if the conclusion is false, the premisses of  the argument must be false, either all or some of

them; but when the  conclusion is true, it is not necessary that the premisses should be  true, either one or all,

yet it is possible, though no part of the  syllogism is true, that the conclusion may none the less be true;  but  it

is not necessitated. The reason is that when two things are  so  related to one another, that if the one is, the

other necessarily  is,  then if the latter is not, the former will not be either, but if  the  latter is, it is not necessary

that the former should be. But it  is  impossible that the same thing should be necessitated by the  being and  by

the notbeing of the same thing. I mean, for example,  that it is  impossible that B should necessarily be great

since A is  white and  that B should necessarily be great since A is not white. For  whenever  since this, A, is

white it is necessary that that, B,  should be great,  and since B is great that C should not be white, then  it is

necessary  if is white that C should not be white. And whenever  it is necessary,  since one of two things is, that

the other should be,  it is necessary,  if the latter is not, that the former (viz. A) should  not be. If then  B is not

great A cannot be white. But if, when A is  not white, it is  necessary that B should be great, it necessarily

results that if B is  not great, B itself is great. (But this is  impossible.) For if B is  not great, A will necessarily

not be white.  If then when this is not  white B must be great, it results that if B  is not great, it is great,  just as if

it were proved through three  terms. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

4 43



Top




Page No 47


5

Circular and reciprocal proof means proof by means of the  conclusion, i.e. by converting one of the premisses

simply and  inferring the premiss which was assumed in the original syllogism:  e.g. suppose it has been

necessary to prove that A belongs to all C,  and it has been proved through B; suppose that A should now be

proved  to belong to B by assuming that A belongs to C, and C to Bso A  belongs to B: but in the first

syllogism the converse was assumed,  viz. that B belongs to C. Or suppose it is necessary to prove that B

belongs to C, and A is assumed to belong to C, which was the  conclusion of the first syllogism, and B to

belong to A but the  converse was assumed in the earlier syllogism, viz. that A belongs  to  B. In no other way

is reciprocal proof possible. If another term is  taken as middle, the proof is not circular: for neither of the

propositions assumed is the same as before: if one of the accepted  terms is taken as middle, only one of the

premisses of the first  syllogism can be assumed in the second: for if both of them are  taken  the same

conclusion as before will result: but it must be  different.  If the terms are not convertible, one of the premisses

from  which the  syllogism results must be undemonstrated: for it is not  possible to  demonstrate through these

terms that the third belongs  to the middle  or the middle to the first. If the terms are  convertible, it is  possible

to demonstrate everything reciprocally,  e.g. if A and B and C  are convertible with one another. Suppose the

proposition AC has been  demonstrated through B as middle term, and  again the proposition AB  through the

conclusion and the premiss BC  converted, and similarly the  proposition BC through the conclusion and  the

premiss AB converted.  But it is necessary to prove both the  premiss CB, and the premiss BA:  for we have

used these alone without  demonstrating them. If then it is  assumed that B belongs to all C, and  C to all A, we

shall have a  syllogism relating B to A. Again if it  is assumed that C belongs to  all A, and A to all B, C must

belong to  all B. In both these  syllogisms the premiss CA has been assumed  without being demonstrated:  the

other premisses had ex hypothesi  been proved. Consequently if we  succeed in demonstrating this premiss,  all

the premisses will have  been proved reciprocally. If then it is  assumed that C belongs to all  B, and B to all A,

both the premisses  assumed have been proved, and C  must belong to A. It is clear then  that only if the terms

are  convertible is circular and reciprocal  demonstration possible (if the  terms are not convertible, the matter

stands as we said above). But it  turns out in these also that we use  for the demonstration the very  thing that is

being proved: for C is  proved of B, and B of by assuming  that C is said of and C is proved of  A through these

premisses, so  that we use the conclusion for the  demonstration. 

In negative syllogisms reciprocal proof is as follows. Let B  belong to all C, and A to none of the Bs: we

conclude that A belongs  to none of the Cs. If again it is necessary to prove that A belongs to  none of the Bs

(which was previously assumed) A must belong to no C,  and C to all B: thus the previous premiss is reversed.

If it is  necessary to prove that B belongs to C, the proposition AB must no  longer be converted as before: for

the premiss 'B belongs to no A'  is  identical with the premiss 'A belongs to no B'. But we must  assume  that B

belongs to all of that to none of which longs. Let A  belong to  none of the Cs (which was the previous

conclusion) and  assume that B  belongs to all of that to none of which A belongs. It is  necessary  then that B

should belong to all C. Consequently each of the  three  propositions has been made a conclusion, and this is

circular  demonstration, to assume the conclusion and the converse of one of the  premisses, and deduce the

remaining premiss. 

In particular syllogisms it is not possible to demonstrate the  universal premiss through the other propositions,

but the particular  premiss can be demonstrated. Clearly it is impossible to demonstrate  the universal premiss:

for what is universal is proved through  propositions which are universal, but the conclusion is not universal,

and the proof must start from the conclusion and the other premiss.  Further a syllogism cannot be made at all

if the other premiss is  converted: for the result is that both premisses are particular. But  the particular premiss

may be proved. Suppose that A has been proved  of some C through B. If then it is assumed that B belongs to

all A and  the conclusion is retained, B will belong to some C: for we obtain the  first figure and A is middle.

But if the syllogism is negative, it  is  not possible to prove the universal premiss, for the reason given  above.

But it is possible to prove the particular premiss, if the  proposition AB is converted as in the universal


PRIOR ANALYTICS

5 44



Top




Page No 48


syllogism, i.e 'B  belongs to some of that to some of which A does not belong': otherwise  no syllogism results

because the particular premiss is negative. 

6

In the second figure it is not possible to prove an affirmative  proposition in this way, but a negative

proposition may be proved.  An  affirmative proposition is not proved because both premisses of the  new

syllogism are not affirmative (for the conclusion is negative) but  an affirmative proposition is (as we saw)

proved from premisses  which  are both affirmative. The negative is proved as follows. Let A  belong  to all B,

and to no C: we conclude that B belongs to no C. If  then it  is assumed that B belongs to all A, it is necessary

that A  should  belong to no C: for we get the second figure, with B as middle.  But if  the premiss AB was

negative, and the other affirmative, we  shall have  the first figure. For C belongs to all A and B to no C,

consequently B  belongs to no A: neither then does A belong to B.  Through the  conclusion, therefore, and one

premiss, we get no  syllogism, but if  another premiss is assumed in addition, a  syllogism will be possible.  But

if the syllogism not universal, the  universal premiss cannot be  proved, for the same reason as we gave  above,

but the particular  premiss can be proved whenever the universal  statement is affirmative.  Let A belong to all

B, and not to all C: the  conclusion is BC. If then  it is assumed that B belongs to all A, but  not to all C, A will

not  belong to some C, B being middle. But if  the universal premiss is  negative, the premiss AC will not be

demonstrated by the conversion of  AB: for it turns out that either  both or one of the premisses is  negative;

consequently a syllogism  will not be possible. But the proof  will proceed as in the universal  syllogisms, if it

is assumed that A  belongs to some of that to some of  which B does not belong. 

7

In the third figure, when both premisses are taken universally, it  is not possible to prove them reciprocally:

for that which is  universal is proved through statements which are universal, but the  conclusion in this figure

is always particular, so that it is clear  that it is not possible at all to prove through this figure the  universal

premiss. But if one premiss is universal, the other  particular, proof of the latter will sometimes be possible,

sometimes  not. When both the premisses assumed are affirmative, and  the  universal concerns the minor

extreme, proof will be possible,  but when  it concerns the other extreme, impossible. Let A belong to  all C and

B  to some C: the conclusion is the statement AB. If then  it is assumed  that C belongs to all A, it has been

proved that C  belongs to some B,  but that B belongs to some C has not been proved.  And yet it is  necessary,

if C belongs to some B, that B should  belong to some C. But  it is not the same that this should belong to  that,

and that to this:  but we must assume besides that if this  belongs to some of that, that  belongs to some of this.

But if this  is assumed the syllogism no  longer results from the conclusion and the  other premiss. But if B

belongs to all C, and A to some C, it will  be possible to prove the  proposition AC, when it is assumed that C

belongs to all B, and A to  some B. For if C belongs to all B and A  to some B, it is necessary  that A should

belong to some C, B being  middle. And whenever one  premiss is affirmative the other negative,  and the

affirmative is  universal, the other premiss can be proved. Let  B belong to all C, and  A not to some C: the

conclusion is that A  does not belong to some B.  If then it is assumed further that C  belongs to all B, it is

necessary  that A should not belong to some  C, B being middle. But when the  negative premiss is universal,

the  other premiss is not except as  before, viz. if it is assumed that that  belongs to some of that, to  some of

which this does not belong, e.g.  if A belongs to no C, and B  to some C: the conclusion is that A does  not

belong to some B. If then  it is assumed that C belongs to some  of that to some of which does not  belong, it is

necessary that C  should belong to some of the Bs. In no  other way is it possible by  converting the universal

premiss to prove  the other: for in no other  way can a syllogism be formed. 

It is clear then that in the first figure reciprocal proof is made  both through the third and through the first

figureif the  conclusion  is affirmative through the first; if the conclusion is  negative  through the last. For it is

assumed that that belongs to  all of that  to none of which this belongs. In the middle figure,  when the


PRIOR ANALYTICS

6 45



Top




Page No 49


syllogism is universal, proof is possible through the  second figure  and through the first, but when particular

through the  second and the  last. In the third figure all proofs are made through  itself. It is  clear also that in the

third figure and in the middle  figure those  syllogisms which are not made through those figures  themselves

either  are not of the nature of circular proof or are  imperfect. 

8

To convert a syllogism means to alter the conclusion and make  another syllogism to prove that either the

extreme cannot belong to  the middle or the middle to the last term. For it is necessary, if the  conclusion has

been changed into its opposite and one of the premisses  stands, that the other premiss should be destroyed.

For if it should  stand, the conclusion also must stand. It makes a difference whether  the conclusion is

converted into its contradictory or into its  contrary. For the same syllogism does not result whichever form

the  conversion takes. This will be made clear by the sequel. By  contradictory opposition I mean the

opposition of 'to all' to 'not  to  all', and of 'to some' to 'to none'; by contrary opposition I  mean the  opposition

of 'to all' to 'to none', and of 'to some' to 'not  to  some'. Suppose that A been proved of C, through B as middle

term.  If  then it should be assumed that A belongs to no C, but to all B, B  will  belong to no C. And if A

belongs to no C, and B to all C, A  will  belong, not to no B at all, but not to all B. For (as we saw) the

universal is not proved through the last figure. In a word it is not  possible to refute universally by conversion

the premiss which  concerns the major extreme: for the refutation always proceeds through  the third since it is

necessary to take both premisses in reference to  the minor extreme. Similarly if the syllogism is negative.

Suppose  it  has been proved that A belongs to no C through B. Then if it is  assumed that A belongs to all C,

and to no B, B will belong to none of  the Cs. And if A and B belong to all C, A will belong to some B: but  in

the original premiss it belonged to no B. 

If the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, the  syllogisms will be contradictory and not universal.

For one premiss is  particular, so that the conclusion also will be particular. Let the  syllogism be affirmative,

and let it be converted as stated. Then if A  belongs not to all C, but to all B, B will belong not to all C. And if

A belongs not to all C, but B belongs to all C, A will belong not to  all B. Similarly if the syllogism is

negative. For if A belongs to  some C, and to no B, B will belong, not to no C at all, butnot to  some C. And

if A belongs to some C, and B to all C, as was  originally  assumed, A will belong to some B. 

In particular syllogisms when the conclusion is converted into its  contradictory, both premisses may be

refuted, but when it is converted  into its contrary, neither. For the result is no longer, as in the  universal

syllogisms, refutation in which the conclusion reached by O,  conversion lacks universality, but no refutation

at all. Suppose  that  A has been proved of some C. If then it is assumed that A belongs  to  no C, and B to some

C, A will not belong to some B: and if A  belongs  to no C, but to all B, B will belong to no C. Thus both

premisses are  refuted. But neither can be refuted if the conclusion is  converted  into its contrary. For if A does

not belong to some C, but  to all B,  then B will not belong to some C. But the original premiss  is not yet

refuted: for it is possible that B should belong to some C,  and should  not belong to some C. The universal

premiss AB cannot be  affected by a  syllogism at all: for if A does not belong to some of  the Cs, but B

belongs to some of the Cs, neither of the premisses is  universal.  Similarly if the syllogism is negative: for if it

should be  assumed  that A belongs to all C, both premisses are refuted: but if  the  assumption is that A belongs

to some C, neither premiss is  refuted.  The proof is the same as before. 

9

In the second figure it is not possible to refute the premiss  which concerns the major extreme by establishing

something contrary to  it, whichever form the conversion of the conclusion may take. For  the  conclusion of

the refutation will always be in the third figure,  and  in this figure (as we saw) there is no universal syllogism.

The  other  premiss can be refuted in a manner similar to the conversion:  I mean,  if the conclusion of the first


PRIOR ANALYTICS

8 46



Top




Page No 50


syllogism is converted into its  contrary, the conclusion of the refutation will be the contrary of the  minor

premiss of the first, if into its contradictory, the  contradictory. Let A belong to all B and to no C: conclusion

BC. If  then it is assumed that B belongs to all C, and the proposition AB  stands, A will belong to all C, since

the first figure is produced. If  B belongs to all C, and A to no C, then A belongs not to all B: the  figure is the

last. But if the conclusion BC is converted into its  contradictory, the premiss AB will be refuted as before, the

premiss,  AC by its contradictory. For if B belongs to some C, and A to  no C,  then A will not belong to some

B. Again if B belongs to some  C, and A  to all B, A will belong to some C, so that the syllogism  results in  the

contradictory of the minor premiss. A similar proof can  be given  if the premisses are transposed in respect of

their quality. 

If the syllogism is particular, when the conclusion is converted  into its contrary neither premiss can be

refuted, as also happened  in  the first figure,' if the conclusion is converted into its  contradictory, both

premisses can be refuted. Suppose that A belongs  to no B, and to some C: the conclusion is BC. If then it is

assumed  that B belongs to some C, and the statement AB stands, the  conclusion  will be that A does not

belong to some C. But the  original statement  has not been refuted: for it is possible that A  should belong to

some  C and also not to some C. Again if B belongs  to some C and A to some  C, no syllogism will be

possible: for  neither of the premisses taken  is universal. Consequently the  proposition AB is not refuted. But

if  the conclusion is converted into  its contradictory, both premisses can  be refuted. For if B belongs  to all C,

and A to no B, A will belong to  no C: but it was assumed  to belong to some C. Again if B belongs to  all C

and A to some C, A  will belong to some B. The same proof can be  given if the universal  statement is

affirmative. 

10

In the third figure when the conclusion is converted into its  contrary, neither of the premisses can be refuted

in any of the  syllogisms, but when the conclusion is converted into its  contradictory, both premisses may be

refuted and in all the moods.  Suppose it has been proved that A belongs to some B, C being taken  as  middle,

and the premisses being universal. If then it is assumed  that  A does not belong to some B, but B belongs to all

C, no syllogism  is  formed about A and C. Nor if A does not belong to some B, but  belongs  to all C, will a

syllogism be possible about B and C. A  similar proof  can be given if the premisses are not universal. For

either both  premisses arrived at by the conversion must be particular,  or the  universal premiss must refer to

the minor extreme. But we found  that  no syllogism is possible thus either in the first or in the  middle  figure.

But if the conclusion is converted into its  contradictory,  both the premisses can be refuted. For if A belongs

to no B, and B to  all C, then A belongs to no C: again if A belongs to  no B, and to all  C, B belongs to no C.

And similarly if one of the  premisses is not  universal. For if A belongs to no B, and B to some C,  A will not

belong to some C: if A belongs to no B, and to C, B will  belong to no  C. 

Similarly if the original syllogism is negative. Suppose it has  been  proved that A does not belong to some B,

BC being affirmative, AC  being negative: for it was thus that, as we saw, a syllogism could  be  made.

Whenever then the contrary of the conclusion is assumed a  syllogism will not be possible. For if A belongs to

some B, and B to  all C, no syllogism is possible (as we saw) about A and C. Nor, if A  belongs to some B, and

to no C, was a syllogism possible concerning  B  and C. Therefore the premisses are not refuted. But when the

contradictory of the conclusion is assumed, they are refuted. For if A  belongs to all B, and B to C, A belongs

to all C: but A was supposed  originally to belong to no C. Again if A belongs to all B, and to no  C, then B

belongs to no C: but it was supposed to belong to all C. A  similar proof is possible if the premisses are not

universal. For AC  becomes universal and negative, the other premiss particular and  affirmative. If then A

belongs to all B, and B to some C, it results  that A belongs to some C: but it was supposed to belong to no C.

Again  if A belongs to all B, and to no C, then B belongs to no C: but it was  assumed to belong to some C. If

A belongs to some B and B to some C,  no syllogism results: nor yet if A belongs to some B, and to no C.

Thus in one way the premisses are refuted, in the other way they are  not. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

10 47



Top




Page No 51


From what has been said it is clear how a syllogism results in  each figure when the conclusion is converted;

when a result contrary  to the premiss, and when a result contradictory to the premiss, is  obtained. It is clear

that in the first figure the syllogisms are  formed through the middle and the last figures, and the premiss

which  concerns the minor extreme is alway refuted through the middle  figure,  the premiss which concerns the

major through the last  figure. In the  second figure syllogisms proceed through the first  and the last  figures,

and the premiss which concerns the minor extreme  is always  refuted through the first figure, the premiss

which concerns  the major  extreme through the last. In the third figure the refutation  proceeds  through the first

and the middle figures; the premiss which  concerns  the major is always refuted through the first figure, the

premiss  which concerns the minor through the middle figure. 

11

It is clear then what conversion is, how it is effected in each  figure, and what syllogism results. The syllogism

per impossibile is  proved when the contradictory of the conclusion stated and another  premiss is assumed; it

can be made in all the figures. For it  resembles conversion, differing only in this: conversion takes place  after

a syllogism has been formed and both the premisses have been  taken, but a reduction to the impossible takes

place not because the  contradictory has been agreed to already, but because it is clear that  it is true. The terms

are alike in both, and the premisses of both are  taken in the same way. For example if A belongs to all B, C

being  middle, then if it is supposed that A does not belong to all B or  belongs to no B, but to all C (which was

admitted to be true), it  follows that C belongs to no B or not to all B. But this is  impossible: consequently the

supposition is false: its contradictory  then is true. Similarly in the other figures: for whatever moods admit  of

conversion admit also of the reduction per impossibile. 

All the problems can be proved per impossibile in all the figures,  excepting the universal affirmative, which

is proved in the middle and  third figures, but not in the first. Suppose that A belongs not to all  B, or to no B,

and take besides another premiss concerning either of  the terms, viz. that C belongs to all A, or that B belongs

to all D;  thus we get the first figure. If then it is supposed that A does not  belong to all B, no syllogism results

whichever term the assumed  premiss concerns; but if it is supposed that A belongs to no B, when  the premiss

BD is assumed as well we shall prove syllogistically  what  is false, but not the problem proposed. For if A

belongs to no B,  and  B belongs to all D, A belongs to no D. Let this be impossible:  it is  false then A belongs

to no B. But the universal affirmative is  not  necessarily true if the universal negative is false. But if the

premiss CA is assumed as well, no syllogism results, nor does it do so  when it is supposed that A does not

belong to all B. Consequently it  is clear that the universal affirmative cannot be proved in the  first  figure per

impossibile. 

But the particular affirmative and the universal and particular  negatives can all be proved. Suppose that A

belongs to no B, and let  it have been assumed that B belongs to all or to some C. Then it is  necessary that A

should belong to no C or not to all C. But this is  impossible (for let it be true and clear that A belongs to all

C):  consequently if this is false, it is necessary that A should belong to  some B. But if the other premiss

assumed relates to A, no syllogism  will be possible. Nor can a conclusion be drawn when the contrary of  the

conclusion is supposed, e.g. that A does not belong to some B.  Clearly then we must suppose the

contradictory. 

Again suppose that A belongs to some B, and let it have been  assumed  that C belongs to all A. It is necessary

then that C should  belong  to some B. But let this be impossible, so that the supposition  is  false: in that case it

is true that A belongs to no B. We may  proceed in the same way if the proposition CA has been taken as

negative. But if the premiss assumed concerns B, no syllogism will  be  possible. If the contrary is supposed,

we shall have a syllogism  and  an impossible conclusion, but the problem in hand is not proved.  Suppose that

A belongs to all B, and let it have been assumed that C  belongs to all A. It is necessary then that C should

belong to all  B.  But this is impossible, so that it is false that A belongs to all  B.  But we have not yet shown it


PRIOR ANALYTICS

11 48



Top




Page No 52


to be necessary that A belongs to no  B,  if it does not belong to all B. Similarly if the other premiss  taken

concerns B; we shall have a syllogism and a conclusion which  is  impossible, but the hypothesis is not refuted.

Therefore it is  the  contradictory that we must suppose. 

To prove that A does not belong to all B, we must suppose that it  belongs to all B: for if A belongs to all B,

and C to all A, then C  belongs to all B; so that if this is impossible, the hypothesis is  false. Similarly if the

other premiss assumed concerns B. The same  results if the original proposition CA was negative: for thus

also  we  get a syllogism. But if the negative proposition concerns B,  nothing  is proved. If the hypothesis is

that A belongs not to all  but to some  B, it is not proved that A belongs not to all B, but  that it belongs  to no B.

For if A belongs to some B, and C to all A,  then C will  belong to some B. If then this is impossible, it is  false

that A  belongs to some B; consequently it is true that A belongs  to no B. But  if this is proved, the truth is

refuted as well; for  the original  conclusion was that A belongs to some B, and does not  belong to some  B.

Further the impossible does not result from the  hypothesis: for  then the hypothesis would be false, since it is

impossible to draw a  false conclusion from true premisses: but in fact  it is true: for A  belongs to some B.

Consequently we must not  suppose that A belongs to  some B, but that it belongs to all B.  Similarly if we

should be  proving that A does not belong to some B:  for if 'not to belong to  some' and 'to belong not to all'

have the  same meaning, the  demonstration of both will be identical. 

It is clear then that not the contrary but the contradictory ought  to be supposed in all the syllogisms. For thus

we shall have necessity  of inference, and the claim we make is one that will be generally  accepted. For if of

everything one or other of two contradictory  statements holds good, then if it is proved that the negation does

not  hold, the affirmation must be true. Again if it is not admitted that  the affirmation is true, the claim that the

negation is true will be  generally accepted. But in neither way does it suit to maintain the  contrary: for it is

not necessary that if the universal negative is  false, the universal affirmative should be true, nor is it generally

accepted that if the one is false the other is true. 

12

It is clear then that in the first figure all problems except the  universal affirmative are proved per impossibile.

But in the middle  and the last figures this also is proved. Suppose that A does not  belong to all B, and let it

have been assumed that A belongs to all C.  If then A belongs not to all B, but to all C, C will not belong to all

B. But this is impossible (for suppose it to be clear that C belongs  to all B): consequently the hypothesis is

false. It is true then  that  A belongs to all B. But if the contrary is supposed, we shall  have a  syllogism and a

result which is impossible: but the problem  in hand is  not proved. For if A belongs to no B, and to all C, C

will belong to  no B. This is impossible; so that it is false that A  belongs to no B.  But though this is false, it

does not follow that  it is true that A  belongs to all B. 

When A belongs to some B, suppose that A belongs to no B, and let  A belong to all C. It is necessary then

that C should belong to no  B.  Consequently, if this is impossible, A must belong to some B. But  if  it is

supposed that A does not belong to some B, we shall have  the  same results as in the first figure. 

Again suppose that A belongs to some B, and let A belong to no C.  It  is necessary then that C should not

belong to some B. But  originally  it belonged to all B, consequently the hypothesis is false:  A then  will belong

to no B. 

When A does not belong to an B, suppose it does belong to all B,  and  to no C. It is necessary then that C

should belong to no B. But  this  is impossible: so that it is true that A does not belong to all  B.  It is clear then

that all the syllogisms can be formed in the  middle  figure. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

12 49



Top




Page No 53


13

Similarly they can all be formed in the last figure. Suppose that  A does not belong to some B, but C belongs

to all B: then A does not  belong to some C. If then this is impossible, it is false that A  does  not belong to

some B; so that it is true that A belongs to all B.  But  if it is supposed that A belongs to no B, we shall have a

syllogism  and a conclusion which is impossible: but the problem in  hand is not  proved: for if the contrary is

supposed, we shall have the  same  results as before. 

But to prove that A belongs to some B, this hypothesis must be  made.  If A belongs to no B, and C to some B,

A will belong not to all  C.  If then this is false, it is true that A belongs to some B. 

When A belongs to no B, suppose A belongs to some B, and let it  have  been assumed that C belongs to all B.

Then it is necessary that A  should belong to some C. But ex hypothesi it belongs to no C, so  that  it is false

that A belongs to some B. But if it is supposed  that A  belongs to all B, the problem is not proved. 

But this hypothesis must be made if we are prove that A belongs  not to all B. For if A belongs to all B and C

to some B, then A  belongs to some C. But this we assumed not to be so, so it is false  that A belongs to all B.

But in that case it is true that A belongs  not to all B. If however it is assumed that A belongs to some B, we

shall have the same result as before. 

It is clear then that in all the syllogisms which proceed per  impossibile the contradictory must be assumed.

And it is plain that in  the middle figure an affirmative conclusion, and in the last figure  a  universal

conclusion, are proved in a way. 

14

Demonstration per impossibile differs from ostensive proof in that  it posits what it wishes to refute by

reduction to a statement  admitted to be false; whereas ostensive proof starts from admitted  positions. Both,

indeed, take two premisses that are admitted, but the  latter takes the premisses from which the syllogism

starts, the former  takes one of these, along with the contradictory of the original  conclusion. Also in the

ostensive proof it is not necessary that the  conclusion should be known, nor that one should suppose

beforehand  that it is true or not: in the other it is necessary to suppose  beforehand that it is not true. It makes

no difference whether the  conclusion is affirmative or negative; the method is the same in  both  cases.

Everything which is concluded ostensively can be proved  per  impossibile, and that which is proved per

impossibile can be  proved  ostensively, through the same terms. Whenever the syllogism  is formed  in the first

figure, the truth will be found in the middle  or the last  figure, if negative in the middle, if affirmative in the

last.  Whenever the syllogism is formed in the middle figure, the truth  will  be found in the first, whatever the

problem may be. Whenever  the  syllogism is formed in the last figure, the truth will be found in  the  first and

middle figures, if affirmative in first, if negative  in the  middle. Suppose that A has been proved to belong to

no B, or  not to  all B, through the first figure. Then the hypothesis must  have been  that A belongs to some B,

and the original premisses that  C belongs to  all A and to no B. For thus the syllogism was made and  the

impossible  conclusion reached. But this is the middle figure, if C  belongs to all  A and to no B. And it is clear

from these premisses  that A belongs to  no B. Similarly if has been proved not to belong  to all B. For the

hypothesis is that A belongs to all B; and the  original premisses are  that C belongs to all A but not to all B.

Similarly too, if the  premiss CA should be negative: for thus also  we have the middle  figure. Again suppose it

has been proved that A  belongs to some B. The  hypothesis here is that is that A belongs to no  B; and the

original  premisses that B belongs to all C, and A either to  all or to some C:  for in this way we shall get what

is impossible. But  if A and B belong  to all C, we have the last figure. And it is clear  from these  premisses that

A must belong to some B. Similarly if B or A  should be  assumed to belong to some C. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

13 50



Top




Page No 54


Again suppose it has been proved in the middle figure that A  belongs  to all B. Then the hypothesis must have

been that A belongs  not to all  B, and the original premisses that A belongs to all C, and  C to all B:  for thus

we shall get what is impossible. But if A belongs  to all C,  and C to all B, we have the first figure. Similarly if

it  has been  proved that A belongs to some B: for the hypothesis then must  have  been that A belongs to no B,

and the original premisses that A  belongs  to all C, and C to some B. If the syllogism is negative, the

hypothesis must have been that A belongs to some B, and the original  premisses that A belongs to no C, and

C to all B, so that the first  figure results. If the syllogism is not universal, but proof has  been  given that A

does not belong to some B, we may infer in the  same way.  The hypothesis is that A belongs to all B, the

original  premisses that  A belongs to no C, and C belongs to some B: for thus we  get the first  figure. 

Again suppose it has been proved in the third figure that A  belongs to all B. Then the hypothesis must have

been that A belongs  not to all B, and the original premisses that C belongs to all B,  and  A belongs to all C;

for thus we shall get what is impossible.  And the  original premisses form the first figure. Similarly if the

demonstration establishes a particular proposition: the hypothesis  then must have been that A belongs to no

B, and the original premisses  that C belongs to some B, and A to all C. If the syllogism is  negative, the

hypothesis must have been that A belongs to some B,  and  the original premisses that C belongs to no A and

to all B, and  this  is the middle figure. Similarly if the demonstration is not  universal.  The hypothesis will then

be that A belongs to all B, the  premisses  that C belongs to no A and to some B: and this is the middle  figure. 

It is clear then that it is possible through the same terms to  prove  each of the problems ostensively as well.

Similarly it will be  possible if the syllogisms are ostensive to reduce them ad impossibile  in the terms which

have been taken, whenever the contradictory of  the  conclusion of the ostensive syllogism is taken as a

premiss. For  the  syllogisms become identical with those which are obtained by means  of  conversion, so that

we obtain immediately the figures through which  each problem will be solved. It is clear then that every

thesis can be  proved in both ways, i.e. per impossibile and ostensively, and it is  not possible to separate one

method from the other. 

15

In what figure it is possible to draw a conclusion from premisses  which are opposed, and in what figure this is

not possible, will be  made clear in this way. Verbally four kinds of opposition are  possible, viz. universal

affirmative to universal negative,  universal  affirmative to particular negative, particular affirmative  to

universal negative, and particular affirmative to particular  negative:  but really there are only three: for the

particular  affirmative is  only verbally opposed to the particular negative. Of  the genuine  opposites I call those

which are universal contraries, the  universal  affirmative and the universal negative, e.g. 'every  science is

good',  'no science is good'; the others I call  contradictories. 

In the first figure no syllogism whether affirmative or negative  can  be made out of opposed premisses: no

affirmative syllogism is  possible  because both premisses must be affirmative, but opposites  are, the one

affirmative, the other negative: no negative syllogism is  possible  because opposites affirm and deny the same

predicate of the  same  subject, and the middle term in the first figure is not  predicated  of both extremes, but

one thing is denied of it, and it is  affirmed of  something else: but such premisses are not opposed. 

In the middle figure a syllogism can be made both  oLcontradictories and of contraries. Let A stand for good,

let B and C  stand for science. If then one assumes that every science is good, and  no science is good, A

belongs to all B and to no C, so that B  belongs  to no C: no science then is a science. Similarly if after  taking

'every science is good' one took 'the science of medicine is  not  good'; for A belongs to all B but to no C, so

that a particular  science will not be a science. Again, a particular science will not be  a science if A belongs to

all C but to no B, and B is science, C  medicine, and A supposition: for after taking 'no science is  supposition',

one has assumed that a particular science is  supposition. This syllogism differs from the preceding because


PRIOR ANALYTICS

15 51



Top




Page No 55


the  relations between the terms are reversed: before, the affirmative  statement concerned B, now it concerns

C. Similarly if one premiss  is  not universal: for the middle term is always that which is stated  negatively of

one extreme, and affirmatively of the other.  Consequently it is possible that contradictories may lead to a

conclusion, though not always or in every mood, but only if the  terms  subordinate to the middle are such that

they are either  identical or  related as whole to part. Otherwise it is impossible: for  the  premisses cannot

anyhow be either contraries or contradictories. 

In the third figure an affirmative syllogism can never be made out  of opposite premisses, for the reason given

in reference to the  first  figure; but a negative syllogism is possible whether the terms  are  universal or not. Let

B and C stand for science, A for medicine.  If  then one should assume that all medicine is science and that no

medicine is science, he has assumed that B belongs to all A and C to  no A, so that a particular science will

not be a science. Similarly if  the premiss BA is not assumed universally. For if some medicine is  science and

again no medicine is science, it results that some science  is not science, The premisses are contrary if the

terms are taken  universally; if one is particular, they are contradictory. 

We must recognize that it is possible to take opposites in the way  we said, viz. 'all science is good' and 'no

science is good' or  'some  science is not good'. This does not usually escape notice. But  it is  possible to

establish one part of a contradiction through  other  premisses, or to assume it in the way suggested in the

Topics.  Since  there are three oppositions to affirmative statements, it  follows that  opposite statements may be

assumed as premisses in six  ways; we may  have either universal affirmative and negative, or  universal

affirmative and particular negative, or particular  affirmative and  universal negative, and the relations between

the  terms may be  reversed; e.g. A may belong to all B and to no C, or to  all C and to  no B, or to all of the one,

not to all of the other; here  too the  relation between the terms may be reversed. Similarly in the  third  figure.

So it is clear in how many ways and in what figures a  syllogism can be made by means of premisses which

are opposed. 

It is clear too that from false premisses it is possible to draw a  true conclusion, as has been said before, but it

is not possible if  the premisses are opposed. For the syllogism is always contrary to the  fact, e.g. if a thing is

good, it is proved that it is not good, if an  animal, that it is not an animal because the syllogism springs out  of

a contradiction and the terms presupposed are either identical or  related as whole and part. It is evident also

that in fallacious  reasonings nothing prevents a contradiction to the hypothesis from  resulting, e.g. if

something is odd, it is not odd. For the  syllogism  owed its contrariety to its contradictory premisses; if we

assume such  premisses we shall get a result that contradicts our  hypothesis. But  we must recognize that

contraries cannot be inferred  from a single  syllogism in such a way that we conclude that what is  not good is

good, or anything of that sort unless a selfcontradictory  premiss is  at once assumed, e.g. 'every animal is

white and not  white', and we  proceed 'man is an animal'. Either we must introduce  the contradiction  by an

additional assumption, assuming, e.g., that  every science is  supposition, and then assuming 'Medicine is a

science, but none of it  is supposition' (which is the mode in which  refutations are made), or  we must argue

from two syllogisms. In no  other way than this, as was  said before, is it possible that the  premisses should be

really  contrary. 

16

To beg and assume the original question is a species of failure to  demonstrate the problem proposed; but this

happens in many ways. A man  may not reason syllogistically at all, or he may argue from  premisses  which

are less known or equally unknown, or he may establish  the  antecedent by means of its consequents; for

demonstration proceeds  from what is more certain and is prior. Now begging the question is  none of these:

but since we get to know some things naturally  through  themselves, and other things by means of something

else (the  first  principles through themselves, what is subordinate to them  through  something else), whenever a

man tries to prove what is not  selfevident by means of itself, then he begs the original question.  This may be


PRIOR ANALYTICS

16 52



Top




Page No 56


done by assuming what is in question at once; it is also  possible to make a transition to other things which

would naturally be  proved through the thesis proposed, and demonstrate it through them,  e.g. if A should be

proved through B, and B through C, though it was  natural that C should be proved through A: for it turns out

that those  who reason thus are proving A by means of itself. This is what those  persons do who suppose that

they are constructing parallel straight  lines: for they fail to see that they are assuming facts which it is

impossible to demonstrate unless the parallels exist. So it turns  out  that those who reason thus merely say a

particular thing is, if it  is:  in this way everything will be selfevident. But that is  impossible. 

If then it is uncertain whether A belongs to C, and also whether A  belongs to B, and if one should assume that

A does belong to B, it  is  not yet clear whether he begs the original question, but it is  evident  that he is not

demonstrating: for what is as uncertain as  the question  to be answered cannot be a principle of a

demonstration. If however B  is so related to C that they are  identical, or if they are plainly  convertible, or the

one belongs to  the other, the original question is  begged. For one might equally well  prove that A belongs to

B through  those terms if they are convertible.  But if they are not convertible,  it is the fact that they are not

that  prevents such a demonstration,  not the method of demonstrating. But if  one were to make the  conversion,

then he would be doing what we have  described and  effecting a reciprocal proof with three propositions. 

Similarly if he should assume that B belongs to C, this being as  uncertain as the question whether A belongs

to C, the question is  not  yet begged, but no demonstration is made. If however A and B are  identical either

because they are convertible or because A follows  B,  then the question is begged for the same reason as

before. For we  have  explained the meaning of begging the question, viz. proving  that which  is not

selfevident by means of itself. 

If then begging the question is proving what is not selfevident  by means of itself, in other words failing to

prove when the failure  is due to the thesis to be proved and the premiss through which it  is  proved being

equally uncertain, either because predicates which are  identical belong to the same subject, or because the

same predicate  belongs to subjects which are identical, the question may be begged in  the middle and third

figures in both ways, though, if the syllogism is  affirmative, only in the third and first figures. If the

syllogism  is  negative, the question is begged when identical predicates are  denied  of the same subject; and

both premisses do not beg the question  indifferently (in a similar way the question may be begged in the

middle figure), because the terms in negative syllogisms are not  convertible. In scientific demonstrations the

question is begged  when  the terms are really related in the manner described, in  dialectical  arguments when

they are according to common opinion so  related. 

17

The objection that 'this is not the reason why the result is  false',  which we frequently make in argument, is

made primarily in the  case of  a reductio ad impossibile, to rebut the proposition which was  being  proved by

the reduction. For unless a man has contradicted this  proposition he will not say, 'False cause', but urge that

something  false has been assumed in the earlier parts of the argument; nor  will  he use the formula in the case

of an ostensive proof; for here  what  one denies is not assumed as a premiss. Further when anything  is  refuted

ostensively by the terms ABC, it cannot be objected that  the  syllogism does not depend on the assumption

laid down. For we  use the  expression 'false cause', when the syllogism is concluded in  spite of  the refutation

of this position; but that is not possible  in ostensive  proofs: since if an assumption is refuted, a syllogism  can

no longer  be drawn in reference to it. It is clear then that the  expression  'false cause' can only be used in the

case of a reductio ad  impossibile, and when the original hypothesis is so related to the  impossible conclusion,

that the conclusion results indifferently  whether the hypothesis is made or not. The most obvious case of the

irrelevance of an assumption to a conclusion which is false is when  a  syllogism drawn from middle terms to

an impossible conclusion is  independent of the hypothesis, as we have explained in the Topics. For  to put that

which is not the cause as the cause, is just this: e.g. if  a man, wishing to prove that the diagonal of the square


PRIOR ANALYTICS

17 53



Top




Page No 57


is  incommensurate with the side, should try to prove Zeno's theorem  that  motion is impossible, and so

establish a reductio ad impossibile:  for  Zeno's false theorem has no connexion at all with the original

assumption. Another case is where the impossible conclusion is  connected with the hypothesis, but does not

result from it. This may  happen whether one traces the connexion upwards or downwards, e.g.  if  it is laid

down that A belongs to B, B to C, and C to D, and it  should  be false that B belongs to D: for if we eliminated

A and  assumed all  the same that B belongs to C and C to D, the false  conclusion would  not depend on the

original hypothesis. Or again trace  the connexion  upwards; e.g. suppose that A belongs to B, E to A and  F to

E, it being  false that F belongs to A. In this way too the  impossible conclusion  would result, though the

original hypothesis  were eliminated. But the  impossible conclusion ought to be connected  with the original

terms:  in this way it will depend on the hypothesis,  e.g. when one traces the  connexion downwards, the

impossible  conclusion must be connected with  that term which is predicate in  the hypothesis: for if it is

impossible that A should belong to D, the  false conclusion will no  longer result after A has been eliminated.

If  one traces the connexion  upwards, the impossible conclusion must be  connected with that term  which is

subject in the hypothesis: for if it  is impossible that F  should belong to B, the impossible conclusion  will

disappear if B is  eliminated. Similarly when the syllogisms are  negative. 

It is clear then that when the impossibility is not related to the  original terms, the false conclusion does not

result on account of the  assumption. Or perhaps even so it may sometimes be independent. For if  it were laid

down that A belongs not to B but to K, and that K belongs  to C and C to D, the impossible conclusion would

still stand.  Similarly if one takes the terms in an ascending series.  Consequently  since the impossibility results

whether the first  assumption is  suppressed or not, it would appear to be independent  of that  assumption. Or

perhaps we ought not to understand the  statement that  the false conclusion results independently of the

assumption, in the  sense that if something else were supposed the  impossibility would  result; but rather we

mean that when the first  assumption is  eliminated, the same impossibility results through the  remaining

premisses; since it is not perhaps absurd that the same  false result  should follow from several hypotheses, e.g.

that  parallels meet, both  on the assumption that the interior angle is  greater than the exterior  and on the

assumption that a triangle  contains more than two right  angles. 

18

A false argument depends on the first false statement in it. Every  syllogism is made out of two or more

premisses. If then the false  conclusion is drawn from two premisses, one or both of them must be  false: for

(as we proved) a false syllogism cannot be drawn from two  premisses. But if the premisses are more than

two, e.g. if C is  established through A and B, and these through D, E, F, and G, one  of  these higher

propositions must be false, and on this the argument  depends: for A and B are inferred by means of D, E, F,

and G.  Therefore the conclusion and the error results from one of them. 

19

In order to avoid having a syllogism drawn against us we must take  care, whenever an opponent asks us to

admit the reason without the  conclusions, not to grant him the same term twice over in his  premisses, since

we know that a syllogism cannot be drawn without a  middle term, and that term which is stated more than

once is the  middle. How we ought to watch the middle in reference to each  conclusion, is evident from our

knowing what kind of thesis is  proved  in each figure. This will not escape us since we know how we  are

maintaining the argument. 

That which we urge men to beware of in their admissions, they  ought in attack to try to conceal. This will be

possible first, if,  instead of drawing the conclusions of preliminary syllogisms, they  take the necessary

premisses and leave the conclusions in the dark;  secondly if instead of inviting assent to propositions which

are  closely connected they take as far as possible those that are not  connected by middle terms. For example


PRIOR ANALYTICS

18 54



Top




Page No 58


suppose that A is to be  inferred to be true of F, B, C, D, and E being middle terms. One ought  then to ask

whether A belongs to B, and next whether D belongs to E,  instead of asking whether B belongs to C; after

that he may ask  whether B belongs to C, and so on. If the syllogism is drawn through  one middle term, he

ought to begin with that: in this way he will most  likely deceive his opponent. 

20

Since we know when a syllogism can be formed and how its terms  must be related, it is clear when refutation

will be possible and when  impossible. A refutation is possible whether everything is conceded,  or the answers

alternate (one, I mean, being affirmative, the other  negative). For as has been shown a se error results from

one of them. 

It sometimes happens that just as we are deceived in the  arrangement  of the terms, so error may arise in our

thought about  them, e.g. if it  is possible that the same predicate should belong to  more than one  subject

immediately, but although knowing the one, a man  may forget  the other and think the opposite true. Suppose

that A  belongs to B and  to C in virtue of their nature, and that B and C  belong to all D in  the same way. If

then a man thinks that A belongs  to all B, and B to  D, but A to no C, and C to all D, he will both know  and

not know the  same thing in respect of the same thing. Again if a  man were to make a  mistake about the

members of a single series; e.g.  suppose A belongs  to B, B to C, and C to D, but some one thinks that A

belongs to all B,  but to no C: he will both know that A belongs to D,  and think that  it does not. Does he then

maintain after this simply  that what he  knows, he does not think? For he knows in a way that A  belongs to C

through B, since the part is included in the whole; so  that what he  knows in a way, this he maintains he does

not think at  all: but that  is impossible. 

In the former case, where the middle term does not belong to the  same series, it is not possible to think both

the premisses with  reference to each of the two middle terms: e.g. that A belongs to  all  B, but to no C, and

both B and C belong to all D. For it turns out  that the first premiss of the one syllogism is either wholly or

partially contrary to the first premiss of the other. For if he thinks  that A belongs to everything to which B

belongs, and he knows that B  belongs to D, then he knows that A belongs to D. Consequently if again  he

thinks that A belongs to nothing to which C belongs, he thinks that  A does not belong to some of that to

which B belongs; but if he thinks  that A belongs to everything to which B belongs, and again thinks that  A

does not belong to some of that to which B belongs, these beliefs  are wholly or partially contrary. In this way

then it is not  possible  to think; but nothing prevents a man thinking one premiss  of each  syllogism of both

premisses of one of the two syllogisms: e.g.  A  belongs to all B, and B to D, and again A belongs to no C. An

error of  this kind is similar to the error into which we fall  concerning  particulars: e.g. if A belongs to all B,

and B to all C,  A will belong  to all C. If then a man knows that A belongs to  everything to which B  belongs,

he knows that A belongs to C. But  nothing prevents his being  ignorant that C exists; e.g. let A stand  for two

right angles, B for  triangle, C for a particular diagram of  a triangle. A man might think  that C did not exist,

though he knew  that every triangle contains two  right angles; consequently he will  know and not know the

same thing at  the same time. For the  expression 'to know that every triangle has its  angles equal to two  right

angles' is ambiguous, meaning to have the  knowledge either of  the universal or of the particulars. Thus then

he  knows that C  contains two right angles with a knowledge of the  universal, but not  with a knowledge of the

particulars; consequently  his knowledge will  not be contrary to his ignorance. The argument in  the Meno that

learning is recollection may be criticized in a similar  way. For it  never happens that a man starts with a

foreknowledge of  the  particular, but along with the process of being led to see the  general  principle he

receives a knowledge of the particulars, by an  act (as it  were) of recognition. For we know some things

directly;  e.g. that  the angles are equal to two right angles, if we know that  the figure  is a triangle. Similarly in

all other cases. 

By a knowledge of the universal then we see the particulars, but  we do not know them by the kind of


PRIOR ANALYTICS

20 55



Top




Page No 59


knowledge which is proper to  them;  consequently it is possible that we may make mistakes about  them, but

not that we should have the knowledge and error that are  contrary to  one another: rather we have the

knowledge of the universal  but make a  mistake in apprehending the particular. Similarly in the  cases stated

above. The error in respect of the middle term is not  contrary to the  knowledge obtained through the

syllogism, nor is the  thought in  respect of one middle term contrary to that in respect of  the other.  Nothing

prevents a man who knows both that A belongs to the  whole of  B, and that B again belongs to C, thinking

that A does not  belong to  C, e.g. knowing that every mule is sterile and that this  is a mule,  and thinking that

this animal is with foal: for he does not  know that  A belongs to C, unless he considers the two propositions

together. So  it is evident that if he knows the one and does not  know the other, he  will fall into error. And this

is the relation of  knowledge of the  universal to knowledge of the particular. For we know  no sensible  thing,

once it has passed beyond the range of our  senses, even if we  happen to have perceived it, except by means of

the  universal and the  possession of the knowledge which is proper to the  particular, but  without the actual

exercise of that knowledge. For  to know is used in  three senses: it may mean either to have  knowledge of the

universal or  to have knowledge proper to the matter  in hand or to exercise such  knowledge: consequently

three kinds of  error also are possible.  Nothing then prevents a man both knowing  and being mistaken about

the  same thing, provided that his knowledge  and his error are not  contrary. And this happens also to the man

whose  knowledge is limited  to each of the premisses and who has not  previously considered the  particular

question. For when he thinks that  the mule is with foal he  has not the knowledge in the sense of its  actual

exercise, nor on the  other hand has his thought caused an error  contrary to his knowledge:  for the error

contrary to the knowledge  of the universal would be a  syllogism. 

But he who thinks the essence of good is the essence of bad will  think the same thing to be the essence of

good and the essence of bad.  Let A stand for the essence of good and B for the essence of bad,  and  again C

for the essence of good. Since then he thinks B and C  identical, he will think that C is B, and similarly that B

is A,  consequently that C is A. For just as we saw that if B is true of  all  of which C is true, and A is true of all

of which B is true, A  is true  of C, similarly with the word 'think'. Similarly also with the  word  'is'; for we saw

that if C is the same as B, and B as A, C is the  same  as A. Similarly therefore with 'opine'. Perhaps then this is

necessary  if a man will grant the first point. But presumably that  is false,  that any one could suppose the

essence of good to be the  essence of  bad, save incidentally. For it is possible to think this in  many  different

ways. But we must consider this matter better. 

22

Whenever the extremes are convertible it is necessary that the  middle should be convertible with both. For if

A belongs to C  through  B, then if A and C are convertible and C belongs everything to  which A  belongs, B is

convertible with A, and B belongs to  everything to which  A belongs, through C as middle, and C is

convertible with B through A  as middle. Similarly if the conclusion is  negative, e.g. if B belongs  to C, but A

does not belong to B,  neither will A belong to C. If then  B is convertible with A, C will be  convertible with

A. Suppose B does  not belong to A; neither then  will C: for ex hypothesi B belonged to  all C. And if C is

convertible with B, B is convertible also with A,  for C is said of  that of all of which B is said. And if C is

convertible in relation to  A and to B, B also is convertible in  relation to A. For C belongs to  that to which B

belongs: but C does  not belong to that to which A  belongs. And this alone starts from the  conclusion; the

preceding  moods do not do so as in the affirmative  syllogism. Again if A and B  are convertible, and similarly

C and D,  and if A or C must belong to  anything whatever, then B and D will be  such that one or other

belongs  to anything whatever. For since B  belongs to that to which A  belongs, and D belongs to that to which

C  belongs, and since A or C  belongs to everything, but not together, it  is clear that B or D  belongs to

everything, but not together. For  example if that which  is uncreated is incorruptible and that which is

incorruptible is  uncreated, it is necessary that what is created  should be  corruptible and what is corruptible

should have been  created. For  two syllogisms have been put together. Again if A or B  belongs to  everything

and if C or D belongs to everything, but they  cannot belong  together, then when A and C are convertible B


PRIOR ANALYTICS

22 56



Top




Page No 60


and D are  convertible.  For if B does not belong to something to which D belongs,  it is  clear that A belongs to

it. But if A then C: for they are  convertible.  Therefore C and D belong together. But this is  impossible. When

A  belongs to the whole of B and to C and is affirmed  of nothing else,  and B also belongs to all C, it is

necessary that A  and B should be  convertible: for since A is said of B and C only, and  B is affirmed  both of

itself and of C, it is clear that B will be said  of everything  of which A is said, except A itself. Again when A

and B  belong to  the whole of C, and C is convertible with B, it is necessary  that A  should belong to all B: for

since A belongs to all C, and C to  B by  conversion, A will belong to all B. 

When, of two opposites A and B, A is preferable to B, and  similarly D is preferable to C, then if A and C

together are  preferable to B and D together, A must be preferable to D. For A is an  object of desire to the

same extent as B is an object of aversion,  since they are opposites: and C is similarly related to D, since  they

also are opposites. If then A is an object of desire to the  same  extent as D, B is an object of aversion to the

same extent as C  (since  each is to the same extent as eachthe one an object of  aversion, the  other an object

of desire). Therefore both A and C  together, and B and  D together, will be equally objects of desire or

aversion. But since A  and C are preferable to B and D, A cannot be  equally desirable with D;  for then B

along with D would be equally  desirable with A along with  C. But if D is preferable to A, then B  must be less

an object of  aversion than C: for the less is opposed  to the less. But the greater  good and lesser evil are

preferable to  the lesser good and greater  evil: the whole BD then is preferable to  the whole AC. But ex

hypothesi this is not so. A then is preferable to  D, and C  consequently is less an object of aversion than B. If

then  every lover  in virtue of his love would prefer A, viz. that the  beloved should be  such as to grant a favour,

and yet should not  grant it (for which C  stands), to the beloved's granting the favour  (represented by D)

without being such as to grant it (represented by  B), it is clear that  A (being of such a nature) is preferable to

granting the favour. To  receive affection then is preferable in love  to sexual intercourse.  Love then is more

dependent on friendship  than on intercourse. And if  it is most dependent on receiving  affection, then this is its

end.  Intercourse then either is not an end  at all or is an end relative to  the further end, the receiving of

affection. And indeed the same is  true of the other desires and arts. 

23

It is clear then how the terms are related in conversion, and in  respect of being in a higher degree objects of

aversion or of  desire.  We must now state that not only dialectical and  demonstrative  syllogisms are formed by

means of the aforesaid figures,  but also  rhetorical syllogisms and in general any form of  persuasion, however

it may be presented. For every belief comes either  through syllogism  or from induction. 

Now induction, or rather the syllogism which springs out of  induction, consists in establishing syllogistically

a relation between  one extreme and the middle by means of the other extreme, e.g. if B is  the middle term

between A and C, it consists in proving through C that  A belongs to B. For this is the manner in which we

make inductions.  For example let A stand for longlived, B for bileless, and C for  the  particular longlived

animals, e.g. man, horse, mule. A then  belongs  to the whole of C: for whatever is bileless is longlived. But

B also  ('not possessing bile') belongs to all C. If then C is  convertible  with B, and the middle term is not

wider in extension,  it is necessary  that A should belong to B. For it has already been  proved that if two  things

belong to the same thing, and the extreme is  convertible with  one of them, then the other predicate will

belong  to the predicate  that is converted. But we must apprehend C as made up  of all the  particulars. For

induction proceeds through an  enumeration of all the  cases. 

Such is the syllogism which establishes the first and immediate  premiss: for where there is a middle term the

syllogism proceeds  through the middle term; when there is no middle term, through  induction. And in a way

induction is opposed to syllogism: for the  latter proves the major term to belong to the third term by means of

the middle, the former proves the major to belong to the middle by  means of the third. In the order of nature,

syllogism through the  middle term is prior and better known, but syllogism through induction  is clearer to us. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

23 57



Top




Page No 61


24

We have an 'example' when the major term is proved to belong to  the middle by means of a term which

resembles the third. It ought to  be known both that the middle belongs to the third term, and that  the  first

belongs to that which resembles the third. For example let A  be  evil, B making war against neighbours, C

Athenians against Thebans,  D  Thebans against Phocians. If then we wish to prove that to fight  with  the

Thebans is an evil, we must assume that to fight against  neighbours is an evil. Evidence of this is obtained

from similar  cases, e.g. that the war against the Phocians was an evil to the  Thebans. Since then to fight

against neighbours is an evil, and to  fight against the Thebans is to fight against neighbours, it is  clear  that to

fight against the Thebans is an evil. Now it is clear  that B  belongs to C and to D (for both are cases of making

war upon  one's  neighbours) and that A belongs to D (for the war against the  Phocians  did not turn out well

for the Thebans): but that A belongs to  B will  be proved through D. Similarly if the belief in the relation of

the  middle term to the extreme should be produced by several similar  cases. Clearly then to argue by example

is neither like reasoning from  part to whole, nor like reasoning from whole to part, but rather  reasoning from

part to part, when both particulars are subordinate  to  the same term, and one of them is known. It differs from

induction,  because induction starting from all the particular cases proves (as we  saw) that the major term

belongs to the middle, and does not apply the  syllogistic conclusion to the minor term, whereas argument by

example  does make this application and does not draw its proof from  all the  particular cases. 

25

By reduction we mean an argument in which the first term clearly  belongs to the middle, but the relation of

the middle to the last term  is uncertain though equally or more probable than the conclusion; or  again an

argument in which the terms intermediate between the last  term and the middle are few. For in any of these

cases it turns out  that we approach more nearly to knowledge. For example let A stand for  what can be

taught, B for knowledge, C for justice. Now it is clear  that knowledge can be taught: but it is uncertain

whether virtue is  knowledge. If now the statement BC is equally or more probable than  AC, we have a

reduction: for we are nearer to knowledge, since we have  taken a new term, being so far without knowledge

that A belongs to  C.  Or again suppose that the terms intermediate between B and C are  few:  for thus too we

are nearer knowledge. For example let D stand for  squaring, E for rectilinear figure, F for circle. If there were

only  one term intermediate between E and F (viz. that the circle is made  equal to a rectilinear figure by the

help of lunules), we should be  near to knowledge. But when BC is not more probable than AC, and the

intermediate terms are not few, I do not call this reduction: nor  again when the statement BC is immediate:

for such a statement is  knowledge. 

26

An objection is a premiss contrary to a premiss. It differs from a  premiss, because it may be particular, but a

premiss either cannot  be  particular at all or not in universal syllogisms. An objection is  brought in two ways

and through two figures; in two ways because every  objection is either universal or particular, by two figures

because  objections are brought in opposition to the premiss, and opposites can  be proved only in the first and

third figures. If a man maintains a  universal affirmative, we reply with a universal or a particular  negative;

the former is proved from the first figure, the latter  from  the third. For example let stand for there being a

single  science, B  for contraries. If a man premises that contraries are  subjects of a  single science, the

objection may be either that  opposites are never  subjects of a single science, and contraries are  opposites, so

that we  get the first figure, or that the knowable and  the unknowable are not  subjects of a single science: this

proof is  in the third figure: for  it is true of C (the knowable and the  unknowable) that they are  contraries, and

it is false that they are  the subjects of a single  science. 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

24 58



Top




Page No 62


Similarly if the premiss objected to is negative. For if a man  maintains that contraries are not subjects of a

single science, we  reply either that all opposites or that certain contraries, e.g.  what  is healthy and what is

sickly, are subjects of the same  science: the  former argument issues from the first, the latter from  the third

figure. 

In general if a man urges a universal objection he must frame his  contradiction with reference to the universal

of the terms taken by  his opponent, e.g. if a man maintains that contraries are not subjects  of the same

science, his opponent must reply that there is a single  science of all opposites. Thus we must have the first

figure: for  the  term which embraces the original subject becomes the middle term. 

If the objection is particular, the objector must frame his  contradiction with reference to a term relatively to

which the subject  of his opponent's premiss is universal, e.g. he will point out that  the knowable and the

unknowable are not subjects of the same  science:  'contraries' is universal relatively to these. And we have  the

third  figure: for the particular term assumed is middle, e.g.  the knowable  and the unknowable. Premisses

from which it is possible  to draw the  contrary conclusion are what we start from when we try  to make

objections. Consequently we bring objections in these  figures only:  for in them only are opposite syllogisms

possible, since  the second  figure cannot produce an affirmative conclusion. 

Besides, an objection in the middle figure would require a fuller  argument, e.g. if it should not be granted that

A belongs to B,  because C does not follow B. This can be made clear only by other  premisses. But an

objection ought not to turn off into other things,  but have its new premiss quite clear immediately. For this

reason also  this is the only figure from which proof by signs cannot be obtained. 

We must consider later the other kinds of objection, namely the  objection from contraries, from similars, and

from common opinion, and  inquire whether a particular objection cannot be elicited from the  first figure or a

negative objection from the second. 

27

A probability and a sign are not identical, but a probability is a  generally approved proposition: what men

know to happen or not to  happen, to be or not to be, for the most part thus and thus, is a  probability, e.g. 'the

envious hate', 'the beloved show affection'.  A  sign means a demonstrative proposition necessary or generally

approved: for anything such that when it is another thing is, or  when  it has come into being the other has

come into being before or  after,  is a sign of the other's being or having come into being. Now  an  enthymeme

is a syllogism starting from probabilities or signs,  and a  sign may be taken in three ways, corresponding to

the position  of the  middle term in the figures. For it may be taken as in the first  figure  or the second or the

third. For example the proof that a  woman is with  child because she has milk is in the first figure: for  to have

milk is  the middle term. Let A represent to be with child, B  to have milk, C  woman. The proof that wise men

are good, since  Pittacus is good, comes  through the last figure. Let A stand for good,  B for wise men, C for

Pittacus. It is true then to affirm both A and B  of C: only men do not  say the latter, because they know it,

though  they state the former.  The proof that a woman is with child because  she is pale is meant to  come

through the middle figure: for since  paleness follows women with  child and is a concomitant of this  woman,

people suppose it has been  proved that she is with child. Let A  stand for paleness, B for being  with child, C

for woman. Now if the  one proposition is stated, we have  only a sign, but if the other is  stated as well, a

syllogism, e.g.  'Pittacus is generous, since  ambitious men are generous and Pittacus  is ambitious.' Or again

'Wise men are good, since Pittacus is not only  good but wise.' In this  way then syllogisms are formed, only

that  which proceeds through the  first figure is irrefutable if it is true  (for it is universal),  that which proceeds

through the last figure is  refutable even if the  conclusion is true, since the syllogism is not  universal nor

correlative to the matter in question: for though  Pittacus is good, it  is not therefore necessary that all other

wise  men should be good. But  the syllogism which proceeds through the  middle figure is always  refutable in


PRIOR ANALYTICS

27 59



Top




Page No 63


any case: for a syllogism can  never be formed when the  terms are related in this way: for though a  woman

with child is  pale, and this woman also is pale, it is not  necessary that she should  be with child. Truth then

may be found in  signs whatever their kind,  but they have the differences we have  stated. 

We must either divide signs in the way stated, and among them  designate the middle term as the index (for

people call that the index  which makes us know, and the middle term above all has this  character), or else we

must call the arguments derived from the  extremes signs, that derived from the middle term the index: for  that

which is proved through the first figure is most generally  accepted  and most true. 

It is possible to infer character from features, if it is granted  that the body and the soul are changed together

by the natural  affections: I say 'natural', for though perhaps by learning music a  man has made some change

in his soul, this is not one of those  affections which are natural to us; rather I refer to passions and  desires

when I speak of natural emotions. If then this were granted  and also that for each change there is a

corresponding sign, and we  could state the affection and sign proper to each kind of animal, we  shall be able

to infer character from features. For if there is an  affection which belongs properly to an individual kind, e.g.

courage  to lions, it is necessary that there should be a sign of it: for ex  hypothesi body and soul are affected

together. Suppose this sign is  the possession of large extremities: this may belong to other kinds  also though

not universally. For the sign is proper in the sense  stated, because the affection is proper to the whole kind,

though  not  proper to it alone, according to our usual manner of speaking. The  same thing then will be found

in another kind, and man may be brave,  and some other kinds of animal as well. They will then have the  sign:

for ex hypothesi there is one sign corresponding to each  affection. If  then this is so, and we can collect signs

of this sort  in these  animals which have only one affection proper to thembut each  affection has its sign,

since it is necessary that it should have a  single signwe shall then be able to infer character from features.

But if the kind as a whole has two properties, e.g. if the lion is  both brave and generous, how shall we know

which of the signs which  are its proper concomitants is the sign of a particular affection?  Perhaps if both

belong to some other kind though not to the whole of  it, and if, in those kinds in which each is found though

not in the  whole of their members, some members possess one of the affections and  not the other: e.g. if a

man is brave but not generous, but possesses,  of the two signs, large extremities, it is clear that this is the sign

of courage in the lion also. To judge character from features, then,  is possible in the first figure if the middle

term is convertible with  the first extreme, but is wider than the third term and not  convertible with it: e.g. let

A stand for courage, B for large  extremities, and C for lion. B then belongs to everything to which C  belongs,

but also to others. But A belongs to everything to which B  belongs, and to nothing besides, but is convertible

with B: otherwise,  there would not be a single sign correlative with each affection. 

THE END 


PRIOR ANALYTICS

27 60



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. PRIOR ANALYTICS, page = 5

   3. by Aristotle, page = 5

4.  Book I, page = 6

   5.  1, page = 6

   6.  2, page = 7

   7.  3, page = 8

   8.  4, page = 8

   9.  5, page = 10

   10.  6, page = 11

   11.  7, page = 13

   12.  8, page = 13

   13.  9, page = 14

   14.  10, page = 14

   15.  11, page = 15

   16.  12, page = 16

   17.  13, page = 16

   18.  14, page = 17

   19.  15, page = 18

   20.  16, page = 20

   21.  17, page = 22

   22.  18, page = 23

   23.  19, page = 23

   24.  20, page = 24

   25.  21, page = 25

   26.  22, page = 25

   27.  23, page = 26

   28.  24, page = 27

   29.  25, page = 28

   30.  26, page = 29

   31.  27, page = 29

   32.  28, page = 30

   33.  29, page = 32

   34.  30, page = 33

   35.  31, page = 33

   36.  32, page = 34

   37.  33, page = 35

   38.  34, page = 35

   39.  35, page = 36

   40.  36, page = 36

   41.  37, page = 37

   42.  38, page = 37

   43.  39, page = 38

   44.  40, page = 38

   45.  41, page = 38

   46.  42, page = 38

   47.  43, page = 38

   48.  44, page = 39

   49.  45, page = 39

   50.  46, page = 40

51.  Book II, page = 42

   52.  1, page = 42

   53.  2, page = 43

   54.  3, page = 45

   55.  4, page = 46

   56.  5, page = 48

   57.  6, page = 49

   58.  7, page = 49

   59.  8, page = 50

   60.  9, page = 50

   61.  10, page = 51

   62.  11, page = 52

   63.  12, page = 53

   64.  13, page = 54

   65.  14, page = 54

   66.  15, page = 55

   67.  16, page = 56

   68.  17, page = 57

   69.  18, page = 58

   70.  19, page = 58

   71.  20, page = 59

   72.  22, page = 60

   73.  23, page = 61

   74.  24, page = 62

   75.  25, page = 62

   76.  26, page = 62

   77.  27, page = 63