Title:   ON INTERPRETATION

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Bookmarks





Page No 1


ON INTERPRETATION

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

ON INTERPRETATION...................................................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

1..............................................................................................................................................................1

2..............................................................................................................................................................1

3..............................................................................................................................................................2

4..............................................................................................................................................................2

5..............................................................................................................................................................3

6..............................................................................................................................................................3

7..............................................................................................................................................................4

8..............................................................................................................................................................5

9..............................................................................................................................................................5

10............................................................................................................................................................7

11............................................................................................................................................................9

12..........................................................................................................................................................11

13..........................................................................................................................................................12

14..........................................................................................................................................................14


ON INTERPRETATION

i



Top




Page No 3


ON INTERPRETATION

by Aristotle

translated by E. M. Edghill

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14  

1

First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms  'denial' and 'affirmation', then 'proposition' and

'sentence.' 

Spoken words are the symbols of mental experience and written  words are the symbols of spoken words. Just

as all men have not the  same writing, so all men have not the same speech sounds, but the  mental

experiences, which these directly symbolize, are the same for  all, as also are those things of which our

experiences are the images.  This matter has, however, been discussed in my treatise about the  soul, for it

belongs to an investigation distinct from that which lies  before us. 

As there are in the mind thoughts which do not involve truth or  falsity, and also those which must be either

true or false, so it is  in speech. For truth and falsity imply combination and separation.  Nouns and verbs,

provided nothing is added, are like thoughts  without  combination or separation; 'man' and 'white', as isolated

terms, are  not yet either true or false. In proof of this, consider  the word  'goatstag.' It has significance, but

there is no truth or  falsity  about it, unless 'is' or 'is not' is added, either in the  present or  in some other tense. 

2

By a noun we mean a sound significant by convention, which has no  reference to time, and of which no part

is significant apart from  the  rest. In the noun 'Fairsteed,' the part 'steed' has no  significance in  and by itself, as

ON INTERPRETATION 1



Top




Page No 4


in the phrase 'fair steed.' Yet  there is a  difference between simple and composite nouns; for in the  former the

part is in no way significant, in the latter it contributes  to the  meaning of the whole, although it has not an

independent  meaning. Thus  in the word 'pirateboat' the word 'boat' has no meaning  except as  part of the

whole word. 

The limitation 'by convention' was introduced because nothing is  by nature a noun or nameit is only so

when it becomes a symbol;  inarticulate sounds, such as those which brutes produce, are  significant, yet none

of these constitutes a noun. 

The expression 'notman' is not a noun. There is indeed no  recognized term by which we may denote such an

expression, for it is  not a sentence or a denial. Let it then be called an indefinite noun. 

The expressions 'of Philo', 'to Philo', and so on, constitute not  nouns, but cases of a noun. The definition of

these cases of a noun is  in other respects the same as that of the noun proper, but, when  coupled with 'is',

'was', or will be', they do not, as they are,  form  a proposition either true or false, and this the noun proper

always  does, under these conditions. Take the words 'of Philo is' or  'of or  'of Philo is not'; these words do not,

as they stand, form  either a  true or a false proposition. 

3

A verb is that which, in addition to its proper meaning, carries  with it the notion of time. No part of it has any

independent meaning,  and it is a sign of something said of something else. 

I will explain what I mean by saying that it carries with it the  notion of time. 'Health' is a noun, but 'is healthy'

is a verb; for  besides its proper meaning it indicates the present existence of the  state in question. 

Moreover, a verb is always a sign of something said of something  else, i.e. of something either predicable of

or present in some  other  thing. 

Such expressions as 'is nothealthy', 'is not, ill', I do not  describe as verbs; for though they carry the

additional note of  time,  and always form a predicate, there is no specified name for this  variety; but let them

be called indefinite verbs, since they apply  equally well to that which exists and to that which does not. 

Similarly 'he was healthy', 'he will be healthy', are not verbs,  but  tenses of a verb; the difference lies in the

fact that the verb  indicates present time, while the tenses of the verb indicate those  times which lie outside the

present. 

Verbs in and by themselves are substantival and have significance,  for he who uses such expressions arrests

the hearer's mind, and  fixes  his attention; but they do not, as they stand, express any  judgement,  either

positive or negative. For neither are 'to be' and  'not to be'  the participle 'being' significant of any fact, unless

something is  added; for they do not themselves indicate anything,  but imply a  copulation, of which we cannot

form a conception apart  from the things  coupled. 

4

A sentence is a significant portion of speech, some parts of which  have an independent meaning, that is to

say, as an utterance, though  not as the expression of any positive judgement. Let me explain. The  word

'human' has meaning, but does not constitute a proposition,  either positive or negative. It is only when other

words are added  that the whole will form an affirmation or denial. But if we  separate  one syllable of the word

'human' from the other, it has no  meaning;  similarly in the word 'mouse', the part 'ouse' has no meaning  in


ON INTERPRETATION

3 2



Top




Page No 5


itself, but is merely a sound. In composite words, indeed, the  parts  contribute to the meaning of the whole;

yet, as has been pointed  out,  they have not an independent meaning. 

Every sentence has meaning, not as being the natural means by  which a physical faculty is realized, but, as

we have said, by  convention. Yet every sentence is not a proposition; only such are  propositions as have in

them either truth or falsity. Thus a prayer is  a sentence, but is neither true nor false. 

Let us therefore dismiss all other types of sentence but the  proposition, for this last concerns our present

inquiry, whereas the  investigation of the others belongs rather to the study of rhetoric or  of poetry. 

5

The first class of simple propositions is the simple affirmation,  the next, the simple denial; all others are only

one by conjunction. 

Every proposition must contain a verb or the tense of a verb. The  phrase which defines the species 'man', if no

verb in present, past,  or future time be added, is not a proposition. It may be asked how the  expression 'a

footed animal with two feet' can be called single; for  it is not the circumstance that the words follow in

unbroken  succession that effects the unity. This inquiry, however, finds its  place in an investigation foreign to

that before us. 

We call those propositions single which indicate a single fact, or  the conjunction of the parts of which results

in unity: those  propositions, on the other hand, are separate and many in number,  which indicate many facts,

or whose parts have no conjunction. 

Let us, moreover, consent to call a noun or a verb an expression  only, and not a proposition, since it is not

possible for a man to  speak in this way when he is expressing something, in such a way as to  make a

statement, whether his utterance is an answer to a question  or  an act of his own initiation. 

To return: of propositions one kind is simple, i.e. that which  asserts or denies something of something, the

other composite, i.e.  that which is compounded of simple propositions. A simple  proposition  is a statement,

with meaning, as to the presence of  something in a  subject or its absence, in the present, past, or  future,

according to  the divisions of time. 

6

An affirmation is a positive assertion of something about  something,  a denial a negative assertion. 

Now it is possible both to affirm and to deny the presence of  something which is present or of something

which is not, and since  these same affirmations and denials are possible with reference to  those times which

lie outside the present, it would be possible to  contradict any affirmation or denial. Thus it is plain that every

affirmation has an opposite denial, and similarly every denial an  opposite affirmation. 

We will call such a pair of propositions a pair of  contradictories. Those positive and negative propositions are

said  to  be contradictory which have the same subject and predicate. The  identity of subject and of predicate

must not be 'equivocal'. Indeed  there are definitive qualifications besides this, which we make to  meet the

casuistries of sophists. 


ON INTERPRETATION

5 3



Top




Page No 6


7

Some things are universal, others individual. By the term  'universal' I mean that which is of such a nature as

to be  predicated  of many subjects, by 'individual' that which is not thus  predicated.  Thus 'man' is a universal,

'Callias' an individual. 

Our propositions necessarily sometimes concern a universal  subject, sometimes an individual. 

If, then, a man states a positive and a negative proposition of  universal character with regard to a universal,

these two propositions  are 'contrary'. By the expression 'a proposition of universal  character with regard to a

universal', such propositions as 'every man  is white', 'no man is white' are meant. When, on the other hand,

the  positive and negative propositions, though they have regard to a  universal, are yet not of universal

character, they will not be  contrary, albeit the meaning intended is sometimes contrary. As  instances of

propositions made with regard to a universal, but not  of  universal character, we may take the 'propositions

'man is  white',  'man is not white'. 'Man' is a universal, but the  proposition is not  made as of universal

character; for the word  'every' does not make the  subject a universal, but rather gives the  proposition a

universal  character. If, however, both predicate and  subject are distributed,  the proposition thus constituted is

contrary to truth; no affirmation  will, under such circumstances, be  true. The proposition 'every man is  every

animal' is an example of  this type. 

An affirmation is opposed to a denial in the sense which I denote  by  the term 'contradictory', when, while the

subject remains the same,  the affirmation is of universal character and the denial is not. The  affirmation

'every man is white' is the contradictory of the denial  'not every man is white', or again, the proposition 'no

man is  white'  is the contradictory of the proposition 'some men are white'.  But  propositions are opposed as

contraries when both the affirmation  and  the denial are universal, as in the sentences 'every man is  white',  'no

man is white', 'every man is just', 'no man is just'. 

We see that in a pair of this sort both propositions cannot be  true,  but the contradictories of a pair of

contraries can sometimes  both  be true with reference to the same subject; for instance 'not  every  man is white'

and some men are white' are both true. Of such  corresponding positive and negative propositions as refer to

universals and have a universal character, one must be true and the  other false. This is the case also when the

reference is to  individuals, as in the propositions 'Socrates is white', 'Socrates  is  not white'. 

When, on the other hand, the reference is to universals, but the  propositions are not universal, it is not always

the case that one  is  true and the other false, for it is possible to state truly that  man  is white and that man is

not white and that man is beautiful and  that  man is not beautiful; for if a man is deformed he is the  reverse of

beautiful, also if he is progressing towards beauty he is  not yet  beautiful. 

This statement might seem at first sight to carry with it a  contradiction, owing to the fact that the proposition

'man is not  white' appears to be equivalent to the proposition 'no man is  white'.  This, however, is not the case,

nor are they necessarily at  the same  time true or false. 

It is evident also that the denial corresponding to a single  affirmation is itself single; for the denial must deny

just that which  the affirmation affirms concerning the same subject, and must  correspond with the affirmation

both in the universal or particular  character of the subject and in the distributed or undistributed sense  in

which it is understood. 

For instance, the affirmation 'Socrates is white' has its proper  denial in the proposition 'Socrates is not white'.

If anything else be  negatively predicated of the subject or if anything else be the  subject though the predicate

remain the same, the denial will not be  the denial proper to that affirmation, but on that is distinct. 


ON INTERPRETATION

7 4



Top




Page No 7


The denial proper to the affirmation 'every man is white' is 'not  every man is white'; that proper to the

affirmation 'some men are  white' is 'no man is white', while that proper to the affirmation 'man  is white' is

'man is not white'. 

We have shown further that a single denial is contradictorily  opposite to a single affirmation and we have

explained which these  are; we have also stated that contrary are distinct from contradictory  propositions and

which the contrary are; also that with regard to a  pair of opposite propositions it is not always the case that

one is  true and the other false. We have pointed out, moreover, what the  reason of this is and under what

circumstances the truth of the one  involves the falsity of the other. 

8

An affirmation or denial is single, if it indicates some one fact  about some one subject; it matters not whether

the subject is  universal and whether the statement has a universal character, or  whether this is not so. Such

single propositions are: 'every man is  white', 'not every man is white';'man is white','man is not white';  'no

man is white', 'some men are white'; provided the word 'white' has  one meaning. If, on the other hand, one

word has two meanings which do  not combine to form one, the affirmation is not single. For  instance,  if a

man should establish the symbol 'garment' as  significant both of  a horse and of a man, the proposition

'garment  is white' would not be  a single affirmation, nor its opposite a single  denial. For it is  equivalent to the

proposition 'horse and man are  white', which, again,  is equivalent to the two propositions 'horse  is white',

'man is  white'. If, then, these two propositions have  more than a single  significance, and do not form a single

proposition,  it is plain that  the first proposition either has more than one  significance or else  has none; for a

particular man is not a horse. 

This, then, is another instance of those propositions of which  both the positive and the negative forms may be

true or false  simultaneously. 

9

In the case of that which is or which has taken place,  propositions,  whether positive or negative, must be true

or false.  Again, in the  case of a pair of contradictories, either when the  subject is  universal and the

propositions are of a universal  character, or when  it is individual, as has been said,' one of the two  must be

true and  the other false; whereas when the subject is  universal, but the  propositions are not of a universal

character,  there is no such  necessity. We have discussed this type also in a  previous chapter. 

When the subject, however, is individual, and that which is  predicated of it relates to the future, the case is

altered. For if  all propositions whether positive or negative are either true or  false, then any given predicate

must either belong to the subject or  not, so that if one man affirms that an event of a given character  will take

place and another denies it, it is plain that the  statement  of the one will correspond with reality and that of the

other will  not. For the predicate cannot both belong and not belong to  the  subject at one and the same time

with regard to the future. 

Thus, if it is true to say that a thing is white, it must  necessarily be white; if the reverse proposition is true, it

will of  necessity not be white. Again, if it is white, the proposition stating  that it is white was true; if it is not

white, the proposition to  the  opposite effect was true. And if it is not white, the man who  states  that it is

making a false statement; and if the man who  states that it  is white is making a false statement, it follows that

it is not white.  It may therefore be argued that it is necessary  that affirmations or  denials must be either true

or false. 


ON INTERPRETATION

8 5



Top




Page No 8


Now if this be so, nothing is or takes place fortuitously, either  in  the present or in the future, and there are no

real alternatives;  everything takes place of necessity and is fixed. For either he that  affirms that it will take

place or he that denies this is in  correspondence with fact, whereas if things did not take place of  necessity, an

event might just as easily not happen as happen; for the  meaning of the word 'fortuitous' with regard to

present or future  events is that reality is so constituted that it may issue in either  of two opposite directions.

Again, if a thing is white now, it was  true before to say that it would be white, so that of anything that  has

taken place it was always true to say 'it is' or 'it will be'. But  if it was always true to say that a thing is or will

be, it is not  possible that it should not be or not be about to be, and when a thing  cannot not come to be, it is

impossible that it should not come to be,  and when it is impossible that it should not come to be, it must  come

to be. All, then, that is about to be must of necessity take  place. It  results from this that nothing is uncertain or

fortuitous,  for if it  were fortuitous it would not be necessary. 

Again, to say that neither the affirmation nor the denial is true,  maintaining, let us say, that an event neither

will take place nor  will not take place, is to take up a position impossible to defend. In  the first place, though

facts should prove the one proposition  false,  the opposite would still be untrue. Secondly, if it was true to  say

that a thing was both white and large, both these qualities must  necessarily belong to it; and if they will

belong to it the next  day,  they must necessarily belong to it the next day. But if an  event is  neither to take

place nor not to take place the next day, the  element  of chance will be eliminated. For example, it would be

necessary that  a seafight should neither take place nor fail to  take place on the  next day. 

These awkward results and others of the same kind follow, if it is  an irrefragable law that of every pair of

contradictory  propositions,  whether they have regard to universals and are stated as  universally  applicable, or

whether they have regard to individuals,  one must be  true and the other false, and that there are no real

alternatives, but  that all that is or takes place is the outcome of  necessity. There  would be no need to

deliberate or to take trouble, on  the supposition  that if we should adopt a certain course, a certain  result would

follow, while, if we did not, the result would not  follow. For a man  may predict an event ten thousand years

beforehand, and another may  predict the reverse; that which was  truly predicted at the moment in  the past

will of necessity take place  in the fullness of time. 

Further, it makes no difference whether people have or have not  actually made the contradictory statements.

For it is manifest that  the circumstances are not influenced by the fact of an affirmation  or  denial on the part

of anyone. For events will not take place or  fail  to take place because it was stated that they would or would

not take  place, nor is this any more the case if the prediction  dates back ten  thousand years or any other space

of time. Wherefore,  if through all  time the nature of things was so constituted that a  prediction about  an event

was true, then through all time it was  necessary that that  should find fulfillment; and with regard to all  events,

circumstances  have always been such that their occurrence is a  matter of necessity.  For that of which

someone has said truly that  it will be, cannot fail  to take place; and of that which takes  place, it was always

true to  say that it would be. 

Yet this view leads to an impossible conclusion; for we see that  both deliberation and action are causative

with regard to the  future,  and that, to speak more generally, in those things which are  not  continuously actual

there is potentiality in either direction.  Such  things may either be or not be; events also therefore may  either

take  place or not take place. There are many obvious  instances of this. It  is possible that this coat may be cut

in half,  and yet it may not be  cut in half, but wear out first. In the same  way, it is possible that  it should not be

cut in half; unless this  were so, it would not be  possible that it should wear out first. So it  is therefore with all

other events which possess this kind of  potentiality. It is therefore  plain that it is not of necessity that

everything is or takes place;  but in some instances there are real  alternatives, in which case the  affirmation is

no more true and no  more false than the denial; while  some exhibit a predisposition and  general tendency in

one direction or  the other, and yet can issue in  the opposite direction by exception. 


ON INTERPRETATION

8 6



Top




Page No 9


Now that which is must needs be when it is, and that which is not  must needs not be when it is not. Yet it

cannot be said without  qualification that all existence and nonexistence is the outcome of  necessity. For

there is a difference between saying that that which  is, when it is, must needs be, and simply saying that all

that is must  needs be, and similarly in the case of that which is not. In the case,  also, of two contradictory

propositions this holds good. Everything  must either be or not be, whether in the present or in the future, but

it is not always possible to distinguish and state determinately which  of these alternatives must necessarily

come about. 

Let me illustrate. A seafight must either take place tomorrow or  not, but it is not necessary that it should

take place tomorrow,  neither is it necessary that it should not take place, yet it is  necessary that it either

should or should not take place tomorrow.  Since propositions correspond with facts, it is evident that when

in  future events there is a real alternative, and a potentiality in  contrary directions, the corresponding

affirmation and denial have the  same character. 

This is the case with regard to that which is not always existent  or  not always nonexistent. One of the two

propositions in such  instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say  determinately that this or

that is false, but must leave the  alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true than  the

other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually false. It  is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of

an affirmation and  a denial one should be true and the other false. For in the case of  that which exists

potentially, but not actually, the rule which  applies to that which exists actually does not hold good. The case

is  rather as we have indicated. 

10

An affirmation is the statement of a fact with regard to a  subject, and this subject is either a noun or that

which has no  name;  the subject and predicate in an affirmation must each denote a  single  thing. I have

already explained' what is meant by a noun and by  that  which has no name; for I stated that the expression

'notman' was  not  a noun, in the proper sense of the word, but an indefinite noun,  denoting as it does in a

certain sense a single thing. Similarly the  expression 'does not enjoy health' is not a verb proper, but an

indefinite verb. Every affirmation, then, and every denial, will  consist of a noun and a verb, either definite or

indefinite. 

There can be no affirmation or denial without a verb; for the  expressions 'is', 'will be', 'was', 'is coming to be',

and the like  are verbs according to our definition, since besides their specific  meaning they convey the notion

of time. Thus the primary affirmation  and denial are 'as follows: 'man is', 'man is not'. Next to these,  there are

the propositions: 'notman is', 'notman is not'. Again we  have the propositions: 'every man is, 'every man is

not', 'all that is  notman is', 'all that is notman is not'. The same classification  holds good with regard to such

periods of time as lie outside the  present. 

When the verb 'is' is used as a third element in the sentence,  there  can be positive and negative propositions

of two sorts. Thus in  the  sentence 'man is just' the verb 'is' is used as a third element,  call it verb or noun,

which you will. Four propositions, therefore,  instead of two can be formed with these materials. Two of the

four, as  regards their affirmation and denial, correspond in their logical  sequence with the propositions which

deal with a condition of  privation; the other two do not correspond with these. 

I mean that the verb 'is' is added either to the term 'just' or to  the term 'notjust', and two negative

propositions are formed in the  same way. Thus we have the four propositions. Reference to the  subjoined

table will make matters clear: 

           A. Affirmation        B. Denial


ON INTERPRETATION

10 7



Top




Page No 10


Man is just       Man is not just

                          \   /

                            X

                          /   \

           D. Denial             C. Affirmation

         Man is not notjust     Man is notjust

Here 'is' and 'is not' are added either to 'just' or to 'notjust'.  This then is the proper scheme for these

propositions, as has been  said in the Analytics. The same rule holds good, if the subject is  distributed. Thus

we have the table: 

       A'. Affirmation               B'. Denial

      Every man is just           Not every man is just

                           \   /

                             X

       D'. Denial          /   \     C'. Affirmation

Not every man is notjust  Every man is notjust  Yet here it is  not possible, in the same way as in the former

case,  that the  propositions joined in the table by a diagonal line should  both be  true; though under certain

circumstances this is the case. 

We have thus set out two pairs of opposite propositions; there are  moreover two other pairs, if a term be

conjoined with 'notman', the  latter forming a kind of subject. Thus: 

            A."                            B."

      Notman is just               Notman is not just

                             \   /

                              X

            D."              /   \         C."

      Notman is not notjust       Notman is notjust

This is an exhaustive enumeration of all the pairs of opposite  propositions that can possibly be framed. This

last group should  remain distinct from those which preceded it, since it employs as  its  subject the expression

'notman'. 

When the verb 'is' does not fit the structure of the sentence (for  instance, when the verbs 'walks', 'enjoys

health' are used), that  scheme applies, which applied when the word 'is' was added. 

Thus we have the propositions: 'every man enjoys health', 'every  man  doesnotenjoyhealth', 'all that is

notman enjoys health', 'all  that  is notman doesnotenjoyhealth'. We must not in these  propositions  use

the expression 'not every man'. The negative must be  attached to  the word 'man', for the word 'every' does not

give to the  subject a  universal significance, but implies that, as a subject, it  is  distributed. This is plain from

the following pairs: 'man enjoys  health', 'man does not enjoy health'; 'notman enjoys health', 'not  man does

not enjoy health'. These propositions differ from the  former  in being indefinite and not universal in character.

Thus the  adjectives 'every' and no additional significance except that the  subject, whether in a positive or in a

negative sentence, is  distributed. The rest of the sentence, therefore, will in each case be  the same. 

Since the contrary of the proposition 'every animal is just' is  'no animal is just', it is plain that these two

propositions will  never both be true at the same time or with reference to the same  subject. Sometimes,

however, the contradictories of these contraries  will both be true, as in the instance before us: the propositions

'not  every animal is just' and 'some animals are just' are both true. 


ON INTERPRETATION

10 8



Top




Page No 11


Further, the proposition 'no man is just' follows from the  proposition 'every man is not just' and the

proposition 'not every man  is not just', which is the opposite of 'every man is notjust',  follows from the

proposition 'some men are just'; for if this be true,  there must be some just men. 

It is evident, also, that when the subject is individual, if a  question is asked and the negative answer is the true

one, a certain  positive proposition is also true. Thus, if the question were asked  Socrates wise?' and the

negative answer were the true one, the  positive inference 'Then Socrates is unwise' is correct. But no such

inference is correct in the case of universals, but rather a  negative  proposition. For instance, if to the question

'Is every man  wise?' the  answer is 'no', the inference 'Then every man is unwise' is  false. But  under these

circumstances the inference 'Not every man is  wise' is  correct. This last is the contradictory, the former the

contrary.  Negative expressions, which consist of an indefinite noun or  predicate, such as 'notman' or

'notjust', may seem to be denials  containing neither noun nor verb in the proper sense of the words. But  they

are not. For a denial must always be either true or false, and he  that uses the expression 'not man', if nothing

more be added, is not  nearer but rather further from making a true or a false statement than  he who uses the

expression 'man'. 

The propositions 'everything that is not man is just', and the  contradictory of this, are not equivalent to any of

the other  propositions; on the other hand, the proposition 'everything that is  not man is not just' is equivalent

to the proposition 'nothing that is  not man is just'. 

The conversion of the position of subject and predicate in a  sentence involves no difference in its meaning.

Thus we say 'man is  white' and 'white is man'. If these were not equivalent, there would  be more than one

contradictory to the same proposition, whereas it has  been demonstrated' that each proposition has one proper

contradictory  and one only. For of the proposition 'man is white'  the appropriate  contradictory is 'man is not

white', and of the  proposition 'white is  man', if its meaning be different, the  contradictory will either be  'white

is not notman' or 'white is not  man'. Now the former of these  is the contradictory of the  proposition 'white is

notman', and the  latter of these is the  contradictory of the proposition 'man is  white'; thus there will be  two

contradictories to one proposition. 

It is evident, therefore, that the inversion of the relative  position of subject and predicate does not affect the

sense of  affirmations and denials. 

11

There is no unity about an affirmation or denial which, either  positively or negatively, predicates one thing of

many subjects, or  many things of the same subject, unless that which is indicated by the  many is really some

one thing. do not apply this word 'one' to those  things which, though they have a single recognized name, yet

do not  combine to form a unity. Thus, man may be an animal, and biped, and  domesticated, but these three

predicates combine to form a unity. On  the other hand, the predicates 'white', 'man', and 'walking' do not  thus

combine. Neither, therefore, if these three form the subject of  an affirmation, nor if they form its predicate, is

there any unity  about that affirmation. In both cases the unity is linguistic, but not  real. 

If therefore the dialectical question is a request for an answer,  i.e. either for the admission of a premiss or for

the admission of one  of two contradictoriesand the premiss is itself always one of two  contradictoriesthe

answer to such a question as contains the above  predicates cannot be a single proposition. For as I have

explained  in  the Topics, question is not a single one, even if the answer  asked for  is true. 

At the same time it is plain that a question of the form 'what is  it?' is not a dialectical question, for a

dialectical questioner  must  by the form of his question give his opponent the chance of  announcing  one of

two alternatives, whichever he wishes. He must  therefore put  the question into a more definite form, and


ON INTERPRETATION

11 9



Top




Page No 12


inquire,  e.g.. whether man  has such and such a characteristic or not. 

Some combinations of predicates are such that the separate  predicates unite to form a single predicate. Let us

consider under  what conditions this is and is not possible. We may either state in  two separate propositions

that man is an animal and that man is a  biped, or we may combine the two, and state that man is an animal

with  two feet. Similarly we may use 'man' and 'white' as separate  predicates, or unite them into one. Yet if a

man is a shoemaker and is  also good, we cannot construct a composite proposition and say that he  is a good

shoemaker. For if, whenever two separate predicates truly  belong to a subject, it follows that the predicate

resulting from  their combination also truly belongs to the subject, many absurd  results ensue. For instance, a

man is man and white. Therefore, if  predicates may always be combined, he is a white man. Again, if the

predicate 'white' belongs to him, then the combination of that  predicate with the former composite predicate

will be permissible.  Thus it will be right to say that he is a white man so on  indefinitely. Or, again, we may

combine the predicates 'musical',  'white', and 'walking', and these may be combined many times.  Similarly we

may say that Socrates is Socrates and a man, and that  therefore he is the man Socrates, or that Socrates is a

man and a  biped, and that therefore he is a twofooted man. Thus it is  manifest  that if man states

unconditionally that predicates can always  be  combined, many absurd consequences ensue. 

We will now explain what ought to be laid down. 

Those predicates, and terms forming the subject of predication,  which are accidental either to the same

subject or to one another,  do  not combine to form a unity. Take the proposition 'man is white  of  complexion

and musical'. Whiteness and being musical do not  coalesce  to form a unity, for they belong only accidentally

to the  same  subject. Nor yet, if it were true to say that that which is white  is  musical, would the terms

'musical' and 'white' form a unity, for it  is  only incidentally that that which is musical is white; the

combination  of the two will, therefore, not form a unity. 

Thus, again, whereas, if a man is both good and a shoemaker, we  cannot combine the two propositions and

say simply that he is a good  shoemaker, we are, at the same time, able to combine the predicates  'animal' and

'biped' and say that a man is an animal with two feet,  for these predicates are not accidental. 

Those predicates, again, cannot form a unity, of which the one is  implicit in the other: thus we cannot

combine the predicate 'white'  again and again with that which already contains the notion 'white',  nor is it

right to call a man an animalman or a twofooted man; for  the notions 'animal' and 'biped' are implicit in the

word 'man'. On  the other hand, it is possible to predicate a term simply of any one  instance, and to say that

some one particular man is a man or that  some one white man is a white man. 

Yet this is not always possible: indeed, when in the adjunct there  is some opposite which involves a

contradiction, the predication of  the simple term is impossible. Thus it is not right to call a dead man  a man.

When, however, this is not the case, it is not impossible. 

Yet the facts of the case might rather be stated thus: when some  such opposite elements are present,

resolution is never possible,  but  when they are not present, resolution is nevertheless not always  possible.

Take the proposition 'Homer is soandso', say 'a poet';  does it follow that Homer is, or does it not? The verb

'is' is here  used of Homer only incidentally, the proposition being that Homer is a  poet, not that he is, in the

independent sense of the word. 

Thus, in the case of those predications which have within them no  contradiction when the nouns are

expanded into definitions, and  wherein the predicates belong to the subject in their own proper sense  and not

in any indirect way, the individual may be the subject of  the  simple propositions as well as of the composite.

But in the case  of  that which is not, it is not true to say that because it is the  object  of opinion, it is; for the

opinion held about it is that it  is not,  not that it is. 


ON INTERPRETATION

11 10



Top




Page No 13


12

As these distinctions have been made, we must consider the mutual  relation of those affirmations and denials

which assert or deny  possibility or contingency, impossibility or necessity: for the  subject is not without

difficulty. 

We admit that of composite expressions those are contradictory  each to each which have the verb 'to be' its

positive and negative  form respectively. Thus the contradictory of the proposition 'man  is'  is 'man is not', not

'notman is', and the contradictory of 'man  is  white' is 'man is not white', not 'man is notwhite'. For

otherwise,  since either the positive or the negative proposition is  true of any  subject, it will turn out true to

say that a piece of wood  is a man  that is not white. 

Now if this is the case, in those propositions which do not  contain the verb 'to be' the verb which takes its

place will  exercise  the same function. Thus the contradictory of 'man walks' is  'man does  not walk', not

'notman walks'; for to say 'man walks'  merely  equivalent to saying 'man is walking'. 

If then this rule is universal, the contradictory of 'it may be'  is may not be', not 'it cannot be'. 

Now it appears that the same thing both may and may not be; for  instance, everything that may be cut or may

walk may also escape  cutting and refrain from walking; and the reason is that those  things  that have

potentiality in this sense are not always actual.  In such  cases, both the positive and the negative propositions

will be  true;  for that which is capable of walking or of being seen has also a  potentiality in the opposite

direction. 

But since it is impossible that contradictory propositions should  both be true of the same subject, it follows

that' it may not be' is  not the contradictory of 'it may be'. For it is a logical  consequence  of what we have said,

either that the same predicate can  be both  applicable and inapplicable to one and the same subject at the  same

time, or that it is not by the addition of the verbs 'be' and  'not  be', respectively, that positive and negative

propositions are  formed.  If the former of these alternatives must be rejected, we  must choose  the latter. 

The contradictory, then, of 'it may be' is 'it cannot be'. The  same rule applies to the proposition 'it is

contingent that it  should  be'; the contradictory of this is 'it is not contingent that it  should  be'. The similar

propositions, such as 'it is necessary' and  'it is  impossible', may be dealt with in the same manner. For it

comes  about  that just as in the former instances the verbs 'is' and 'is not'  were  added to the subjectmatter of

the sentence 'white' and 'man', so  here  'that it should be' and 'that it should not be' are the  subjectmatter  and

'is possible', 'is contingent', are added. These  indicate that a  certain thing is or is not possible, just as in the

former instances  'is' and 'is not' indicated that certain things  were or were not the  case. 

The contradictory, then, of 'it may not be' is not 'it cannot be',  but 'it cannot not be', and the contradictory of 'it

may be' is not  'it may not be', but cannot be'. Thus the propositions 'it may be' and  'it may not be' appear each

to imply the other: for, since these two  propositions are not contradictory, the same thing both may and may

not be. But the propositions 'it may be' and 'it cannot be' can  never  be true of the same subject at the same

time, for they are  contradictory. Nor can the propositions 'it may not be' and 'it cannot  not be' be at once true

of the same subject. 

The propositions which have to do with necessity are governed by  the  same principle. The contradictory of 'it

is necessary that it  should  be', is not 'it is necessary that it should not be,' but 'it is  not  necessary that it should

be', and the contradictory of 'it is  necessary that it should not be' is 'it is not necessary that it  should not be'. 

Again, the contradictory of 'it is impossible that it should be'  is not 'it is impossible that it should not be' but 'it


ON INTERPRETATION

12 11



Top




Page No 14


is not  impossible that it should be', and the contradictory of 'it is  impossible that it should not be' is 'it is not

impossible that it  should not be'. 

To generalize, we must, as has been stated, define the clauses  'that  it should be' and 'that it should not be' as

the subjectmatter  of the  propositions, and in making these terms into affirmations and  denials we must

combine them with 'that it should be' and 'that it  should not be' respectively. 

We must consider the following pairs as contradictory propositions: 

It may be.              It cannot be.

It is contingent.       It is not contingent.

It is impossible.       It is not impossible.

It is necessary.        It is not necessary.

It is true.             It is not true.

13

Logical sequences follow in due course when we have arranged the  propositions thus. From the proposition

'it may be' it follows that it  is contingent, and the relation is reciprocal. It follows also that it  is not impossible

and not necessary. 

From the proposition 'it may not be' or 'it is contingent that  it  should not be' it follows that it is not necessary

that it should  not  be and that it is not impossible that it should not be. From the  proposition 'it cannot be' or 'it

is not contingent' it follows that  it is necessary that it should not be and that it is impossible that  it should be.

From the proposition 'it cannot not be' or 'it is not  contingent that it should not be' it follows that it is

necessary that  it should be and that it is impossible that it should not be. 

Let us consider these statements by the help of a table: 

A.  B.  It may be.  It cannot be.  It is contingent.  It is not  contingent.  It is not impossible  It is impossible that it

that it  should be.  should be.  It is not necessary  It is necessary that it  that it should be.  should not be. 

C.  D.  It may not be.  It cannot not be.  It is contingent that it  It is not contingent that  should not be.  it should

not be.  It is  not impossible  It is impossible thatit  that it should not be.  should  not be.  It is not necessary that  It

is necessary that it  it should  not be.  should be.

Now the propositions 'it is impossible that it should be' and 'it  is  not impossible that it should be' are

consequent upon the  propositions  'it may be', 'it is contingent', and 'it cannot be',  'it  is not  contingent', the

contradictories upon the contradictories. But  there  is inversion. The negative of the proposition 'it is

impossible'  is  consequent upon the proposition 'it may be' and the corresponding  positive in the first case

upon the negative in the second. For 'it is  impossible' is a positive proposition and 'it is not impossible' is

negative. 

We must investigate the relation subsisting between these  propositions and those which predicate necessity.

That there is a  distinction is clear. In this case, contrary propositions follow  respectively from contradictory

propositions, and the contradictory  propositions belong to separate sequences. For the proposition 'it  is  not

necessary that it should be' is not the negative of 'it is  necessary that it should not be', for both these

propositions may be  true of the same subject; for when it is necessary that a thing should  not be, it is not

necessary that it should be. The reason why the  propositions predicating necessity do not follow in the same

kind of  sequence as the rest, lies in the fact that the proposition 'it is  impossible' is equivalent, when used with


ON INTERPRETATION

13 12



Top




Page No 15


a contrary subject, to the  proposition 'it is necessary'. For when it is impossible that a  thing  should be, it is

necessary, not that it should be, but that it  should  not be, and when it is impossible that a thing should not be,

it is  necessary that it should be. Thus, if the propositions  predicating  impossibility or nonimpossibility

follow without change  of subject  from those predicating possibility or nonpossibility,  those  predicating

necessity must follow with the contrary subject; for  the  propositions 'it is impossible' and 'it is necessary' are

not  equivalent, but, as has been said, inversely connected. 

Yet perhaps it is impossible that the contradictory propositions  predicating necessity should be thus arranged.

For when it is  necessary that a thing should be, it is possible that it should be.  (For if not, the opposite

follows, since one or the other must follow;  so, if it is not possible, it is impossible, and it is thus impossible

that a thing should be, which must necessarily be; which is absurd.) 

Yet from the proposition 'it may be' it follows that it is not  impossible, and from that it follows that it is not

necessary; it  comes about therefore that the thing which must necessarily be need  not be; which is absurd. But

again, the proposition 'it is necessary  that it should be' does not follow from the proposition 'it may be',  nor

does the proposition 'it is necessary that it should not be'.  For  the proposition 'it may be' implies a twofold

possibility,  while, if  either of the two former propositions is true, the twofold  possibility  vanishes. For if a

thing may be, it may also not be, but  if it is  necessary that it should be or that it should not be, one  of the two

alternatives will be excluded. It remains, therefore,  that the  proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not

be'  follows from  the proposition 'it may be'. For this is true also of  that which must  necessarily be. 

Moreover the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not  be'  is the contradictory of that which follows

from the proposition  'it  cannot be'; for 'it cannot be' is followed by 'it is impossible  that  it should be' and by 'it

is necessary that it should not be', and  the contradictory of this is the proposition 'it is not necessary that  it

should not be'. Thus in this case also contradictory propositions  follow contradictory in the way indicated,

and no logical  impossibilities occur when they are thus arranged. 

It may be questioned whether the proposition 'it may be' follows  from the proposition 'it is necessary that it

should be'. If not,  the  contradictory must follow, namely that it cannot be, or, if a  man  should maintain that

this is not the contradictory, then the  proposition 'it may not be'. 

Now both of these are false of that which necessarily is. At the  same time, it is thought that if a thing may be

cut it may also not be  cut, if a thing may be it may also not be, and thus it would follow  that a thing which

must necessarily be may possibly not be; which is  false. It is evident, then, that it is not always the case that

that  which may be or may walk possesses also a potentiality in the other  direction. There are exceptions. In

the first place we must except  those things which possess a potentiality not in accordance with a  rational

principle, as fire possesses the potentiality of giving out  heat, that is, an irrational capacity. Those

potentialities which  involve a rational principle are potentialities of more than one  result, that is, of contrary

results; those that are irrational are  not always thus constituted. As I have said, fire cannot both heat and  not

heat, neither has anything that is always actual any twofold  potentiality. Yet some even of those potentialities

which are  irrational admit of opposite results. However, thus much has been said  to emphasize the truth that it

is not every potentiality which  admits  of opposite results, even where the word is used always in  the same

sense. 

But in some cases the word is used equivocally. For the term  'possible' is ambiguous, being used in the one

case with reference  to  facts, to that which is actualized, as when a man is said to find  walking possible

because he is actually walking, and generally when  a  capacity is predicated because it is actually realized; in

the other  case, with reference to a state in which realization is  conditionally  practicable, as when a man is said

to find walking  possible because  under certain conditions he would walk. This last  sort of potentiality

belongs only to that which can be in motion,  the former can exist also  in the case of that which has not this

power. Both of that which is  walking and is actual, and of that  which has the capacity though not  necessarily


ON INTERPRETATION

13 13



Top




Page No 16


realized, it is true  to say that it is not impossible that  it should walk (or, in the other  case, that it should be),

but while  we cannot predicate this latter  kind of potentiality of that which is  necessary in the unqualified

sense of the word, we can predicate the  former. 

Our conclusion, then, is this: that since the universal is  consequent upon the particular, that which is

necessary is also  possible, though not in every sense in which the word may be used. 

We may perhaps state that necessity and its absence are the  initial principles of existence and nonexistence,

and that all else  must be regarded as posterior to these. 

It is plain from what has been said that that which is of  necessity is actual. Thus, if that which is eternal is

prior,  actuality also is prior to potentiality. Some things are actualities  without potentiality, namely, the

primary substances; a second class  consists of those things which are actual but also potential, whose

actuality is in nature prior to their potentiality, though posterior  in time; a third class comprises those things

which are never  actualized, but are pure potentialities. 

14

The question arises whether an affirmation finds its contrary in a  denial or in another affirmation; whether the

proposition 'every man  is just' finds its contrary in the proposition 'no man is just', or in  the proposition 'every

man is unjust'. Take the propositions  'Callias  is just', 'Callias is not just', 'Callias is unjust'; we have  to

discover which of these form contraries. 

Now if the spoken word corresponds with the judgement of the mind,  and if, in thought, that judgement is the

contrary of another, which  pronounces a contrary fact, in the way, for instance, in which the  judgement 'every

man is just' pronounces a contrary to that pronounced  by the judgement 'every man is unjust', the same must

needs hold  good  with regard to spoken affirmations. 

But if, in thought, it is not the judgement which pronounces a  contrary fact that is the contrary of another,

then one affirmation  will not find its contrary in another, but rather in the corresponding  denial. We must

therefore consider which true judgement is the  contrary of the false, that which forms the denial of the false

judgement or that which affirms the contrary fact. 

Let me illustrate. There is a true judgement concerning that which  is good, that it is good; another, a false

judgement, that it is not  good; and a third, which is distinct, that it is bad. Which of these  two is contrary to

the true? And if they are one and the same, which  mode of expression forms the contrary? 

It is an error to suppose that judgements are to be defined as  contrary in virtue of the fact that they have

contrary subjects; for  the judgement concerning a good thing, that it is good, and that  concerning a bad thing,

that it is bad, may be one and the same, and  whether they are so or not, they both represent the truth. Yet the

subjects here are contrary. But judgements are not contrary because  they have contrary subjects, but because

they are to the contrary  effect. 

Now if we take the judgement that that which is good is good, and  another that it is not good, and if there are

at the same time other  attributes, which do not and cannot belong to the good, we must  nevertheless refuse to

treat as the contraries of the true judgement  those which opine that some other attribute subsists which does

not  subsist, as also those that opine that some other attribute does not  subsist which does subsist, for both

these classes of judgement are of  unlimited content. 

Those judgements must rather be termed contrary to the true  judgements, in which error is present. Now these


ON INTERPRETATION

14 14



Top




Page No 17


judgements are  those  which are concerned with the starting points of generation,  and  generation is the passing

from one extreme to its opposite;  therefore  error is a like transition. 

Now that which is good is both good and not bad. The first quality  is part of its essence, the second

accidental; for it is by accident  that it is not bad. But if that true judgement is most really true,  which

concerns the subject's intrinsic nature, then that false  judgement likewise is most really false, which concerns

its  intrinsic  nature. Now the judgement that that is good is not good is a  false  judgement concerning its

intrinsic nature, the judgement that it  is  bad is one concerning that which is accidental. Thus the  judgement

which denies the true judgement is more really false than  that which  positively asserts the presence of the

contrary quality.  But it is the  man who forms that judgement which is contrary to the  true who is most

thoroughly deceived, for contraries are among the  things which differ  most widely within the same class. If

then of  the two judgements one  is contrary to the true judgement, but that  which is contradictory is  the more

truly contrary, then the latter, it  seems, is the real  contrary. The judgement that that which is good  is bad is

composite.  For presumably the man who forms that judgement  must at the same time  understand that that

which is good is not good. 

Further, the contradictory is either always the contrary or never;  therefore, if it must necessarily be so in all

other cases, our  conclusion in the case just dealt with would seem to be correct. Now  where terms have no

contrary, that judgement is false, which forms the  negative of the true; for instance, he who thinks a man is

not a man  forms a false judgement. If then in these cases the negative is the  contrary, then the principle is

universal in its application. 

Again, the judgement that that which is not good is not good is  parallel with the judgement that that which is

good is good. Besides  these there is the judgement that that which is good is not good,  parallel with the

judgement that that that is not good is good. Let us  consider, therefore, what would form the contrary of the

true  judgement that that which is not good is not good. The judgement  that  it is bad would, of course, fail to

meet the case, since two true  judgements are never contrary and this judgement might be true at  the  same

time as that with which it is connected. For since some  things  which are not good are bad, both judgements

may be true. Nor is  the  judgement that it is not bad the contrary, for this too might be  true,  since both

qualities might be predicated of the same subject. It  remains, therefore, that of the judgement concerning that

which is not  good, that it is not good, the contrary judgement is that it is  good;  for this is false. In the same

way, moreover, the judgement  concerning  that which is good, that it is not good, is the contrary of  the

judgement that it is good. 

It is evident that it will make no difference if we universalize  the  positive judgement, for the universal

negative judgement will form  the  contrary. For instance, the contrary of the judgement that  everything that is

good is good is that nothing that is good is  good.  For the judgement that that which is good is good, if the

subject be  understood in a universal sense, is equivalent to the  judgement that  whatever is good is good, and

this is identical with  the judgement  that everything that is good is good. We may deal  similarly with

judgements concerning that which is not good. 

If therefore this is the rule with judgements, and if spoken  affirmations and denials are judgements expressed

in words, it is  plain that the universal denial is the contrary of the affirmation  about the same subject. Thus

the propositions 'everything good is  good', 'every man is good', have for their contraries the propositions

'nothing good is good', 'no man is good'. The contradictory  propositions, on the other hand, are 'not

everything good is good',  'not every man is good'. 

It is evident, also, that neither true judgements nor true  propositions can be contrary the one to the other. For

whereas, when  two propositions are true, a man may state both at the same time  without inconsistency,

contrary propositions are those which state  contrary conditions, and contrary conditions cannot subsist at one

and  the same time in the same subject. 


ON INTERPRETATION

14 15



Top




Page No 18


THE END 


ON INTERPRETATION

14 16



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. ON INTERPRETATION, page = 4

   3. by Aristotle, page = 4

   4.  1, page = 4

   5.  2, page = 4

   6.  3, page = 5

   7.  4, page = 5

   8.  5, page = 6

   9.  6, page = 6

   10.  7, page = 7

   11.  8, page = 8

   12.  9, page = 8

   13.  10, page = 10

   14.  11, page = 12

   15.  12, page = 14

   16.  13, page = 15

   17.  14, page = 17