Title:   ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Bookmarks





Page No 1


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION......................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

Book I ...................................................................................................................................................................1

1..............................................................................................................................................................1

2..............................................................................................................................................................3

3..............................................................................................................................................................6

4..............................................................................................................................................................9

5............................................................................................................................................................10

6............................................................................................................................................................13

7............................................................................................................................................................15

8............................................................................................................................................................16

9............................................................................................................................................................19

10..........................................................................................................................................................20

Book II...............................................................................................................................................................22

1............................................................................................................................................................22

2............................................................................................................................................................23

3............................................................................................................................................................24

4............................................................................................................................................................25

5............................................................................................................................................................26

6............................................................................................................................................................28

7............................................................................................................................................................29

8............................................................................................................................................................30

9............................................................................................................................................................31

10..........................................................................................................................................................32

11..........................................................................................................................................................34


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

i



Top




Page No 3


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

by Aristotle

translated by H. H. Joachim

Book I  

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10  

Book II  

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11  

Book I

1

OUR next task is to study comingtobe and passingaway. We are to  distinguish the causes, and to state the

definitions, of these  processes considered in generalas changes predicable uniformly of all  the things that

cometobe and passaway by nature. Further, we are to  study growth and 'alteration'. We must inquire what

each of them is;  and whether 'alteration' is to be identified with comingtobe, or  whether to these different

names there correspond two separate  processes with distinct natures. 

On this question, indeed, the early philosophers are divided. Some  of them assert that the socalled

'unqualified comingtobe' is  'alteration', while others maintain that 'alteration' and comingtobe  are

ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION 1



Top




Page No 4


distinct. For those who say that the universe is one something  (i.e. those who generate all things out of one

thing) are bound to  assert that comingtobe is 'alteration', and that whatever  'comestobe' in the proper

sense of the term is 'being altered':  but  those who make the matter of things more than one must distinguish

comingtobe from 'alteration'. To this latter class belong  Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Leucippus. And yet

Anaxagoras himself  failed to understand his own utterance. He says, at all events, that  comingtobe and

passingaway are the same as 'being altered':' yet,  in common with other thinkers, he affirms that the

elements are  many.  Thus Empedocles holds that the corporeal elements are four,  while all  the

elementsincluding those which initiate movementare six  in  number; whereas Anaxagoras agrees with

Leucippus and Democritus  that  the elements are infinite. 

(Anaxagoras posits as elements the 'homoeomeries', viz. bone,  flesh,  marrow, and everything else which is

such that part and whole  are  the same in name and nature; while Democritus and Leucippus say  that  there are

indivisible bodies, infinite both in number and in the  varieties of their shapes, of which everything else is

composedthe  compounds differing one from another according to the shapes,  'positions', and 'groupings' of

their constituents.) 

For the views of the school of Anaxagoras seem diametrically  opposed  to those of the followers of

Empedocles. Empedocles says that  Fire,  Water, Air, and Earth are four elements, and are thus 'simple'  rather

than flesh, bone, and bodies which, like these, are  'homoeomeries'. But the followers of Anaxagoras regard

the  'homoeomeries' as 'simple' and elements, whilst they affirm that  Earth, Fire, Water, and Air are

composite; for each of these is  (according to them) a 'common seminary' of all the 'homoeomeries'. 

Those, then, who construct all things out of a single element,  must maintain that comingtobe and

passingaway are 'alteration'.  For  they must affirm that the underlying something always remains  identical

and one; and change of such a substratum is what we call  'altering' Those, on the other hand, who make the

ultimate kinds of  things more than one, must maintain that 'alteration' is distinct from  comingtobe: for

comingtobe and passingaway result from the  consilience and the dissolution of the many kinds. That is

why  Empedocles too uses language to this effect, when he says 'There is no  comingtobe of anything, but

only a mingling and a divorce of what  has been mingled'. Thus it is clear (i) that to describe  comingtobe

and passingaway in these terms is in accordance with  their  fundamental assumption, and (ii) that they do in

fact so  describe  them: nevertheless, they too must recognize 'alteration' as a  fact  distinct from coming tobe,

though it is impossible for them to  do so  consistently with what they say. 

That we are right in this criticism is easy to perceive. For  'alteration' is a fact of observation. While the

substance of the  thing remains unchanged, we see it 'altering' just as we see in it the  changes of magnitude

called 'growth' and 'diminution'. Nevertheless,  the statements of those who posit more 'original reals' than one

make  'alteration' impossible. For 'alteration, as we assert, takes  place in  respect to certain qualities: and these

qualities (I mean,  e.g.  hotcold, whiteblack, drymoist, softhard, and so forth) are,  all of  them, differences

characterizing the 'elements'. The actual  words of  Empedocles may be quoted in illustration 

The sun everywhere bright to see, and hot,

The rain everywhere dark and cold;

and he distinctively characterizes his remaining elements in a similar  manner. Since, therefore, it is not

possible for Fire to become Water,  or Water to become Earth, neither will it be possible for anything  white to

become black, or anything soft to become hard; and the same  argument applies to all the other qualities. Yet

this is what  'alteration' essentially is. 

It follows, as an obvious corollary, that a single matter must  always be assumed as underlying the contrary

'poles' of any change  whether change of place, or growth and diminution, or 'alteration';  further, that the being

of this matter and the being of 'alteration'  stand and fall together. For if the change is 'alteration', then the


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION 2



Top




Page No 5


substratum is a single element; i.e. all things which admit of  change  into one another have a single matter.

And, conversely, if  the  substratum of the changing things is one, there is 'alteration'. 

Empedocles, indeed, seems to contradict his own statements as well  as the observed facts. For he denies that

any one of his elements  comestobe out of any other, insisting on the contrary that they  are  the things out of

which everything else comestobe; and yet  (having  brought the entirety of existing things, except Strife,

together into  one) he maintains, simultaneously with this denial, that  each thing  once more comestobe out

of the One. Hence it was  clearly out of a  One that this cametobe Water, and that Fire,  various portions of it

being separated off by certain characteristic  differences or  qualitiesas indeed he calls the sun 'white and hot',

and the earth  'heavy and hard'. If, therefore, these characteristic  differences be  taken away (for they can be

taken away, since they  cametobe), it  will clearly be inevitable for Earth to come tobe out  of Water and

Water out of Earth, and for each of the other elements to  undergo a  similar transformationnot only then, but

also nowif, and  because,  they change their qualities. And, to judge by what he says,  the  qualities are such

that they can be 'attached' to things and can  again  be 'separated' from them, especially since Strife and Love

are  still  fighting with one another for the mastery. It was owing to  this same  conflict that the elements were

generated from a One at  the former  period. I say 'generated', for presumably Fire, Earth,  and Water had  no

distinctive existence at all while merged in one. 

There is another obscurity in the theory Empedocles. Are we to  regard the One as his 'original real'? Or is it

the Manyi.e. Fire and  Earth, and the bodies coordinate with these? For the One is an  'element' in so far as it

underlies the process as matteras that  out  of which Earth and Fire cometobe through a change of qualities

due  to 'the motion'. On the other hand, in so far as the One results  from  composition (by a consilience of the

Many), whereas they result  from  disintegration the Many are more 'elementary' than the One, and  prior  to it

in their nature. 

2

We have therefore to discuss the whole subject of 'unqualified'  comingtobe and passingaway; we have to

inquire whether these changes  do or do not occur and, if they occur, to explain the precise  conditions of their

occurrence. We must also discuss the remaining  forms of change, viz. growth and 'alteration'. For though, no

doubt,  Plato investigated the conditions under which things cometobe and  passaway, he confined his

inquiry to these changes; and he  discussed  not all comingtobe, but only that of the elements. He  asked no

questions as to how flesh or bones, or any of the other  similar  compound things, cometobe; nor again did

he examine the  conditions  under which 'alteration' or growth are attributable to  things. 

A similar criticism applies to all our predecessors with the  single exception of Democritus. Not one of them

penetrated below the  surface or made a thorough examination of a single one of the  problems. Democritus,

however, does seem not only to have thought  carefully about all the problems, but also to be distinguished

from  the outset by his method. For, as we are saying, none of the other  philosophers made any definite

statement about growth, except such  as  any amateur might have made. They said that things grow 'by the

accession of like to like', but they did not proceed to explain the  manner of this accession. Nor did they give

any account of  'combination': and they neglected almost every single one of the  remaining problems, offering

no explanation, e.g. of 'action' or  'passion' how in physical actions one thing acts and the other  undergoes

action. Democritus and Leucippus, however, postulate the  'figures', and make 'alteration' and comingtobe

result from them.  They explain comingtobe and passingaway by their 'dissociation' and  'association', but

'alteration' by their 'grouping' and 'Position'.  And since they thought that the 'truth lay in the appearance, and

the  appearances are conflicting and infinitely many, they made the  'figures' infinite in number. Henceowing

to the changes of the  compoundthe same thing seems different and conflicting to different  people: it is

'transposed' by a small additional ingredient, and  appears utterly other by the 'transposition' of a single

constituent.  For Tragedy and Comedy are both composed of the same  letters. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

2 3



Top




Page No 6


Since almost all our predecessors think (i) that comingtobe is  distinct from 'alteration', and (ii) that,

whereas things 'alter' by  change of their qualities, it is by 'association' and 'dissociation'  that they cometobe

and passaway, we must concentrate our  attention  on these theses. For they lead to many perplexing and

wellgrounded  dilemmas. If, on the one hand, comingtobe is  'association', many  impossible consequences

result: and yet there  are other arguments, not  easy to unravel, which force the conclusion  upon us that

comingtobe  cannot possibly be anything else. If, on the  other hand, comingtobe  is not 'association',

either there is no such  thing as comingtobe at  all or it is 'alteration': or else we must  endeavour to unravel

this  dilemma tooand a stubborn one we shall find  it. The fundamental  question, in dealing with all these

difficulties, is this: 'Do things  cometobe and "alter" and grow, and  undergo the contrary changes,  because

the primary "reals" are  indivisible magnitudes? Or is no  magnitude indivisible?' For the  answer we give to

this question makes  the greatest difference. And  again, if the primary 'reals' are  indivisible magnitudes, are

these  bodies, as Democritus and Leucippus  maintain? Or are they planes, as  is asserted in the Timaeus? 

To resolve bodies into planes and no furtherthis, as we have also  remarked elsewhere, in itself a paradox.

Hence there is more to be  said for the view that there are indivisible bodies. Yet even these  involve much of

paradox. Still, as we have said, it is possible to  construct 'alteration' and comingtobe with them, if one

'transposes'  the same by 'turning' and 'intercontact', and by 'the varieties of the  figures', as Democritus does.

(His denial of the reality of colour  is  a corollary from this position: for, according to him, things get  coloured

by 'turning' of the 'figures'.) But the possibility of such a  construction no longer exists for those who divide

bodies into planes.  For nothing except solids results from putting planes together: they  do not even attempt to

generate any quality from them. 

Lack of experience diminishes our power of taking a comprehensive  view of the admitted facts. Hence those

who dwell in intimate  association with nature and its phenomena grow more and more able to  formulate, as

the foundations of their theories, principles such as to  admit of a wide and coherent development: while those

whom devotion to  abstract discussions has rendered unobservant of the facts are too  ready to dogmatize on

the basis of a few observations. The rival  treatments of the subject now before us will serve to illustrate how

great is the difference between a 'scientific' and a 'dialectical'  method of inquiry. For, whereas the Platonists

argue that there must  be atomic magnitudes 'because otherwise "The Triangle" will be more  than one',

Democritus would appear to have been convinced by arguments  appropriate to the subject, i.e. drawn from

the science of nature. Our  meaning will become clear as we proceed. For to suppose that a body  (i.e. a

magnitude) is divisible through and through, and that this  division is possible, involves a difficulty. What will

there be in the  body which escapes the division? 

If it is divisible through and through, and if this division is  possible, then it might be, at one and the same

moment, divided  through and through, even though the dividings had not been effected  simultaneously: and

the actual occurrence of this result would involve  no impossibility. Hence the same principle will apply

whenever a  body  is by nature divisible through and through, whether by bisection,  or  generally by any

method whatever: nothing impossible will have  resulted if it has actually been dividednot even if it has been

divided into innumerable parts, themselves divided innumerable  times.  Nothing impossible will have

resulted, though perhaps nobody in  fact  could so divide it. 

Since, therefore, the be dy is divisible through and through, let  it  have been divided. What, then, will remain?

A magnitude? No: that  is  impossible, since then there will be something not divided, whereas  ex  hypothesis

the body was divisible through and through. But if it be  admitted that neither a body nor a magnitude will

remain, and yet  division is to take place, the constituents of the body will either be  points (i.e. without

magnitude) or absolutely nothing. If its  constituents are nothings, then it might both cometobe out of

nothings and exist as a composite of nothings: and thus presumably the  whole body will be nothing but an

appearance. But if it consists of  points, a similar absurdity will result: it will not possess any  magnitude. For

when the points were in contact and coincided to form a  single magnitude, they did not make the whole any

bigger (since,  when  the body was divided into two or more parts, the whole was not  a bit  smaller or bigger


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

2 4



Top




Page No 7


than it was before the division): hence,  even if all  the points be put together, they will not make any

magnitude. 

But suppose that, as the body is being divided, a minute sectiona  piece of sawdust, as it wereis extracted,

and that in this sensea  body 'comes away' from the magnitude, evading the division. Even  then  the same

argument applies. For in what sense is that section  divisible? But if what 'came away' was not a body but a

separable form  or quality, and if the magnitude is 'points or contacts thus  qualified': it is paradoxical that a

magnitude should consist of  elements, which are not magnitudes. Moreover, where will the points  be? And

are they motionless or moving? And every contact is always a  contact of two somethings, i.e. there is always

something besides  the  contact or the division or the point. 

These, then, are the difficulties resulting from the supposition  that any and every body, whatever its size, is

divisible through and  through. There is, besides, this further consideration. If, having  divided a piece of wood

or anything else, I put it together, it is  again equal to what it was, and is one. Clearly this is so, whatever  the

point at which I cut the wood. The wood, therefore, has been  divided potentially through and through. What,

then, is there in the  wood besides the division? For even if we suppose there is some  quality, yet how is the

wood dissolved into such constituents and  how  does it cometobe out of them? Or how are such

constituents  separated  so as to exist apart from one another? Since, therefore,  it is  impossible for magnitudes

to consist of contacts or points,  there must  be indivisible bodies and magnitudes. Yet, if we do  postulate the

latter, we are confronted with equally impossible  consequences, which  we have examined in other works.'

But we must  try to disentangle these  perplexities, and must therefore formulate  the whole problem over

again. 

On the one hand, then, it is in no way paradoxical that every  perceptible body should be indivisible as well as

divisible at any and  every point. For the second predicate will at. tach to it potentially,  but the first actually.

On the other hand, it would seem to be  impossible for a body to be, even potentially, divisible at all points

simultaneously. For if it were possible, then it might actually occur,  with the result, not that the body would

simultaneously be actually  both (indivisible and divided), but that it would be simultaneously  divided at any

and every point. Consequently, nothing will remain  and  the body will have passedaway into what is

incorporeal: and so it  might cometobe again either out of points or absolutely out of  nothing. And how is

that possible? 

But now it is obvious that a body is in fact divided into  separable magnitudes which are smaller at each

divisioninto  magnitudes which fall apart from one another and are actually  separated. Hence (it is urged) the

process of dividing a body part  by  part is not a 'breaking up' which could continue ad infinitum;  nor can  a

body be simultaneously divided at every point, for that is  not  possible; but there is a limit, beyond which the

'breaking up'  cannot  proceed. The necessary consequenceespecially if comingtobe  and  passingaway are

to take place by 'association' and 'dissociation'  respectivelyis that a body must contain atomic magnitudes

which are  invisible. Such is the argument which is believed to establish the  necessity of atomic magnitudes:

we must now show that it conceals a  faulty inference, and exactly where it conceals it. 

For, since point is not 'immediatelynext' to point, magnitudes  are 'divisible through and through' in one

sense, and yet not in  another. When, however, it is admitted that a magnitude is  'divisible  through and

through', it is thought there is a point not  only  anywhere, but also everywhere, in it: hence it is supposed to

follow,  from the admission, that the magnitude must be divided away  into  nothing. For it is supposedthere is

a point everywhere within  it, so  that it consists either of contacts or of points. But it is  only in  one sense that

the magnitude is 'divisible through and  through', viz.  in so far as there is one point anywhere within it  and all

its points  are everywhere within it if you take them singly  one by one. But there  are not more points than one

anywhere within it,  for the points are  not 'consecutive': hence it is not simultaneously  'divisible through  and

through'. For if it were, then, if it be  divisible at its centre,  it will be divisible also at a point

'immediatelynext' to its centre.  But it is not so divisible: for  position is not 'immediatelynext' to  position,


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

2 5



Top




Page No 8


nor point to  pointin other words, division is not  'immediatelynext' to  division, nor composition to

composition. 

Hence there are both 'association' and 'dissociation', though  neither (a) into, and out of, atomic magnitudes

(for that involves  many impossibilities), nor (b) so that division takes place through  and throughfor this

would have resulted only if point had been  'immediatelynext' to point: but 'dissociation' takes place into

small  (i.e. relatively small) parts, and 'association' takes place out of  relatively small parts. 

It is wrong, however, to suppose, as some assert, that  comingtobe and passingaway in the unqualified and

complete sense  are distinctively defined by 'association' and 'dissociation', while  the change that takes place

in what is continuous is 'alteration'.  On  the contrary, this is where the whole error lies. For unqualified

comingtobe and passingaway are not effected by 'association' and  'dissociation'. They take place when a

thing changes, from this to  that, as a whole. But the philosophers we are criticizing suppose that  all such

change is 'alteration': whereas in fact there is a  difference. For in that which underlies the change there is a

factor  corresponding to the definition and there is a material factor.  When,  then, the change is in these

constitutive factors, there will be  comingtobe or passingaway: but when it is in the thing's qualities,  i.e. a

change of the thing per accidents, there will be 'alteration'. 

'Dissociation' and 'association' affect the thing's susceptibility  to passingaway. For if water has first been

'dissociated' into  smallish drops, air comestobe out of it more quickly: while, if  drops of water have first

been 'associated', air comestobe more  slowly. Our doctrine will become clearer in the sequel.' Meantime,

so  much may be taken as establishedviz. that comingtobe cannot be  'association', at least not the kind of

'association' some  philosophers assert it to be. 

3

Now that we have established the preceding distinctions, we must  first consider whether there is anything

which comestobe and  passesaway in the unqualified sense: or whether nothing comestobe  in this strict

sense, but everything always comestobe something  and  out of somethingI mean, e.g.

comestobehealthy out of beingill  and  ill out of beinghealthy, comestobesmall out of being big and

big  out of beingsmall, and so on in every other instance. For if  there is  to be comingtobe without

qualification, 'something'  mustwithout  qualification'cometobe out of notbeing', so that it  would be true

to say that 'notbeing is an attribute of some  things'. For qualified  comingtobe is a process out of qualified

notbeing (e.g. out of  notwhite or notbeautiful), but unqualified  comingtobe is a process  out of

unqualified notbeing. 

Now 'unqulified' means either (i) the primary predication within  each Category, or (ii) the universal, i.e. the

allcomprehensive,  predication. Hence, if'unqualified notbeing 'means the negation of  'being' in the sense of

the primary term of the Category in  question,  we shall have, in 'unqualified comingtobe', a comingtobe

of a  substance out of notsubstance. But that which is not a substance  or a  'this' clearly cannot possess

predicates drawn from any of the  other  Categories eithere.g. we cannot attribute to it any quality,  quantity,

or position. Otherwise, properties would admit of  existence  in separation from substances. If, on the other

hand,  'unqualified  notbeing' means 'what is not in any sense at all', it  will be a  universal negation of all

forms of being, so that what  comestobe  will have to cometobe out of nothing. 

Although we have dealt with these problems at greater length in  another work,where we have set forth the

difficulties and  established  the distinguishing definitions, the following concise  restatement of  our results

must here be offered: In one sense things  cometobe out  of that which has no 'being' without qualification:

yet  in another  sense they cometobe always out of what is'. For  comingtobe  necessarily implies the

preexistence of something  which potentially  'is', but actually 'is not'; and this something is  spoken of both as


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

3 6



Top




Page No 9


'being' and as 'notbeing'. 

These distinctions may be taken as established: but even then it  is extraordinarily difficult to see how there

can be 'unqualified  comingtobe' (whether we suppose it to occur out of what  potentially  'is', or in some

other way), and we must recall this  problem for  further examination. For the question might be raised

whether  substance (i.e. the 'this') comestobe at all. Is it not  rather the  'such', the 'so great', or the

'somewhere', which  comestobe? And the  same question might be raised about  'passingaway' also. For if a

substantial thing comestobe, it is  clear that there will 'be' (not  actually, but potentially) a  substance, out of

which its comingtobe  will proceed and into which  the thing that is passingaway will  necessarily change.

Then will  any predicate belonging to the remaining  Categories attach actually to  this presupposed substance?

In other  words, will that which is only  potentially a 'this' (which only  potentially is), while without the

qualification 'potentially' it is  not a 'this' (i.e. is not), possess,  e.g. any determinate size or  quality or position?

For (i) if it  possesses none of these  determinations actually, but all of them  only potentially, the result  is first

that a being, which is not a  determinate being, is capable of  separate existence; and in addition  that

comingtobe proceeds out of  nothing preexistinga thesis which,  more than any other, preoccupied  and

alarmed the earliest  philosophers. On the other hand (ii) if,  although it is not a 'this  somewhat' or a substance,

it is to possess  some of the remaining  determinations quoted above, then (as we said)'  properties will be

separable from substances. 

We must therefore concentrate all our powers on the discussion of  these difficulties and on the solution of a

further questionviz. What  is the cause of the perpetuity of comingtobe? Why is there always  unqualified,

as well as partial, comingtobe? Cause' in this  connexion has two senses. It means (i) the source from

which, as we  say, the process 'originates', and (ii) the matter. It is the material  cause that we have here to

state. For, as to the other cause, we  have  already explained (in our treatise on Motion that it involves (a)

something immovable through all time and (b) something always being  moved. And the accurate treatment of

the first of theseof the  immovable 'originative source'belongs to the province of the other,  or 'prior',

philosophy: while as regards 'that which sets everything  else in motion by being itself continuously moved',

we shall have to  explain later' which amongst the socalled 'specific' causes  exhibits  this character. But at

present we are to state the material  causethe  cause classed under the head of matterto which it is due  that

passingaway and comingtobe never fail to occur in Nature.  For  perhaps, if we succeed in clearing up this

question, it will  simultaneously become clear what account we ought to give of that  which perplexed us just

now, i.e. of unqualified passingaway and  comingtobe. 

Our new question tooviz. 'what is the cause of the unbroken  continuity of comingtobe?'is sufficiently

perplexing, if in fact  what passesaway vanishes into 'what is not' and 'what is not' is  nothing (since 'what is

not' is neither a thing, nor possessed of a  quality or quantity, nor in any place). If, then, some one of the

things 'which are' constantly disappearing, why has not the whole of  'what is' been used up long ago and

vanished away assuming of course  that the material of all the several comingstobe was finite? For,

presumably, the unfailing continuity of comingtobe cannot be  attributed to the infinity of the material.

That is impossible, for  nothing is actually infinite. A thing is infinite only potentially,  i.e. the dividing of it

can continue indefinitely: so that we should  have to suppose there is only one kind of comingtobe in the

worldviz. one which never fails, because it is such that what  comestobe is on each successive occasion

smaller than before. But in  fact this is not what we see occurring. 

Why, then, is this form of change necessarily ceaseless? Is it  because the passingaway of this is a

comingtobe of something  else,  and the comingtobe of this a passingaway of something else? 

The cause implied in this solution must no doubt be considered  adequate to account for comingtobe and

passingaway in their general  character as they occur in all existing things alike. Yet, if the same  process is a

coming tobe of this but a passingaway of that, and a  passingaway of this but a comingtobe of that, why

are some things  said to cometobe and passaway without qualification, but others  only with a


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

3 7



Top




Page No 10


qualification? 

The distinction must be investigated once more, for it demands  some explanation. (It is applied in a twofold

manner.) For (i) we  say  'it is now passingaway' without qualification, and not merely  'this  is passingaway':

and we call this change 'comingtobe', and  that  'passingaway', without qualification. And (ii) soandso

'comestobesomething', but does not 'cometobe' without  qualification; for we say that the student

'comestobelearned',  not  'comestobe' without qualification. 

(i) Now we often divide terms into those which signify a 'this  somewhat' and those which do not. And (the

first form of) the  distinction, which we are investigating, results from a similar  division of terms: for it makes

a difference into what the changing  thing changes. Perhaps, e.g. the passage into Fire is 'comingtobe'

unqualified, but 'passingawayofsomething' (e.g. Earth): whilst the  comingtobe of Earth is qualified (not

unqualified) 'comingtobe',  though unqualified 'passingaway' (e.g. of Fire). This would be the  case on the

theory set forth in Parmenides: for he says that the  things into which change takes place are two, and he

asserts that  these two, viz. what is and what is not, are Fire and Earth. Whether  we postulate these, or other

things of a similar kind, makes no  difference. For we are trying to discover not what undergoes these

changes, but what is their characteristic manner. The passage, then,  into what 'is' not except with a

qualification is unqualified  passingaway, while the passage into what 'is' without qualification  is unqualified

comingtobe. Hence whatever the contrasted 'poles'  of  the changes may be whether Fire and Earth, or some

other couplethe  one of them will be 'a being' and the other 'a notbeing'. 

We have thus stated one characteristic manner in which unqualified  will be distinguished from qualified

comingtobe and passingaway:  but they are also distinguished according to the special nature of the

material of the changing thing. For a material, whose constitutive  differences signify more a 'this somewhat',

is itself more  'substantial' or 'real': while a material, whose constitutive  differences signify privation, is 'not

real'. (Suppose, e.g. that 'the  hot' is a positive predication, i.e. a 'form', whereas 'cold' is a  privation, and that

Earth and Fire differ from one another by these  constitutive differences.) 

The opinion, however, which most people are inclined to prefer, is  that the distinction depends upon the

difference between 'the  perceptible' and 'the imperceptible'. Thus, when there is a change  into perceptible

material, people say there is 'comingtobe'; but  when there is a change into invisible material, they call it

'passingaway'. For they distinguish 'what is' and 'what is not' by  their perceiving and notperceiving, just as

what is knowable 'is' and  what is unknowable 'is not'perception on their view having the  force  of

knowledge. Hence, just as they deem themselves to live and to  'be'  in virtue of their perceiving or their

capacity to perceive, so  too  they deem the things to 'be' qua perceived or perceptibleand in  this  they are in a

sense on the track of the truth, though what they  actually say is not true. 

Thus unqualified comingtobe and passingaway turn out to be  different according to common opinion from

what they are in truth. For  Wind and Air are in truth more real more a 'this somewhat' or a  'form'than Earth.

But they are less real to perception which explains  why things are commonly said to 'passaway' without

qualification when  they change into Wind and Air, and to 'cometobe' when they change  into what is

tangible, i.e. into Earth. 

We have now explained why there is 'unqualified comingtobe'  (though it is a passingawayofsomething)

and 'unqualified passingaway  (though it is a comingtobeofsomething). For this distinction of  appellation

depends upon a difference in the material out of which,  and into which, the changes are effected. It depends

either upon  whether the material is or is not 'substantial', or upon whether it is  more or less 'substantial', or

upon whether it is more or less  perceptible. 

(ii) But why are some things said to 'come tobe' without  qualification, and others only to

'cometobesoandso', in cases  different from the one we have been considering where two things


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

3 8



Top




Page No 11


cometobe reciprocally out of one another? For at present we have  explained no more than this:why, when

two things change  reciprocally  into one another, we do not attribute comingtobe and  passingaway

uniformly to them both, although every comingtobe is  a passingaway  of something else and every

passingaway some other  thing's  comingtobe. But the question subsequently formulated  involves a

different problemviz. why, although the learning thing  is said to  'cometobelearned' but not to

'cometobe' without  qualification, yet  the growing thing is said to 'cometobe'. 

The distinction here turns upon the difference of the Categories.  For some things signify a this somewhat,

others a such, and others a  somuch. Those things, then, which do not signify substance, are not  said to

'cometobe' without qualification, but only to  'cometobesoandso'. Nevertheless, in all changing

things alike, we  speak of 'comingtobe' when the thing comestobe something in one of  the two

Columnse.g. in Substance, if it comestobe Fire but not if  it comestobe Earth; and in Quality, if it

comestobe learned but  not when it comestobe ignorant. 

We have explained why some things come tobe without  qualification, but not others both in general, and

also when the  changing things are substances and nothing else; and we have stated  that the substratum is the

material cause of the continuous occurrence  of coming tobe, because it is such as to change from contrary to

contrary and because, in substances, the comingtobe of one thing  is  always a passingaway of another, and

the passingaway of one thing  is  always another's comingtobe. But there is no need even to discuss  the

other question we raisedviz. why comingtobe continues though  things are constantly being destroyed. For

just as people speak of  'a  passingaway' without qualification when a thing has passed into  what  is

imperceptible and what in that sense 'is not', so also they  speak  of 'a comingtobe out of a notbeing' when

a thing emerges from  an  imperceptible. Whether, therefore, the substratum is or is not  something, what

comestobe emerges out of a 'notbeing': so that a  thing comestobe out of a notbeing' just as much as it

'passesaway  into what is not'. Hence it is reasonable enough that  comingtobe  should never fail. For

comingtobe is a passingaway  of 'what is not'  and passingaway is a coming tobe of 'what is not'. 

But what about that which 'is' not except with a qualification? Is  it one of the two contrary poles of the

change.g. Earth (i.e. the  heavy) a 'notbeing', but Fire (i.e. the light) a 'being'? Or, on  the  contrary, does

what is 'include Earth as well as Fire, whereas  what is  not' is matterthe matter of Earth and Fire alike? And

again, is the  matter of each different? Or is it the same, since  otherwise they  would not cometobe

reciprocally out of one another,  i.e. contraries  out of contraries? For these thingsFire, Earth,  Water, Airare

characterized by 'the contraries'. 

Perhaps the solution is that their matter is in one sense the  same, but in another sense different. For that which

underlies them,  whatever its nature may be qua underlying them, is the same: but its  actual being is not the

same. So much, then, on these topics. 

4

Next we must state what the difference is between comingtobe and  'alteration'for we maintain that these

changes are distinct from  one  another. 

Since, then, we must distinguish (a) the substratum, and (b) the  property whose nature it is to be predicated of

the substratum; and  since change of each of these occurs; there is 'alteration' when the  substratum is

perceptible and persists, but changes in its own  properties, the properties in question being opposed to one

another  either as contraries or as intermediates. The body, e.g. although  persisting as the same body, is now

healthy and now ill; and the  bronze is now spherical and at another time angular, and yet remains  the same

bronze. But when nothing perceptible persists in its identity  as a substratum, and the thing changes as a whole

(when e.g. the  seed  as a whole is converted into blood, or water into air, or air  as a  whole into water), such an


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

4 9



Top




Page No 12


occurrence is no longer  'alteration'. It is  a comingtobe of one substance and a passingaway  of the

otherespecially if the change proceeds from an imperceptible  something to something perceptible (either to

touch or to all the  senses), as when water comestobe out of, or passesaway into, air:  for air is pretty well

imperceptible. If, however, in such cases,  any  property (being one of a pair of contraries) persists, in the  thing

that has cometobe, the same as it was in the thing which has  passedawayif, e.g. when water comestobe

out of air, both are  transparent or coldthe second thing, into which the first changes,  must not be a property

of this persistent identical something.  Otherwise the change will be 'alteration.' Suppose, e.g. that the  musical

man passedaway and an unmusical man cametobe, and that the  man persists as something identical. Now,

if 'musicalness and  unmusicalness' had not been a property essentially inhering in man,  these changes would

have been a comingtobe of unmusicalness and a  passingaway of musicalness: but in fact 'musicalness and

unmusicalness' are a property of the persistent identity, viz. man.  (Hence, as regards man, these changes are

'modifications'; though,  as  regards musical man and unmusical man, they are a passingaway  and a

comingtobe.) Consequently such changes are 'alteration.'  When the  change from contrary to contrary is in

quantity, it is  'growth and  diminution'; when it is in place, it is 'motion'; when  it is in  property, i.e. in quality,

it is 'alteration': but, when  nothing  persists, of which the resultant is a property (or an  'accident' in  any sense

of the term), it is 'comingtobe', and the  converse change  is 'passingaway'. 

'Matter', in the most proper sense of the term, is to be  identified with the substratum which is receptive of

comingtobe  and  passingaway: but the substratum of the remaining kinds of change  is  also, in a certain

sense, 'matter', because all these substrata are  receptive of 'contrarieties' of some kind. So much, then, as an

answer  to the questions (i) whether comingtobe 'is' or 'is not'i.e. what  are the precise conditions of its

occurrence and (ii) what  'alteration' is: but we have still to treat of growth. 

5

We must explain (i) wherein growth differs from comingtobe and  from 'alteration', and ii) what is the

process of growing and the  sprocess of diminishing in each and all of the things that grow and  diminish. 

Hence our first question is this: Do these changes differ from one  another solely because of a difference in

their respective  'spheres'?  In other words, do they differ because, while a change from  this to  that (viz. from

potential to actual substance) is  comingtobe, a  change in the sphere of magnitude is growth and one in  the

sphere of  quality is 'alteration'both growth and 'alteration'  being changes  from what ispotentially to what

isactually magnitude  and quality  respectively? Or is there also a difference in the  manner of the  change,

since it is evident that, whereas neither what  is 'altering'  nor what is comingtobe necessarily changes its

place, what is  growing or diminishing changes its spatial position  of necessity,  though in a different manner

from that in which the  moving thing does  so? For that which is being moved changes its  place as a whole: but

the growing thing changes its place like a metal  that is being beaten,  retaining its position as a whole while its

parts change their places.  They change their places, but not in the  same way as the parts of a  revolving globe.

For the parts of the globe  change their places while  the whole continues to occupy an equal  place: but the

parts of the  rowing thing expand over an  everincreasing place and the parts of the  diminishing thing  contract

within an everdiminishing area. 

It is clear, then, that these changesthe changes of that which is  comingtobe, of that which is 'altering', and

of that which is  growingdiffer in manner as well as in sphere. But how are we to  conceive the 'sphere' of the

change which is growth and diminution?  The sphere' of growing and diminishing is believed to be

magnitude.  Are we to suppose that body and magnitude cometobe out of  something  which, though

potentially magnitude and body, is actually  incorporeal  and devoid of magnitude? And since this description

may be  understood  in two different ways, in which of these two ways are we to  apply it  to the process of

growth? Is the matter, out of which  growth takes  place, (i) 'separate' and existing alone by itself, or  (ii)

'separate'  but contained in another body? 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

5 10



Top




Page No 13


Perhaps it is impossible for growth to take place in either of  these  ways. For since the matter is 'separate',

either (a) it will  occupy no  place (as if it were a point), or (b) it will be a 'void',  i.e. a  nonperceptible body.

But the first of these alternatives is  impossible. For since what comestobe out of this incorporeal and

sizeless something will always be 'somewhere', it too must be  'somewhere'either intrinsically or indirectly.

And the second  alternative necessarily implies that the matter is contained in some  other body. But if it is to

be 'in' another body and yet remains  'separate' in such a way that it is in no sense a part of that body  (neither a

part of its substantial being nor an 'accident' of it),  many impossibilities will result. It is as if we were to

suppose  that  when, e.g. air comestobe out of water the process were due  not to a  change of the but to the

matter of the air being 'contained  in' the  water as in a vessel. This is impossible. For (i) there is  nothing to

prevent an indeterminate number of matters being thus  'contained in'  the water, so that they might

cometobe actually an  indeterminate  quantity of air; and (ii) we do not in fact see air  comingtobe out  of

water in this fashion, viz. withdrawing out of  it and leaving it  unchanged. 

It is therefore better to suppose that in all instances of  comingtobe the matter is inseparable, being

numerically identical  and one with the 'containing' body, though isolable from it by  definition. But the same

reasons also forbid us to regard the  matter,  out of which the body comestobe, as points or lines. The  matter

is  that of which points and lines are limits, and it is  something that  can never exist without quality and

without form. 

Now it is no doubt true, as we have also established elsewhere,'  that one thing 'comestobe' (in the

unqualified sense) out of  another  thing: and further it is true that the efficient cause of  its  comingtobe is

either (i) an actual thing (which is the same as  the  effect either genericallyor the efficient cause of the

comingtobe  of a hard thing is not a hard thing or specifically, as  e.g. fire is  the efficient cause of the

comingtobe of fire or one  man of the  birth of another), or (ii) an actuality. Nevertheless,  since there is  also

a matter out of which corporeal substance itself  comestobe  (corporeal substance, however, already

characterized as  suchandsuch  a determinate body, for there is no such thing as body  in general),  this same

matter is also the matter of magnitude and  qualitybeing  separable from these matters by definition, but not

separable in place  unless Qualities are, in their turn, separable. 

It is evident, from the preceding development and discussion of  difficulties, that growth is not a change out of

something which,  though potentially a magnitude, actually possesses no magnitude.  For,  if it were, the 'void'

would exist in separation; but we have  explained in a former work' that this is impossible. Moreover, a

change of that kind is not peculiarly distinctive of growth, but  characterizes comingtobe as such or in

general. For growth is an  increase, and diminution is a lessening, of the magnitude which is  there

alreadythat, indeed, is why the growing thing must possess some  magnitude. Hence growth must not be

regarded as a process from a  matter without magnitude to an actuality of magnitude: for this  would  be a

body's comingtobe rather than its growth. 

We must therefore come to closer quarters with the subject of our  inquiry. We must grapple' with it (as it

were) from its beginning, and  determine the precise character of the growing and diminishing whose  causes

we are investigating. 

It is evident (i) that any and every part of the growing thing has  increased, and that similarly in diminution

every part has become  smaller: also (ii) that a thing grows by the accession, and diminishes  by the departure,

of something. Hence it must grow by the accession  either (a) of something incorporeal or (b) of a body. Now,

if (a) it  grows by the accession of something incorporeal, there will exist  separate a void: but (as we have

stated before)' is impossible for a  matter of magnitude to exist 'separate'. If, on the other hand (b)  it  grows by

the accession of a body, there will be two bodiesthat  which  grows and that which increases itin the same

place: and this  too is  impossible. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

5 11



Top




Page No 14


But neither is it open to us to say that growth or diminution  occurs  in the way in which e.g. air is generated

from water. For,  although  the volume has then become greater, the change will not be  growth, but  a coming

tobe of the oneviz. of that into which the  change is taking  placeand a passingaway of the contrasted

body. It  is not a growth of  either. Nothing grows in the process; unless indeed  there be something  common to

both things (to that which is  comingtobe and to that which  passedaway), e.g. 'body', and this  grows. The

water has not grown,  nor has the air: but the former has  passedaway and the latter has  cometobe, andif

anything has  grownthere has been a growth of  'body.' Yet this too is impossible.  For our account of growth

must  preserve the characteristics of that  which is growing and diminishing.  And these characteristics are

three:  (i) any and every part of the  growing magnitude is made bigger (e.g.  if flesh grows, every  particle of

the flesh gets bigger), (ii) by the  accession of  something, and (iii) in such a way that the growing thing  is

preserved  and persists. For whereas a thing does not persist in the  processes of  unqualified comingtobe or

passingaway, that which  grows or 'alters'  persists in its identity through the 'altering' and  through the

growing or diminishing, though the quality (in  'alteration') and the  size (in growth) do not remain the same.

Now if  the generation of  air from water is to be regarded as growth, a thing  might grow without  the accession

(and without the persistence) of  anything, and  diminish without the departure of anythingand that  which

grows need  not persist. But this characteristic must be  preserved: for the growth  we are discussing has been

assumed to be  thus characterized. 

One might raise a further difficulty. What is 'that which grows'?  Is  it that to which something is added? If,

e.g. a man grows in his  shin,  is it the shin which is greaterbut not that 'whereby' he grows,  viz. not the food?

Then why have not both 'grown'? For when A is added  to B, both A and B are greater, as when you mix wine

with water; for  each ingredient is alike increased in volume. Perhaps the  explanation  is that the substance of

the one remains unchanged, but  the substance  of the other (viz. of the food) does not. For indeed,  even in the

mixture of wine and water, it is the prevailing ingredient  which is  said to have increased in volume. We say,

e.g. that the  wine has  increased, because the whole mixture acts as wine but not  as water. A  similar principle

applies also to 'alteration'. Flesh is  said to have  been 'altered' if, while its character and substance  remain,

some one  of its essential properties, which was not there  before, now qualifies  it: on the other hand, that

'whereby' it has  been 'altered' may have  undergone no change, though sometimes it too  has been affected. The

altering agent, however, and the originative  source of the process are  in the growing thing and in that which is

being 'altered': for the  efficient cause is in these. No doubt the  food, which has come in, may  sometimes

expand as well as the body that  has consumed it (that is so,  e.g. if, after having come in, a food  is converted

into wind), but  when it has undergone this change it  has passedaway: and the efficient  cause is not in the

food. 

We have now developed the difficulties sufficiently and must  therefore try to find a solution of the problem.

Our solution must  preserve intact the three characteristics of growththat the growing  thing persists, that it

grows by the accession (and diminishes by  the  departure) of something, and further that every perceptible

particle  of it has become either larger or smaller. We must  recognize also (a)  that the growing body is not

'void' and that yet  there are not two  magnitudes in the same place, and (b) that it does  not grow by the

accession of something incorporeal. 

Two preliminary distinctions will prepare us to grasp the cause of  growth. We must note (i) that the organic

parts grow by the growth  of  the tissues (for every organ is composed of these as its  constituents); and (ii) that

flesh, bone, and every such partlike  every other thing which has its form immersed in matterhas a  twofold

nature: for the form as well as the matter is called 'flesh'  or  'bone'. 

Now, that any and every part of the tissue qua form should  growand grow by the accession of somethingis

possible, but not  that  any and every part of the tissue qua matter should do so. For  we must  think of the tissue

after the image of flowing water that is  measured  by one and the same measure: particle after particle

comestobe, and  each successive particle is different. And it is in  this sense that  the matter of the flesh

grows, some flowing out and  some flowing in  fresh; not in the sense that fresh matter accedes to  every


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

5 12



Top




Page No 15


particle of  it. There is, however, an accession to every part of  its figure or  'form'. 

That growth has taken place proportionally, is more manifest in  the organic partse.g. in the hand. For there

the fact that the matter  is distinct from the form is more manifest than in flesh, i.e. than in  the tissues. That is

why there is a greater tendency to suppose that a  corpse still possesses flesh and bone than that it still has a

hand or  an arm. 

Hence in one sense it is true that any and every part of the flesh  has grown; but in another sense it is false. For

there has been an  accession to every part of the flesh in respect to its form, but not  in respect to its matter.

The whole, however, has become larger. And  this increase is due (a) on the one hand to the accession of

something, which is called 'food' and is said to be 'contrary' to  flesh, but (b) on the other hand to the

transformation of this food  into the same form as that of flesh as if, e.g. 'moist' were to accede  to 'dry' and,

having acceded, were to be transformed and to become  'dry'. For in one sense 'Like grows by Like', but in

another sense  'Unlike grows by Unlike'. 

One might discuss what must be the character of that 'whereby' a  thing grows. Clearly it must be potentially

that which is  growingpotentially flesh, e.g. if it is flesh that is growing.  Actually, therefore, it must be 'other'

than the growing thing. This  'actual other', then, has passedaway and cometobe flesh. But it has  not been

transformed into flesh alone by itself (for that would have  been a comingtobe, not a growth): on the

contrary, it is the growing  thing which has cometobe flesh (and grown) by the food. In what way,  then, has

the food been modified by the growing thing? Perhaps we  should say that it has been 'mixed' with it, as if one

were to pour  water into wine and the wine were able to convert the new ingredient  into wine. And as fire lays

hold of the inflammable, so the active  principle of growth, dwelling in the growing thing that which is

actually flesh), lays hold of an acceding food which is potentially  flesh and converts it into actual flesh. The

acceding food, therefore,  must be together with the growing thing: for if it were apart from it,  the change

would be a comingtobe. For it is possible to produce fire  by piling logs on to the already burning fire. That

is 'growth'. But  when the logs themselves are set on fire, that is 'comingtobe'. 

'Quantumingeneral' does not cometobe any more than 'animal'  which is neither man nor any other of the

specific forms of animal:  what 'animalingeneral' is in comingtobe, that 'quantumingeneral'  is in

growth. But what does cometobe in growth is flesh or boneor a  hand or arm (i.e. the tissues of these

organic parts). Such things  cometobe, then, by the accession not of quantifiedflesh but of a

quantifiedsomething. In so far as this acceding food is potentially  the double result e.g. is potentially

somuchfleshit produces  growth: for it is bound to become actually both somuch and flesh. But  in so far

as it is potentially flesh only, it nourishes: for it is  thus that 'nutrition' and 'growth' differ by their definition.

That is  why a body's' nutrition' continues so long as it is kept alive (even  when it is diminishing), though not

its 'growth'; and why nutrition,  though 'the same' as growth, is yet different from it in its actual  being. For in

so far as that which accedes is potentially 'so  muchflesh' it tends to increase flesh: whereas, in so far as it is

potentially 'flesh' only, it is nourishment. 

The form of which we have spoken is a kind of power immersed in  mattera duct, as it were. If, then, a

matter accedesa matter,  which  is potentially a duct and also potentially possesses determinate  quantity the

ducts to which it accedes will become bigger. But if it  is no longer able to actif it has been weakened by the

continued  influx of matter, just as water, continually mixed in greater and  greater quantity with wine, in the

end makes the wine watery and  converts it into waterthen it will cause a diminution of the quantum;  though

still the form persists. 

6

(In discussing the causes of comingtobe) we must first  investigate the matter, i.e. the socalled 'elements'.


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

6 13



Top




Page No 16


We must ask  whether they really are clements or not, i.e. whether each of them  is  eternal or whether there is a

sense in which they cometobe:  and, if  they do cometobe, whether all of them cometobe in the same

manner  reciprocally out of one another, or whether one amongst them is  something primary. Hence we must

begin by explaining certain  preliminary matters, about which the statements now current are vague. 

For all (the pluralist philosophers) those who generate the  'elements' as well as those who generate the

bodies that are  compounded of the elements make use of 'dissociation' and  'association', and of 'action' and

'passion'. Now 'association' is  'combination'; but the precise meaning of the process we call  'combining' has

not been explained. Again, (all the monists make use  of 'alteration': but) without an agent and a patient there

cannot be  'altering' any more than there can be 'dissociating' and  'associating'. For not only those who

postulate a plurality of  elements employ their reciprocal action and passion to generate the  compounds: those

who derive things from a single element are equally  compelled to introduce 'acting'. And in this respect

Diogenes is right  when he argues that 'unless all things were derived from one,  reciprocal action and passion

could not have occurred'. The hot thing,  e.g. would not be cooled and the cold thing in turn be warmed: for

heat and cold do not change reciprocally into one another, but what  changes (it is clear) is the substratum.

Hence, whenever there is  action and passion between two things, that which underlies them  must  be a single

something. No doubt, it is not true to say that all  things  are of this character: but it is true of all things

between  which  there is reciprocal action and passion. 

But if we must investigate 'actionpassion' and 'combination', we  must also investigate 'contact'. For action

and passion (in the proper  sense of the terms) can only occur between things which are such as to  touch one

another; nor can things enter into combination at all unless  they have come into a certain kind of contact.

Hence we must give a  definite account of these three things of 'contact', 'combination',  and 'acting'. 

Let us start as follows. All things which admit of 'combination'  must be capable of reciprocal contact: and the

same is true of any two  things, of which one 'acts' and the other 'suffers action' in the  proper sense of the

terms. For this reason we must treat of  'contact'  first. every term which possesses a variety of meaning

includes those  various meanings either owing to a mere coincidence  of language, or  owing to a real order of

derivation in the different  things to which  it is applied: but, though this may be taken to hold  of 'contact' as  of

all such terms, it is nevertheless true that  contact' in the proper  sense applies only to things which have

'position'. And 'position'  belongs only to those things which also  have a Place': for in so far  as we attribute

'contact' to the  mathematical things, we must also  attribute 'place' to them, whether  they exist in separation or

in some  other fashion. Assuming,  therefore, that 'to touch' isas we have  defined it in a previous  work''to

have the extremes together', only  those things will touch  one another which, being separate magnitudes  and

possessing  position, have their extremes 'together'. And since  position belongs  only to those things which also

have a 'place', while  the primary  differentiation of 'place' is the above' and 'the below'  (and the  similar pairs of

opposites), all things which touch one  another will  have 'weight' or 'lightness' either both these qualities  or

one or the  other of them. But bodies which are heavy or light are  such as to  'act' and 'suffer action'. Hence it is

clear that those  things are  by nature such as to touch one another, which (being  separate  magnitudes) have

their extremes 'together' and are able to  move, and  be moved by, one another. 

The manner in which the 'mover' moves the moved' not always the  same: on the contrary, whereas one kind

of 'mover' can only impart  motion by being itself moved, another kind can do so though  remaining  itself

unmoved. Clearly therefore we must recognize a  corresponding  variety in speaking of the 'acting' thing too:

for the  'mover' is said  to 'act' (in a sense) and the 'acting' thing to  'impart motion'.  Nevertheless there is a

difference and we must draw a  distinction. For  not every 'mover' can 'act', if (a) the term  'agent' is to be used

in  contrast to 'patient' and (b) 'patient' is to  be applied only to those  things whose motion is a 'qualitative

affection'i.e. a quality, like  white' or 'hot', in respect to which  they are moved' only in the sense  that they are

'altered': on the  contrary, to 'impart motion' is a  wider term than to 'act'. Still,  so much, at any rate, is clear:

the  things which are 'such as to  impart motion', if that description be  interpreted in one sense,  will touch the

things which are 'such as to  be moved by them'while  they will not touch them, if the description  be


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

6 14



Top




Page No 17


interpreted in a  different sense. But the disjunctive definition of  'touching' must  include and distinguish (a)

'contact in general' as  the relation  between two things which, having position, are such that  one is able  to

impart motion and the other to be moved, and (b)  'reciprocal  contact' as the relation between two things, one

able to  impart motion  and the other able to be moved in such a way that  'action and passion'  are predicable of

them. 

As a rule, no doubt, if A touches B, B touches A. For indeed  practically all the 'movers' within our ordinary

experience impart  motion by being moved: in their case, what touches inevitably must,  and also evidently

does, touch something which reciprocally touches  it. Yet, if A moves B, it is possibleas we sometimes

express itfor A  'merely to touch' B, and that which touches need not touch a something  which touches it.

Nevertheless it is commonly supposed that 'touching'  must be reciprocal. The reason of this belief is that

'movers' which  belong to the same kind as the 'moved' impart motion by being moved.  Hence if anything

imparts motion without itself being moved, it may  touch the 'moved' and yet itself be touched by nothingfor

we say  sometimes that the man who grieves us 'touches' us, but not that we  'touch' him. 

The account just given may serve to distinguish and define the  'contact' which occurs in the things of Nature. 

7

Next in order we must discuss 'action' and 'passion'. The  traditional theories on the subject are conflicting. For

(i) most  thinkers are unanimous in maintaining (a) that 'like' is always  unaffected by 'like', because (as they

argue) neither of two 'likes'  is more apt than the other either to act or to suffer action, since  all the properties

which belong to the one belong identically and in  the same degree to the other; and (b) that 'unlikes', i.e.

'differents', are by nature such as to act and suffer action  reciprocally. For even when the smaller fire is

destroyed by the  greater, it suffers this effect (they say) owing to its  'contrariety'  since the great is contrary to

the small. But (ii)  Democritus  dissented from all the other thinkers and maintained a  theory peculiar  to

himself. He asserts that agent and patient are  identical, i.e.  'like'. It is not possible (he says) that 'others',  i.e.

'differents',  should suffer action from one another: on the  contrary, even if two  things, being 'others', do act in

some way on  one another, this  happens to them not qua 'others' but qua  possessing an identical  property. 

Such, then, are the traditional theories, and it looks as if the  statements of their advocates were in manifest

conflict. But the  reason of this conflict is that each group is in fact stating a  part,  whereas they ought to have

taken a comprehensive view of the  subject  as a whole. For (i) if A and B are 'like'absolutely and in  all

respects without difference from one another it is reasonable  to  infer that neither is in any way affected by

the other. Why,  indeed,  should either of them tend to act any more than the other?  Moreover,  if 'like' can be

affected by 'like', a thing can also be  affected by  itself: and yet if that were soif 'like' tended in fact  to act qua

'like'there would be nothing indestructible or  immovable, for  everything would move itself. And (ii) the

same  consequence follows if  A and B are absolutely 'other', i.e. in no  respect identical.  Whiteness could not

be affected in any way by  line nor line by  whisenessexcept perhaps 'coincidentally', viz. if  the line happened

to be white or black: for unless two things either  are, or are  composed of, 'contraries', neither drives the other

out of  its natural  condition. But (iii) since only those things which  either involve a  'contrariety' or are

'contraries'and not any  things selected at  randomare such as to suffer action and to act,  agent and patient

must  be 'like' (i.e. identical) in kind and yet  'unlike' (i.e. contrary) in  species. (For it is a law of nature that

body is affected by body,  flavour by flavour, colour by colour, and so  in general what belongs  to any kind by

a member of the same kindthe  reason being that  'contraries' are in every case within a single  identical kind,

and it  is 'contraries' which reciprocally act and  suffer action.) Hence agent  and patient must be in one sense

identical, but in another sense other  than (i.e. 'unlike') one  another. And since (a) patient and agent are

generically identical  (i.e. 'like') but specifically 'unlike', while  (b) it is  'contraries' that exhibit this character: it

is clear that  'contraries' and their 'intermediates' are such as to suffer action  and to act reciprocallyfor indeed

it is these that constitute the  entire sphere of passingaway and comingtobe. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

7 15



Top




Page No 18


We can now understand why fire heats and the cold thing cools, and  in general why the active thing

assimilates to itself the patient. For  agent and patient are contrary to one another, and comingtobe is a

process into the contrary: hence the patient must change into the  agent, since it is only thus that comingto be

will be a process  into  the contrary. And, again, it is intelligible that the advocates  of  both views, although

their theories are not the same, are yet in  contact with the nature of the facts. For sometimes we speak of the

substratum as suffering action (e.g. of 'the man' as being healed,  being warmed and chilled, and similarly in

all the other cases), but  at other times we say 'what is cold is 'being warmed', 'what is sick  is being healed':

and in both these ways of speaking we express the  truth, since in one sense it is the 'matter', while in another

sense  it is the 'contrary', which suffers action. (We make the same  distinction in speaking of the agent: for

sometimes we say that 'the  man', but at other times that 'what is hot', produces heat.) Now the  one group of

thinkers supposed that agent and patient must possess  something identical, because they fastened their

attention on the  substratum: while the other group maintained the opposite because  their attention was

concentrated on the 'contraries'. We must conceive  the same account to hold of action and passion as that

which is true  of 'being moved' and 'imparting motion'. For the 'mover', like the  'agent', has two meanings.

Both (a) that which contains the  originative source of the motion is thought to 'impart motion' (for  the

originative source is first amongst the causes), and also (b) that  which is last, i.e. immediately next to the

moved thing and to the  comingtobe. A similar distinction holds also of the agent: for we  speak not only (a)

of the doctor, but also (b) of the wine, as  healing. Now, in motion, there is nothing to prevent the firs; mover

being unmoved (indeed, as regards some 'first' movers' this is  actually necessary) although the last mover

always imparts motion by  being itself moved: and, in action, there is nothing to prevent the  first agent being

unaffected, while the last agent only acts by  suffering action itself. For agent and patient have not the same

matter, agent acts without being affected: thus the art of healing  produces health without itself being acted

upon in any way by that  which is being healed. But (b) the food, in acting, is itself in  some  way acted upon:

for, in acting, it is simultaneously heated or  cooled  or otherwise affected. Now the art of healing corresponds

to an  'originative source', while the food corresponds to 'the last' (i.e.  'continuous') mover. 

Those active powers, then, whose forms are not embodied in matter,  are unaffected: but those whose forms

are in matter are such as to  be  affected in acting. For we maintain that one and the same  'matter' is  equally, so

to say, the basis of either of the two opposed  thingsbeing as it were a 'kind'; and that that which can he hot

must  be made hot, provided the heating agent is there, i.e. comes  near.  Hence (as we have said) some of the

active powers are unaffected  while  others are such as to be affected; and what holds of motion is  true  also of

the active powers. For as in motion 'the first mover'  is  unmoved, so among the active powers 'the first agent'

is  unaffected. 

The active power is a 'cause' in the sense of that from which the  process originates: but the end, for the sake

of which it takes place,  is not 'active'. (That is why health is not 'active', except  metaphorically.) For when the

agent is there, the patient hecomes  something: but when 'states' are there, the patient no longer  becomes  but

already isand 'forms' (i.e. lends') are a kind of  'state'. As to  the 'matter', it (qua matter) is passive. Now fire

contains 'the hot'  embodied in matter: but a 'hot' separate from  matter (if such a thing  existed) could not suffer

any action. Perhaps,  indeed, it is  impossible that 'the hot' should exist in separation  from matter: but  if there

are any entities thus separable, what we are  saying would be  true of them. 

We have thus explained what action and passion are, what things  exhibit them, why they do so, and in what

manner. We must go on to  discuss how it is possible for action and passion to take place. 

8

Some philosophers think that the 'last' agentthe 'agent' in the  strictest senseenters in through certain pores,

and so the patient  suffers action. It is in this way, they assert, that we see and hear  and exercise all our other

senses. Moreover, according to them, things  are seen through air and water and other transparent bodies,


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

8 16



Top




Page No 19


because  such bodies possess pores, invisible indeed owing to their minuteness,  but closeset and arranged in

rows: and the more transparent the body,  the more frequent and serial they suppose its pores to be. Such was

the theory which some philosophers (induding Empedocles) advanced in  regard to the structure of certain

bodies. They do not restrict it  to  the bodies which act and suffer action: but 'combination' too, they  say, takes

place 'only between bodies whose pores are in reciprocal  symmetry'. The most systematic and consistent

theory, however, and one  that applied to all bodies, was advanced by Leucippus and  Democritus:  and, in

maintaining it, they took as their  startingpoint what  naturally comes first. 

For some of the older philosophers thought that 'what is' must of  necessity be 'one' and immovable. The void,

they argue, 'is not':  but  unless there is a void with a separate being of its own, 'what is'  cannot be movednor

again can it be 'many', since there is nothing  to  keep things apart. And in this respect, they insist, the view

that the  universe is not 'continuous' but 'discretesincontact' is no  better  than the view that there are 'many'

(and not 'one') and a void.  For  (suppose that the universe is discretesincontact. Then), if it  is  divisible

through and through, there is no 'one', and therefore  no  'many' either, but the Whole is void; while to maintain

that it  is  divisible at some points, but not at others, looks like an  arbitrary  fiction. For up to what limit is it

divisible? And for  what reason is  part of the Whole indivisible, i.e. a plenum, and  part divided?  Further, they

maintain, it is equally necessary to  deny the existence  of motion. 

Reasoning in this way, therefore, they were led to transcend  senseperception, and to disregard it on the

ground that 'one ought to  follow the argument': and so they assert that the universe is 'one'  and immovable.

Some of them add that it is 'infinite', since the limit  (if it had one) would be a limit against the void. 

There were, then, certain thinkers who, for the reasons we have  stated, enunciated views of this kind as their

theory of 'The  Truth'.... Moreover, although these opinions appear to follow  logically in a dialectical

discussion, yet to believe them seems  next  door to madness when one considers the facts. For indeed no

lunatic  seems to be so far out of his senses as to suppose that fire  and ice  are 'one': it is only between what is

right and what seems  right from  habit, that some people are mad enough to see no  difference. 

Leucippus, however, thought he had a theory which harmonized with  senseperception and would not

abolish either comingtobe and  passingaway or motion and the multiplicity of things. He made these

concessions to the facts of perception: on the other hand, he conceded  to the Monists that there could be no

motion without a void. The  result is a theory which he states as follows: 'The void is a "not  being", and no

part of "what is" is a "notbeing"; for what "is" in  the strict sense of the term is an absolute plenum. This

plenum,  however, is not "one": on the contrary, it is a many" infinite in  number and invisible owing to the

minuteness of their bulk. The "many"  move in the void (for there is a void): and by coming together they

produce "coming tobe", while by separating they produce  "passingaway". Moreover, they act and suffer

action wherever they  chance to be in contact (for there they are not "one"), and they  generate by being put

together and becoming intertwined. From the  genuinelyone, on the other hand, there never could have

cometobe  a  multiplicity, nor from the genuinelymany a "one": that is  impossible.  But' (just as

Empedocles and some of the other  philosophers say that  things suffer action through their pores, so)  'all

"alteration" and  all "passion" take place in the way that has  been explained:  breakingup (i.e. passingaway)

is effected by means  of the void, and  so too is growthsolids creeping in to fill the  void places.'  Empedocles

too is practically bound to adopt the same  theory as  Leucippus. For he must say that there are certain solids

which,  however, are indivisibleunless there are continuous pores  all through  the body. But this last

alternative is impossible: for  then there will  be nothing solid in the body (nothing beside the  pores) but all of

it  will be void. It is necessary, therefore, for his  'contiguous  discretes' to be indivisible, while the intervals

between themwhich  he calls 'pores'must be void. But this is  precisely Leucippus' theory  of action and

passion. 

Such, approximately, are the current explanations of the manner in  which some things 'act' while others

'suffer action'. And as regards  the Atomists, it is not only clear what their explanation is: it is  also obvious


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

8 17



Top




Page No 20


that it follows with tolerable consistency from the  assumptions they employ. But there is less obvious

consistency in  the  explanation offered by the other thinkers. It is not clear, for  instance, how, on the theory of

Empedocles, there is to be  'passingaway' as well as 'alteration'. For the primary bodies of  the  Atomiststhe

primary constituents of which bodies are composed,  and  the ultimate elements into which they are

dissolvedare  indivisible,  differing from one another only in figure. In the  philosophy of  Empedocles, on the

other hand, it is evident that all  the other bodies  down to the 'elements' have their comingtobe and  their

passingaway:  but it is not clear how the 'elements'  themselves, severally in their  aggregated masses,

cometobe and  passaway. Nor is it possible for  Empedocles to explain how they do  so, since he does not

assert that  Fire too (and similarly every one of  his other 'elements') possesses  'elementary constituents' of

itself. 

Such an assertion would commit him to doctrines like those which  Plato has set forth in the Timaeus. For

although both Plato and  Leucippus postulate elementary constituents that are indivisible and  distinctively

characterized by figures, there is this great difference  between the two theories: the 'indivisibles' of Leucippus

(i) are  solids, while those of Plato are planes, and (ii) are characterized by  an infinite variety of figures, while

the characterizing figures  employed by Plato are limited in number. Thus the 'comingstobe'  and  the

'dissociations' result from the 'indivisibles' (a) according  to  Leucippus through the void and through contact

(for it is at the  point  of contact that each of the composite bodies is divisible),  but (b)  according to Plato in

virtue of contact alone, since he denies  there  is a void. 

Now we have discussed 'indivisible planes' in the preceding  treatise.' But with regard to the assumption of

'indivisible  solids',  although we must not now enter upon a detailed study of its  consequences, the following

criticisms fall within the compass of a  short digression: i. The Atomists are committed to the view that every

'indivisible' is incapable alike of receiving a sensible property (for  nothing can 'suffer action' except through

the void) and of  producing  oneno 'indivisible' can be, e.g. either hard or cold. Yet  it is  surely a paradox that

an exception is made of 'the hot''the  hot'  being assigned as peculiar to the spherical figure: for, that  being  so,

its 'contrary' also ('the cold') is bound to belong to  another of  the figures. If, however, these properties (heat

and  cold) do belong  to the 'indivisibles', it is a further paradox that  they should not  possess heaviness and

lightness, and hardness and  softness. And yet  Democritus says 'the more any indivisible exceeds,  the heavier

it  is'to which we must clearly add 'and the hotter it  is'. But if that  is their character, it is impossible they

should  not be affected by  one another: the 'slightlyhot indivisible', e.g.  will inevitably  suffer action from one

which far exceeds it in heat.  Again, if any  'indivisible' is 'hard', there must also be one which is  'soft': but  'the

soft' derives its very name from the fact that it  suffers a  certain actionfor 'soft' is that which yields to

pressure. 

II. But further, not only is it paradoxical (i) that no property  except figure should belong to the 'indivisibles':

it is also  paradoxical (ii) that, if other properties do belong to them, one only  of these additional properties

should attach to eache.g. that this  'indivisible' should be cold and that 'indivisible' hot. For, on  that

supposition, their substance would not even be uniform. And it is  equally impossible (iii) that more than one

of these additional  properties should belong to the single 'indivisible'. For, being  indivisible, it will possess

these properties in the same pointso  that, if it 'suffers action' by being chilled, it will also, qua  chilled, 'act' or

'suffer action' in some other way. And the same line  of argument applies to all the other properties too: for the

difficulty we have just raised confronts, as a necessary  consequence,  all who advocate 'indivisibles' (whether

solids or  planes), since  their 'indivisibles' cannot become either 'rarer' or  'derser' inasmuch  as there is no void

in them. 

III. It is a further paradox that there should be small  'indivisibles', but not large ones. For it is natural enough,

from the  ordinary point of view, that the larger bodies should be more liable  to fracture than the small ones,

since they (viz. the large bodies)  are easily broken up because they collide with many other bodies.  But  why

should indivisibility as such be the property of small, rather  than of large, bodies? 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

8 18



Top




Page No 21


IV. Again, is the substance of all those solids uniform, or do  they fall into sets which differ from one

anotheras if, e.g. some  of  them, in their aggregated bulk, were 'fiery', others earthy'? For  (i)  if all of them are

uniform in substance, what is it that separated  one  from another? Or why, when they come into contact, do

they not  coalesce into one, as drops of water run together when drop touches  drop (for the two cases are

precisely parallel)? On the other hand  (ii) if they fall into differing sets, how are these characterized? It  is

clear, too, that these, rather than the 'figures', ought to be  postulated as 'original reals', i.e. causes from which

the phenomena  result. Moreover, if they differed in substance, they would both act  and suffer action on

coming into reciprocal contact. 

V. Again, what is it which sets them moving? For if their 'mover'  is  other than themselves, they are such as to

'suffer action'. If, on  the  other hand, each of them sets itself in motion, either (a) it will  be divisible

('imparting motion' qua this, 'being moved' qua that), or  (b) contrary properties will attach to it in the same

respecti.e.  'matter' will be identical inpotentiality as well as  numericallyidentical. 

As to the thinkers who explain modification of property through  the movement facilitated by the pores, if this

is supposed to occur  notwithstanding the fact that the pores are filled, their postulate of  pores is superfluous.

For if the whole body suffers action under these  conditions, it would suffer action in the same way even if it

had no  pores but were just its own continuous self. Moreover, how can their  account of 'vision through a

medium' be correct? It is impossible  for  (the visual ray) to penetrate the transparent bodies at their  'contacts';

and impossible for it to pass through their pores if every  pore be full. For how will that differ from having no

pores at all?  The body will be uniformly 'full' throughout. But, further, even if  these passages, though they

must contain bodies, are 'void', the  same  consequence will follow once more. And if they are 'too minute to

admit any body', it is absurd to suppose there is a 'minute' void  and  yet to deny the existence of a 'big' one (no

matter how small  the  'big' may be), or to imagine 'the void' means anything else than a  body's placewhence

it clearly follows that to every body there will  correspond a void of equal cubic capacity. 

As a general criticism we must urge that to postulate pores is  superfluous. For if the agent produces no effect

by touching the  patient, neither will it produce any by passing through its pores.  On  the other hand, if it acts

by contact, theneven without poressome  things will 'suffer action' and others will 'act', provided they are

by nature adapted for reciprocal action and passion. Our arguments  have shown that it is either false or futile

to advocate pores in  the  sense in which some thinkers conceive them. But since bodies are  divisible through

and through, the postulate of pores is ridiculous:  for, qua divisible, a body can fall into separate parts. 

9

Let explain the way in which things in fact possess the power of  generating, and of acting and suffering

action: and let us start  from  the principle we have often enunciated. For, assuming the  distinction  between (a)

that which is potentially and (b) that which  is actually  suchandsuch, it is the nature of the first, precisely in

so far as  it is what it is, to suffer action through and through,  not merely to  be susceptible in some parts while

insusceptible in  others. But its  susceptibility varies in degree, according as it is  more or less;  suchand such,

and one would be more justified in  speaking of 'pores'  in this connexion: for instance, in the metals  there are

veins of 'the  susceptible' stretching continuously through  the substance. 

So long, indeed, as any body is naturally coherent and one, it is  insusceptible. So, too, bodies are

insusceptible so long as they are  not in contact either with one another or with other bodies which  are  by

nature such as to act and suffer action. (To illustrate my  meaning:  Fire heats not only when in contact, but

also from a  distance. For the  fire heats the air, and the airbeing by nature such  as both to act  and suffer

actionheats the body.) But the  supposition that a body is  'susceptible in some parts, but  insusceptible in

others' (is only  possible for those who hold an  erroneous view concerning the  divisibility of magnitudes. For

us)  the following account results from  the distinctions we established  at the beginning. For (i) if  magnitudes


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

9 19



Top




Page No 22


are not divisible through  and throughif, on the contrary,  there are indivisible solids or  planesthen indeed no

body would be  susceptible through and through  :but neither would any be continuous.  Since, however, (ii)

this is  false, i.e. since every body is  divisible, there is no difference  between 'having been divided into  parts

which remain in contact' and  'being divisible'. For if a body  'can be separated at the contacts'  (as some

thinkers express it),  then, even though it has not yet been  divided, it will be in a state  of dividednesssince, as

it can be  divided, nothing inconceivable  results. And (iii) the suposition is  open to this general objectionit  is

a paradox that 'passion' should  occur in this manner only, viz. by  the bodies being split. For this  theory

abolishes 'alteration': but we  see the same body liquid at  one time and solid at another, without  losing its

continuity. It has  suffered this change not by 'division'  and composition', nor yet by  'turning' and 'intercontact'

as  Democritus asserts; for it has  passed from the liquid to the solid  state without any change of  'grouping' or

'position' in the  constituents of its substance. Nor are  there contained within it those  'hard' (i.e. congealed)

particles  'indivisible in their bulk': on the  contrary, it is liquidand  again, solid and congealeduniformly all

through. This theory, it must  be added, makes growth and diminution  impossible also. For if there is  to be

opposition (instead of the  growing thing having changed as a  whole, either by the admixture of  something or

by its own  transformation), increase of size will not  have resulted in any and  every part. 

So much, then, to establish that things generate and are  generated, act and suffer action, reciprocally; and to

distinguish the  way in which these processes can occur from the (impossible) way in  which some thinkers say

they occur. 

10

But we have still to explain 'combination', for that was the third  of the subjects we originally proposed to

discuss. Our explanation  will proceed on the same method as before. We must inquire: What is  'combination',

and what is that which can 'combine'? Of what things,  and under what conditions, is 'combination' a property?

And,  further,  does 'combination' exist in fact, or is it false to assert  its  existence? 

For, according to some thinkers, it is impossible for one thing to  be combined with another. They argue that

(i) if both the 'combined'  constituents persist unaltered, they are no more 'combined' now than  they were

before, but are in the same condition: while (ii) if one has  been destroyed, the constituents have not been

'combined'on the  contrary, one constituent is and the other is not, whereas  'combination' demands

uniformity of condition in them both: and on the  same principle (iii) even if both the combining constituents

have been  destroyed as the result of their coalescence, they cannot 'have been  combined' since they have no

being at all. 

What we have in this argument is, it would seem, a demand for the  precise distinction of 'combination' from

comingtobe and passingaway  (for it is obvious that 'combination', if it exists, must differ  from  these

processes) and for the precise distinction of the  'combinable'  from that which is such as to cometobe and

passaway.  As soon,  therefore, as these distinctions are clear, the  difficulties raised by  the argument would

be solved. 

Now (i) we do not speak of the wood as 'combined' with the fire,  nor  of its burning as a 'combining' either of

its particles with one  another or of itself with the fire: what we say is that 'the fire is  comingtobe, but the

wood is 'passingaway'. Similarly, we speak  neither (ii) of the food as 'combining' with the body, nor (iii) of

the shape as 'combining' with the wax and thus fashioning the lump.  Nor can body 'combine' with white, nor

(to generalize) 'properties'  and 'states' with 'things': for we see them persisting unaltered.  But  again (iv) white

and knowledge cannot be 'combined' either, nor  any  other of the 'adjectivals'. (Indeed, this is a blemish in the

theory  of those who assert that 'once upon a time all things were  together  and combined'. For not everything

can 'combine' with  everything. On  the contrary, both of the constituents that are  combined in the  compound

must originally have existed in separation:  but no property  can have separate existence.) 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

10 20



Top




Page No 23


Since, however, some things arepotentially while others  areactually, the constituents combined in a

compound can 'be' in a  sense and yet 'notbe'. The compound may heactually other than the  constituents

from which it has resulted; nevertheless each of them may  still hepotentially what it was before they were

combined, and both  of them may survive undestroyed. (For this was the difficulty that  emerged in the

previous argument: and it is evident that the combining  constituents not only coalesce, having formerly

existed in separation,  but also can again be separated out from the compound.) The  constituents, therefore,

neither (a) persist actually, as 'body' and  'white' persist: nor (b) are they destroyed (either one of them or

both), for their 'power of action' is preserved. Hence these  difficulties may be dismissed: but the problem

immediately connected  with themwhether combination is something relative to perception'  must be set out

and discussed. 

When the combining constituents have been divided into parts so  small, and have been juxtaposed in such a

manner, that perception  fails to discriminate them one from another, have they then 'been  combined Or ought

we to say 'No, not until any and every part of one  constituent is juxtaposed to a part of the other'? The term,

no doubt,  is applied in the former sense: we speak, e.g. of wheat having been  'combined' with barley when

each grain of the one is juxtaposed to a  grain of the other. But every body is divisible and therefore, since

body 'combined' with body is uniform in texture throughout, any and  every part of each constituent ought to

be juxtaposed to a part of the  other. 

No body, however, can be divided into its 'least' parts: and  'composition' is not identical with 'combination',

but other than  it.  From these premises it clearly follows (i) that so long as the  constituents are preserved in

small particles, we must not speak of  them as 'combined'. (For this will be a 'composition' instead of a

'blending' or 'combination': nor will every portion of the resultant  exhibit the same ratio between its

constituents as the whole. But we  maintain that, if 'combination' has taken place, the compound must  be

uniform in texture throughoutany part of such a compound being the  same as the whole, just as any part of

water is water: whereas, if  'combination' is 'composition of the small particles', nothing of  the  kind will

happen. On the contrary, the constituents will only be  'combined' relatively to perception: and the same thing

will be  'combined' to one percipient, if his sight is not sharp, (but not to  another,) while to the eye of Lynceus

nothing will be 'combined'.)  It  clearly follows (ii) that we must not speak of the constituents  as  'combined in

virtue of a division such that any and every part of  each  is juxtaposed to a part of the other: for it is

impossible for  them to  be thus divided. Either, then, there is no 'combination', or  we have  still to explain the

manner in which it can take place. 

Now, as we maintain, some things are such as to act and others  such as to suffer action from them. Moreover,

some thingsviz. those  Which have the same matter'reciprocate', i.e. are such as to act upon  one another and

to suffer action from one another; while other things,  viz. agents which have not the same matter as their

patients, act  without themselves suffering action. Such agents cannot 'combine'that  is why neither the art of

healing nor health produces health by  'combining' with the bodies of the patients. Amongst those things,

however, which are reciprocally active and passive, some are  easilydivisible. Now (i) if a great quantity (or

a large bulk) of one  of these easilydivisible 'reciprocating' materials be brought  together with a little (or with

a small piece) of another, the  effect  produced is not 'combination', but increase of the dominant:  for the  other

material is transformed into the dominant. (That is  why a drop  of wine does not 'combine' with ten thousand

gallons of  water: for its  form is dissolved, and it is changed so as to merge  in the total  volume of water.) On

the other hand (ii) when there is  a certain  equilibrium between their 'powers of action', then each of  them

changes out of its own nature towards the dominant: yet neither  becomes the other, but both become an

intermediate with properties  common to both. 

Thus it is clear that only those agents are 'combinable' which  involve a contrarietyfor these are such as to

suffer action  reciprocally. And, further, they combine more freely if small pieces  of each of them are

juxtaposed. For in that condition they change  one  another more easily and more quickly; whereas this effect

takes  a long  time when agent and patient are present in bulk. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

10 21



Top




Page No 24


Hence, amongst the divisible susceptible materials, those whose  shape is readily adaptable have a tendency to

combine: for they are  easily divided into small particles, since that is precisely what  'being readily adaptable

in shape' implies. For instance, liquids  are  the most 'combinable' of all bodiesbecause, of all divisible

materials, the liquid is most readily adaptable in shape, unless it be  viscous. Viscous liquids, it is true,

produce no effect except to  increase the volume and bulk. But when one of the constituents is  alone

susceptibleor superlatively susceptible, the other being  susceptible in a very slight degreethe compound

resulting from  their  combination is either no greater in volume or only a little  greater.  This is what happens

when tin is combined with bronze. For  some things  display a hesitating and ambiguous attitude towards one

anothershowing a slight tendency to combine and also an inclination  to behave as 'receptive matter' and

'form' respectively. The behaviour  of these metals is a case in point. For the tin almost vanishes,  behaving as

if it were an immaterial property of the bronze: having  been combined, it disappears, leaving no trace except

the colour it  has imparted to the bronze. The same phenomenon occurs in other  instances too. 

It is clear, then, from the foregoing account, that 'combination'  occurs, what it is, to what it is due, and what

kind of thing is  'combinable'. The phenomenon depends upon the fact that some things  are such as to be (a)

reciprocally susceptible and (b) readily  adaptable in shape, i.e. easily divisible. For such things can be

'combined' without its being necessary either that they should have  been destroyed or that they should survive

absolutely unaltered: and  their 'combination' need not be a 'composition', nor merely  'relative  to perception'.

On the contrary: anything is 'combinable'  which, being  readily adaptable in shape, is such as to suffer action

and to act;  and it is 'combinable with' another thing similarly  characterized (for  the 'combinable' is relative to

the  'combinable'); and 'combination'  is unification of the  'combinables', resulting from their  'alteration'. 

Book II

1

WE have explained under what conditions 'combination', 'contact',  and 'actionpassion' are attributable to the

things which undergo  natural change. Further, we have discussed 'unqualified'  comingtobe  and

passingaway, and explained under what conditions  they are  predicable, of what subject, and owing to what

cause.  Similarly, we  have also discussed 'alteration', and explained what  'altering' is and  how it differs from

comingtobe and passingaway.  But we have still  to investigate the socalled 'elements' of bodies. 

For the complex substances whose formation and maintenance are due  to natural processes all presuppose the

perceptible bodies as the  condition of their comingtobe and passingaway: but philosophers  disagree in

regard to the matter which underlies these perceptible  bodies. Some maintain it is single, supposing it to be,

e.g. Air or  Fire, or an 'intermediate' between these two (but still a body with  a  separate existence). Others, on

the contrary, postulate two or  more  materialsascribing to their 'association' and 'dissociation', or  to  their

'alteration', the comingtobe and passingaway of things.  (Some, for instance, postulate Fire and Earth:

some add Air, making  three: and some, like Empedocles, reckon Water as well, thus  postulating four.) 

Now we may agree that the primary materials, whose change (whether  it be 'association and dissociation' or a

process of another kind)  results in comingtobe and passingaway, are rightly described as  'originative

sources, i.e. elements'. But (i) those thinkers are in  error who postulate, beside the bodies we have mentioned,

a single  matterand that corporeal and separable matter. For this 'body' of  theirs cannot possibly exist without

a 'perceptible contrariety': this  'Boundless', which some thinkers identify with the 'original real',  must be

either light or heavy, either cold or hot. And (ii) what Plato  has written in the Timaeus is not based on any

preciselyarticulated  conception. For he has not stated clearly whether his  'Omnirecipient"  exists in

separation from the 'elements'; nor does  he make any use of  it. He says, indeed, that it is a substratum  prior to

the socalled  'elements'underlying them, as gold underlies  the things that are  fashioned of gold. (And yet

this comparison, if  thus expressed, is  itself open to criticism. Things which cometobe  and passaway


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

Book II 22



Top




Page No 25


cannot  be called by the name of the material out of  which they have  cometobe: it is only the results of

'alteration'  which retain the  name of the substratum whose 'alterations' they  are. However, he  actually says'

that the truest account is to affirm  that each of them  is "gold"'.) Nevertheless he carries his analysis of  the

'elements'solids though they areback to 'planes', and it is  impossible for 'the Nurse' (i.e. the primary matter)

to be identical  with 'the planes'. 

Our own doctrine is that although there is a matter of the  perceptible bodies (a matter out of which the

socalled 'clements'  cometobe), it has no separate existence, but is always bound up with  a contrariety. A

more precise account of these presuppositions has  been given in another work': we must, however, give a

detailed  explanation of the primary bodies as well, since they too are  similarly derived from the matter. We

must reckon as an 'originative  source' and as 'primary' the matter which underlies, though it is  inseparable

from, the contrary qualities: for the hot' is not matter  for 'the cold' nor 'the cold' for 'the hot', but the

substratum is  matter for them both. We therefore have to recognize three  'originative sources': firstly that

which potentially perceptible  body, secondly the contrarieties (I mean, e.g. heat and cold), and  thirdly Fire,

Water, and the like. Only 'thirdly', however: for  these  bodies change into one another (they are not immutable

as  Empedocles  and other thinkers assert, since 'alteration' would then  have been  impossible), whereas the

contrarieties do not change. 

Nevertheless, even so the question remains: What sorts of  contrarieties, and how many of them, are to be

accounted  'originative  sources' of body? For all the other thinkers assume and  use them  without explaining

why they are these or why they are just so  many. 

2

Since, then, we are looking for 'originative sources' of  perceptible  body; and since 'perceptible' is equivalent

to 'tangible',  and  'tangible' is that of which the perception is touch; it is clear  that not all the contrarieties

constitute 'forms' and 'originative  sources' of body, but only those which correspond to touch. For it  is  in

accordance with a contrarietya contrariety, moreover, of  tangible  qualitiesthat the primary bodies are

differentiated. That is  why  neither whiteness (and blackness), nor sweetness (and bitterness),  nor  (similarly)

any quality belonging to the other perceptible  contrarieties either, constitutes an 'element'. And yet vision is

prior to touch, so that its object also is prior to the object of  touch. The object of vision, however, is a quality

of tangible body  not qua tangible, but qua something elsequa something which may  well  be naturally prior

to the object of touch. 

Accordingly, we must segregate the tangible differences and  contrarieties, and distinguish which amongst

them are primary.  Contrarieties correlative to touch are the following: hotcold,  drymoist, heavylight,

hardsoft, viscousbrittle, roughsmooth,  coarsefine. Of these (i) heavy and light are neither active nor

susceptible. Things are not called 'heavy' and 'light' because they  act upon, or suffer action from, other things.

But the 'elements' must  be reciprocally active and susceptible, since they 'combine' and are  transformed into

one another. On the other hand (ii) hot and cold, and  dry and moist, are terms, of which the first pair implies

power to act  and the second pair susceptibility. 'Hot' is that which 'associates'  things of the same kind (for

'dissociating', which people attribute to  Fire as its function, is 'associating' things of the same class, since  its

effect is to eliminate what is foreign), while 'cold' is that  which brings together, i.e. 'associates', homogeneous

and  heterogeneous things alike. And moise is that which, being readily  adaptable in shape, is not

determinable by any limit of its own: while  'dry' is that which is readily determinable by its own limit, but  not

readily adaptable in shape. 

From moist and dry are derived (iii) the fine and coarse, viscous  and brittle, hard and soft, and the remaining

tangible differences.  For (a) since the moist has no determinate shape, but is readily  adaptable and follows the

outline of that which is in contact with it,  it is characteristic of it to be 'such as to fill up'. Now 'the  fine'  is


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

2 23



Top




Page No 26


'such as to fill up'. For the fine' consists of subtle  particles;  but that which consists of small particles is 'such

as to  fill up',  inasmuch as it is in contact whole with wholeand 'the fine'  exhibits  this character in a

superlative degree. Hence it is evident  that the  fine derives from the moist, while the coarse derives from  the

dry.  Again (b) the viscous' derives from the moist: for 'the  viscous' (e.g.  oil) is a 'moist' modified in a certain

way. 'The  brittle', on the  other hand, derives from the dry: for 'brittle' is  that which is  completely dryso

completely, that its solidification  has actually  been due to failure of moisture. Further (c) 'the soft'  derives

from  the moist. For 'soft' is that which yields to pressure by  retiring  into itself, though it does not yield by

total displacement  as the  moist doeswhich explains why the moist is not 'soft', although  'the  soft' derives

from the moist. 'The hard', on the other hand,  derives  from the dry: for 'hard' is that which is solidified, and

the  solidified is dry. 

The terms 'dry' and 'moist' have more senses than one. For 'the  damp', as well as the moist, is opposed to the

dry: and again 'the  solidified', as well as the dry, is opposed to the moist. But all  these qualities derive from

the dry and moist we mentioned first.' For  (i) the dry is opposed to the damp: i.e. 'damp' is that which has

foreign moisture on its surface ('sodden' being that which is  penetrated to its core), while 'dry' is that which

has lost foreign  moisture. Hence it is evident that the damp will derive from the  moist, and 'the dry' which is

opposed to it will derive from the  primary dry. Again (ii) the 'moist' and the solidified derive in the  same way

from the primary pair. For 'moist' is that which contains  moisture of itsown deep within it ('sodden' being

that which is  deeply penetrated by foreign mosture), whereas 'solidigied' is that  which has lost this inner

moisture. Hence these too derive from the  primary pair, the 'solidified' from the dry and the 'solidified'  from

the dry the 'liquefiable' from the moist. 

It is clear, then, that all the other differences reduce to the  first four, but that these admit of no further

reduction. For the  hot  is not essentially moist or dry, nor the moist essentially hot  or  cold: nor are the cold

and the dry derivative forms, either of  one  another or of the hot and the moist. Hence these must be four. 

3

The elementary qualities are four, and any four terms can be  combined in six couples. Contraries, however,

refuse to be coupled:  for it is impossible for the same thing to be hot and cold, or moist  and dry. Hence it is

evident that the 'couplings' of the elementary  qualities will be four: hot with dry and moist with hot, and again

cold with dry and cold with moist. And these four couples have  attached themselves to the apparently 'simple'

bodies (Fire, Air,  Water, and Earth) in a manner consonant with theory. For Fire is hot  and dry, whereas Air

is hot and moist (Air being a sort of aqueous  vapour); and Water is cold and moist, while Earth is cold and

dry.  Thus the differences are reasonably distributed among the primary  bodies, and the number of the latter is

consonant with theory. For all  who make the simple bodies 'elements' postulate either one, or two, or  three, or

four. Now (i) those who assert there is one only, and then  generate everything else by condensation and

rarefaction, are in  effect making their 'originative sources' two, viz. the rare and the  dense, or rather the hot

and the cold: for it is these which are the  moulding forces, while the 'one' underlies them as a 'matter'. But  (ii)

those who postulate two from the startas Parmenides postulated  Fire and Earthmake the intermediates (e.g.

Air and Water) blends of  these. The same course is followed (iii) by those who advocate  three.  (We may

compare what Plato does in Me Divisions': for he  makes 'the  middle' a blend.) Indeed, there is practically no

difference between  those who postulate two and those who postulate  three, except that the  former split the

middle 'element' into two,  while the latter treat it  as only one. But (iv) some advocate four  from the start, e.g.

Empedocles: yet he too draws them together so  as to reduce them to the  two, for he opposes all the others to

Fire. 

In fact, however, fire and air, and each of the bodies we have  mentioned, are not simple, but blended. The

'simple' bodies are indeed  similar in nature to them, but not identical with them. Thus the  'simple' body

corresponding to fire is 'suchasfire, not fire: that  which corresponds to air is 'suchasair': and so on with


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

3 24



Top




Page No 27


the rest  of  them. But fire is an excess of heat, just as ice is an excess of  cold.  For freezing and boiling are

excesses of heat and cold  respectively.  Assuming, therefore, that ice is a freezing of moist and  cold, fire

analogously will be a boiling of dry and hot: a fact, by  the way,  which explains why nothing comestobe

either out of ice or  out of  fire. 

The 'simple' bodies, since they are four, fall into two pairs  which belong to the two regions, each to each: for

Fire and Air are  forms of the body moving towards the 'limit', while Earth and Water  are forms of the body

which moves towards the 'centre'. Fire and  Earth, moreover, are extremes and purest: Water and Air, on the

contrary are intermediates and more like blends. And, further, the  members of either pair are contrary to those

of the other, Water being  contrary to Fire and Earth to Air; for the qualities constituting  Water and Earth are

contrary to those that constitute Fire and Air.  Nevertheless, since they are four, each of them is characterized

par  excellence a single quality: Earth by dry rather than by cold, Water  by cold rather than by moist, Air by

moist rather than by hot, and  Fire by hot rather than by dry. 

4

It has been established before' that the comingtobe of the  'simple' bodies is reciprocal. At the same time, it

is manifest,  even  on the evidence of perception, that they do cometobe: for  otherwise  there would not have

been 'alteration, since 'alteration' is  change in  respect to the qualities of the objects of touch.  Consequently,

we  must explain (i) what is the manner of their  reciprocal  transformation, and (ii) whether every one of them

can come  tobe out  of every oneor whether some can do so, but not others. 

Now it is evident that all of them are by nature such as to change  into one another: for comingtobe is a

change into contraries and out  of contraries, and the 'elements' all involve a contrariety in their  mutual

relations because their distinctive qualities are contrary. For  in some of them both qualities are contrarye.g.

in Fire and Water,  the first of these being dry and hot, and the second moist and cold:  while in others one of

the qualities (though only one) is  contrarye.g. in Air and Water, the first being moist and hot, and the  second

moist and cold. It is evident, therefore, if we consider them  in general, that every one is by nature such as to

cometobe out of  every one: and when we come to consider them severally, it is not  difficult to see the

manner in which their transformation is effected.  For, though all will result from all, both the speed and the

facility  of their conversion will differ in degree. 

Thus (i) the process of conversion will be quick between those  which  have interchangeable 'complementary

factors', but slow between  those  which have none. The reason is that it is easier for a single  thing to  change

than for many. Air, e.g. will result from Fire if a  single  quality changes: for Fire, as we saw, is hot and dry

while Air  is  hot and moist, so that there will be Air if the dry be overcome by  the  moist. Again, Water will

result from Air if the hot be overcome by  the  cold: for Air, as we saw, is hot and moist while Water is cold

and  moist, so that, if the hot changes, there will be Water. So too, in  the same manner, Earth will result from

Water and Fire from Earth,  since the two 'elements' in both these couples have interchangeable

'complementary factors'. For Water is moist and cold while Earth is  cold and dryso that, if the moist be

overcome, there will be Earth:  and again, since Fire is dry and hot while Earth is cold and dry, Fire  will result

from Earth if the cold passaway. 

It is evident, therefore, that the comingtobe of the 'simple'  bodies will be cyclical; and that this cyclical

method of  transformation is the easiest, because the consecutive 'clements'  contain interchangeable

'complementary factors'. On the other hand  (ii) the transformation of Fire into Water and of Air into Earth,

and  again of Water and Earth into Fire and Air respectively, though  possible, is more difficult because it

involves the change of more  qualities. For if Fire is to result from Water, both the cold and  the  moist must

passaway: and again, both the cold and the dry must  passaway if Air is to result from Earth. So' too, if

Water and  Earth  are to result from Fire and Air respectivelyboth qualities must  change. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

4 25



Top




Page No 28


This second method of comingtobe, then, takes a longer time. But  (iii) if one quality in each of two

'elements' passaway, the  transformation, though easier, is not reciprocal. Still, from Fire  plus Water there

will result Earth and Air, and from Air plus Earth  Fire and Water. For there will be Air, when the cold of the

Water  and  the dry of the Fire have passedaway (since the hot of the  latter and  the moist of the former are

left): whereas, when the hot of  the Fire  and the moist of the Water have passedaway, there will be  Earth,

owing to the survival of the dry of the Fire and the cold of  the  Water. So, too, in the same Way, Fire and

Water will result from  Air  plus Earth. For there will be Water, when the hot of the Air and  the  dry of the

Earth have passedaway (since the moist of the former  and  the cold of the latter are left): whereas, when the

moist of the  Air  and the cold of the Earth have passedaway, there will be Fire,  owing  to the survival of the

hot of the Air and the dry of the  Earthqualities essentially constitutive of Fire. Moreover, this  mode  of Fire's

comingtobe is confirmed by perception. For flame is  par  excellence Fire: but flame is burning smoke, and

smoke consists of  Air  and Earth. 

No transformation, however, into any of the 'simple' bodies can  result from the passingaway of one

elementary quality in each of two  'elements' when they are taken in their consecutive order, because  either

identical or contrary qualities are left in the pair: but no  'simple' body can be formed either out of identical, or

out of  contrary, qualities. Thus no 'simple' body would result, if the dry of  Fire and the moist of Air were to

passaway: for the hot is left in  both. On the other hand, if the hot passaway out both, the  contrariesdry

and moistare left. A similar result will occur in  all  the others too: for all the consecutive 'elements' contain

one  identical, and one contrary, quality. Hence, too, it clearly follows  that, when one of the consecutive

'elements' is transformed into  one,  the comingtobe is effected by the passingaway of a single  quality:

whereas, when two of them are transformed into a third,  more than one  quality must have passedaway. 

We have stated that all the 'elements' cometobe out of any one  of them; and we have explained the manner

in which their mutual  conversion takes place. Let us nevertheless supplement our theory by  the following

speculations concerning them. 

5

If Water, Air, and the like are a 'matter' of which the natural  bodies consist, as some thinkers in fact believe,

these 'clements'  must be either one, or two, or more. Now they cannot all of them be  onethey cannot, e.g. all

be Air or Water or Fire or Earthbecause  'Change is into contraries'. For if they all were Air, then  (assuming

Air to persist) there will be 'alteration' instead of  comingtobe.  Besides, nobody supposes a single 'element'

to  persist, as the basis  of all, in such a way that it is Water as well  as Air (or any other  'element') at the same

time. So there will be a  certain contrariety,  i.e. a differentiating quality: and the other  member of this

contrariety, e.g. heat, will belong to some other  'element', e.g. to  Fire. But Fire will certainly not be 'hot Air'.

For  a change of that  kind (a) is 'alteration', and (b) is not what is  observed. Moreover  (c) if Air is again to

result out of the Fire, it  will do so by the  conversion of the hot into its contrary: this  contrary, therefore,  will

belong to Air, and Air will be a cold  something: hence it is  impossible for Fire to be 'hot Air', since in  that

case the same thing  will be simultaneously hot and cold. Both  Fire and Air, therefore,  will be something else

which is the same;  i.e. there will be some  'matter', other than either, common to both. 

The same argument applies to all the 'elements', proving that  there is no single one of them out of which they

all originate. But  neither is there, beside these four, some other body from which they  originatea something

intermediate, e.g. between Air and Water  (coarser than Air, but finer than Water), or between Air and Fire

(coarser than Fire, but finer than Air). For the supposed  'intermediate' will be Air and Fire when a pair of

contrasted  qualities is added to it: but, since one of every two contrary  qualities is a 'privation', the

'intermediate' never can existas some  thinkers assert the 'Boundless' or the 'Environing' existsin  isolation. It

is, therefore, equally and indifferently any one of  the  'elements', or else it is nothing. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

5 26



Top




Page No 29


Since, then, there is nothingat least, nothing perceptibleprior  to  these, they must be all. That being so,

either they must always  persist and not be transformable into one another: or they must  undergo

transformationeither all of them, or some only (as Plato  wrote in the Timacus).' Now it has been proved

before that they must  undergo reciprocal transformation. It has also been proved that the  speed with which

they cometobe, one out of another, is not  uniformsince the process of reciprocal transformation is

relatively  quick between the 'elements' with a 'complementary factor', but  relatively slow between those

which possess no such factor.  Assuming,  then, that the contrariety, in respect to which they are  transformed,

is one, the elements' will inevitably be two: for it is  'matter' that  is the 'mean' between the two contraries, and

matter  is imperceptible  and inseparable from them. Since, however, the  'elements' are seen to  be more than

two, the contrarieties must at the  least be two. But the  contrarieties being two, the 'elements' must  be four (as

they  evidently are) and cannot be three: for the  couplings' are four,  since, though six are possible, the two in

which the qualities are  contrary to one another cannot occur. 

These subjects have been discussed before:' but the following  arguments will make it clear that, since the

'elements' are  transformed into one another, it is impossible for any one of  themwhether it be at the end or in

the middleto be an 'originative  source' of the rest. There can be no such 'originative element' at the  ends: for

all of them would then be Fire or Earth, and this theory  amounts to the assertion that all things are made of

Fire or Earth.  Nor can a 'middleelement' be such an originative source'as some  thinkers suppose that Air is

transformed both into Fire and into  Water, and Water both into Air and into Earth, while the  'endelements'

are not further transformed into one another. For the  process must come to a stop, and cannot continue ad

infinitum in a  straight line in either direction, since otherwise an infinite  number  of contrarieties would attach

to the single 'element'. Let E  stand for  Earth, W for Water, A for Air, and F for Fire. Then (i)  since A is

transformed into F and W, there will be a contrariety  belonging to A  F. Let these contraries be whiteness and

blackness.  Again (ii) since A  is transformed into W, there will be another  contrariety: for W is not  the same

as F. Let this second contrariety  be dryness and moistness, D  being dryness and M moistness. Now if,  when

A is transformed into W,  the 'white' persists, Water will be  moist and white: but if it does  not persist, Water

will be black since  change is into contraries.  Water, therefore, must be either white or  black. Let it then be the

first. On similar grounds, therefore, D  (dryness) will also belong to  F. Consequently F (Fire) as well as  Air

will be able to be transformed  into Water: for it has qualities  contrary to those of Water, since  Fire was first

taken to be black and  then to be dry, while Water was  moist and then showed itself white.  Thus it is evident

that all the  'elements' will be able to be  transformed out of one another; and  that, in the instances we have

taken, E (Earth) also will contain the  remaining two 'complementary  factors', viz. the black and the moist  (for

these have not yet been  coupled). 

We have dealt with this last topic before the thesis we set out to  prove. That thesisviz. that the process

cannot continue ad  infinitumwill be clear from the following considerations. If Fire  (which is represented by

F) is not to revert, but is to be transformed  in turn into some other 'element' (e.g. into Q), a new contrariety,

other than those mentioned, will belong to Fire and Q: for it has been  assumed that Q is not the same as any

of the four, E W A and F. Let K,  then, belong to F and Y to Q. Then K will belong to all four, E W A  and F:

for they are transformed into one another. This last point,  however, we may admit, has not yet been proved:

but at any rate it  is  clear that if Q is to be transformed in turn into yet another  'element', yet another

contrariety will belong not only to Q but  also  to F (Fire). And, similarly, every addition of a new 'element'

will  carry with it the attachment of a new contrariety to the  preceding  elements'. Consequently, if the

'elements' are infinitely  many, there  will also belong to the single 'element' an infinite  number of  contrarieties.

But if that be so, it will be impossible to  define any  'element': impossible also for any to cometobe. For if

one is to  result from another, it will have to pass through such a  vast number  of contrarietiesand indeed even

more than any determinate  number.  Consequently (i) into some 'elements' transformation will  never be

effectedviz. if the intermediates are infinite in number, as  they  must be if the 'elements' are infinitely many:

further (ii) there  will  not even be a transformation of Air into Fire, if the  contrarieties  are infinitely many:

moreover (iii) all the 'elements'  become one. For  all the contrarieties of the 'elements' above F must  belong to

those  below F, and vice versa: hence they will all be one. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

5 27



Top




Page No 30


6

As for those who agree with Empedocles that the 'elements' of body  are more than one, so that they are not

transformed into one  anotherone may well wonder in what sense it is open to them to  maintain that the

'elements' are comparable. Yet Empedocles says  'For  these are all not only equal...' 

If it is meant that they are comparable in their amount, all the  'comparables' must possess an identical

something whereby they are  measured. If, e.g. one pint of Water yields ten of Air, both are  measured by the

same unit; and therefore both were from the first an  identical something. On the other hand, suppose (ii) they

are not  'comparable in their amount' in the sense that somuch of the one  yields so much of the other, but

comparable in 'power of action (a  pint of Water, e.g. having a power of cooling equal to that of ten  pints of

Air); even so, they are 'comparable in their amount',  though  not qua 'amount' but qua Isomuch power'. There

is also (iii) a  third  possibility. Instead of comparing their powers by the measure of  their  amount, they might

be compared as terms in a 'correspondence':  e.g.  'as x is hot, so correspondingly y is white'. But

'correspondence',  though it means equality in the quantum, means  similarity in a quale.  Thus it is manifestly

absurd that the  'simple' bodies, though they are  not transformable, are comparable not  merely as

'corresponding', but  by a measure of their powers; i.e. that  somuch Fire is comparable  with many

timesthatamount of Air, as  being 'equally' or 'similarly'  hot. For the same thing, if it be  greater in amount,

will, since it  belongs to the same kind, have its  ratio correspondingly increased. 

A further objection to the theory of Empedocles is that it makes  even growth impossible, unless it be increase

by addition. For his  Fire increases by Fire: 'And Earth increases its own frame and Ether  increases Ether."

These, however, are cases of addition: but it is not  by addition that growing things are believed to increase.

And it is  far more difficult for him to account for the comingtobe which  occurs in nature. For the things

which cometobe by natural process  all exhibit, in their comingtobe, a uniformity either absolute or

highly regular: while any exceptions any results which are in  accordance neither with the invariable nor with

the general rule are  products of chance and luck. Then what is the cause determining that  man comestobe

from man, that wheat (instead of an olive) comestobe  from wheat, either invariably or generally? Are we

to say 'Bone  comestobe if the "elements" be put together in suchand such a  manner'? For, according to

his own estatements, nothing comestobe  from their 'fortuitous consilience', but only from their 'consilience'

in a certain proportion. What, then, is the cause of this proportional  consilience? Presumably not Fire or

Earth. But neither is it Love  and  Strife: for the former is a cause of 'association' only, and the  latter only of

'dissociation'. No: the cause in question is the  essential nature of each thingnot merely to quote his words) 'a

mingling and a divorce of what has been mingled'. And chance, not  proportion, 'is the name given to these

occurrences': for things can  be 'mingled' fortuitously. 

The cause, therefore, of the comingtobe of the things which owe  their existence to nature is that they are in

suchandsuch a  determinate condition: and it is this which constitutes, the  'nature'  of each thinga 'nature'

about which he says nothing. What he  says,  therefore, is no explanation of 'nature'. Moreover, it is this  which

is both 'the excellence' of each thing and its 'good': whereas  he  assigns the whole credit to the 'mingling'.

(And yet the 'elements'  at  all events are 'dissociated' not by Strife, but by Love: since  the  'elements' are by

nature prior to the Deity, and they too are  Deities.) 

Again, his account of motion is vague. For it is not an adequate  explanation to say that 'Love and Strife set

things moving, unless the  very nature of Love is a movement of this kind and the very nature  of  Strife a

movement of that kind. He ought, then, either to have  defined  or to have postulated these characteristic

movements, or to  have  demonstrated themwhether strictly or laxly or in some other  fashion.  Moreover,

since (a) the 'simple' bodies appear to move  'naturally' as  well as by compulsion, i.e. in a manner contrary to

nature (fire, e.g.  appears to move upwards without compulsion,  though it appears to move  by compulsion

downwards); and since (b) what  is 'natural' is contrary  to that which is due to compulsion, and  movement by


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

6 28



Top




Page No 31


compulsion  actually occurs; it follows that 'natural  movement' can also occur in  fact. Is this, then, the

movement that  Love sets going? No: for, on  the contrary, the 'natural movement'  moves Earth downwards

and  resembles 'dissociation', and Strife  rather than Love is its causeso  that in general, too, Love rather  than

Strife would seem to be  contrary to nature. And unless Love or  Strife is actually setting them  in motion, the

'simple' bodies  themselves have absolutely no movement  or rest. But this is  paradoxical: and what is more,

they do in fact  obviously move. For  though Strife 'dissociated', it was not by Strife  that the 'Ether' was  borne

upwards. On the contrary, sometimes he  attributes its movement  to something like chance ('For thus, as it  ran,

it happened to meet  them then, though often otherwise"), while at  other times he says it  is the nature of Fire

to be borne upwards, but  'the Ether' (to quote  his words) 'sank down upon the Earth with long  roots'. With

such  statements, too, he combines the assertion that the  Order of the World  is the same now, in the reign of

Strife, as it was  formerly in the  reign of Love. What, then, is the 'first mover' of the  'elements'?  What causes

their motion? Presumably not Love and Strife:  on the  contrary, these are causes of a particular motion, if at

least  we  assume that 'first mover' to be an originative source'. 

An additional paradox is that the soul should consist of the  'elements', or that it should be one of them. How

are the soul's  'alterations' to take Place? How, e.g. is the change from being  musical to being unmusical, or

how is memory or forgetting, to  occur?  For clearly, if the soul be Fire, only such modifications  will happen  to

it as characterize Fire qua Fire: while if it be  compounded out of  the elements', only the corporeal

modifications will  occur in it. But  the changes we have mentioned are none of them  corporeal. 

7

The discussion of these difficulties, however, is a task  appropriate  to a different investigation:' let us return to

the  'elements' of  which bodies are composed. The theories that 'there is  something  common to all the

"elements"', and that they are  reciprocally  transformed', are so related that those who accept either  are bound

to  accept the other as well. Those, on the other hand, who  do not make  their comingtobe reciprocalwho

refuse to suppose that  any one of  the 'elements' comestobe out of any other taken singly,  except in  the

sense in which bricks cometobe out of a wallare faced  with a  paradox. How, on their theory, are flesh and

bones or any of  the other  compounds to result from the 'elements' taken together? 

Indeed, the point we have raised constitutes a problem even for  those who generate the 'elements' out of one

another. In what manner  does anything other than, and beside, the 'elements' cometobe out of  them? Let

me illustrate my meaning. Water can cometobe out of Fire  and Fire out of Water; for their substralum is

something common to  them both. But flesh too, presumably, and marrow cometobe out of  them. How,

then, do such things come tobe? For (a) how is the  manner  of their comingtobe to be conceived by those

who maintain a  theory  like that of Empedocles? They must conceive it as  compositionjust as  a wall

comestobe out of bricks and stones: and  the 'Mixture', of  which they speak, will be composed of the

'elements', these being  preserved in it unaltered but with their small  particles juxtaposed  each to each. That

will be the manner,  presumably, in which flesh and  every other compound results from the  'elements'.

Consequently, it  follows that Fire and Water do not  cometobe 'out of any and every  part of flesh'. For

instance,  although a sphere might cometobe out  of this part of a lump of wax  and a pyramid out of some

other part, it  was nevertheless possible for  either figure to have cometobe out of  either part indifferently:

that is the manner of comingtobe when  'both Fire and Water  cometobe out of any and every part of

flesh'.  Those, however, who  maintain the theory in question, are not at  liberty to conceive that  'both

cometobe out of flesh' in that  manner, but only as a stone and  a brick 'both cometobe out of a  wall'viz.

each out of a different  place or part. Similarly (b) even  for those who postulate a single  matter of their

'elements' there is a  certain difficulty in explaining  how anything is to result from two of  them taken

togethere.g. from  'cold' and hot', or from Fire and Earth.  For if flesh consists of both  and is neither of them,

nor again is a  'composition' of them in  which they are preserved unaltered, what  alternative is left except to

identify the resultant of the two  'elements' with their matter? For  the passingaway of either 'element'  produces


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

7 29



Top




Page No 32


either the other or the  matter. 

Perhaps we may suggest the following solution. (i) There are  differences of degree in hot and cold. Although,

therefore, when  either is fully real without qualification, the other will exist  potentially; yet, when neither

exists in the full completeness of  its  being, but both by combining destroy one another's excesses so  that  there

exist instead a hot which (for a 'hot') is cold and a  cold which  (for a 'cold') is hot; then what results from these

two  contraries  will be neither their matter, nor either of them existing  in its full  reality without qualification.

There will result instead  an  'intermediate': and this 'intermediate', according as it is  potentially more hot than

cold or vice versa, will possess a  powerofheating that is double or triple its powerofcooling, or

otherwise related thereto in some similar ratio. Thus all the other  bodies will result from the contraries, or

rather from the 'elements',  in so far as these have been 'combined': while the elements' will  result from the

contraries, in so far as these 'exist potentially'  in  a special sensenot as matter 'exists potentially', but in the

sense  explained above. And when a thing comestobe in this manner,  the  process is cobination'; whereas

what comestobe in the other  manner  is matter. Moreover (ii) contraries also 'suffer action', in  accordance

with the disjunctivelyarticulated definition established  in the early part of this work.' For the actuallyhot is

potentiallycold and the actually cold potentiallyhot; so that hot  and cold, unless they are equally balanced,

are transformed into one  another (and all the other contraries behave in a similar way). It  is  thus, then, that in

the first place the 'elements' are transformed;  and that (in the second place) out of the 'elements' there

cometobe  flesh and bones and the likethe hot becoming cold and  the cold  becoming hot when they have

been brought to the 'mean'. For  at the  'mean' is neither hot nor cold. The 'mean', however, is of  considerable

extent and not indivisible. Similarly, it is qua  reduced  to a 'mean' condition that the dry and the moist, as well

as  the  contraries we have used as examples, produce flesh and bone and  the  remaining compounds. 

8

All the compound bodiesall of which exist in the region belonging  to the central bodyare composed of all

the 'simple' bodies. For  they  all contain Earth because every 'simple' body is to be found  specially  and most

abundantly in its own place. And they all contain  Water  because (a) the compound must possess a definite

outline and  Water,  alone of the 'simple' bodies, is readily adaptable in shape:  moreover  (b) Earth has no

power of cohesion without the moist. On  the contrary,  the moist is what holds it together; for it would fall  to

pieces if  the moist were eliminated from it completely. 

They contain Earth and Water, then, for the reasons we have given:  and they contain Air and Fire, because

these are contrary to Earth and  Water (Earth being contrary to Air and Water to Fire, in so far as one

Substance can be 'contrary' to another). Now all compounds  presuppose  in their comingtobe constituents

which are contrary to  one another:  and in all compounds there is contained one set of the  contrasted  extremes.

Hence the other set must be contained in them  also, so that  every compound will include all the 'simple'

bodies. 

Additional evidence seems to be furnished by the food each  compound takes. For all of them are fed by

substances which are the  same as their constituents, and all of them are fed by more substances  than one.

Indeed, even the plants, though it might be thought they are  fed by one substance only, viz. by Water, are fed

by more than one:  for Earth has been mixed with the Water. That is why farmers too  endeavour to mix before

watering. Although food is akin to the matter,  that which is fed is the 'figure'i.e. the 'form' taken along with

the  matter. This fact enables us to understand why, whereas all the  'simple' bodies cometobe out of one

another, Fire is the only one of  them which (as our predecessors also assert) 'is fed'. For Fire  aloneor more

than all the restis akin to the 'form' because it tends  by nature to be borne towards the limit. Now each of

them naturally  tends to be borne towards its own place; but the 'figure'i.e. the  'form'Of them all is at the

limits. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

8 30



Top




Page No 33


Thus we have explained that all the compound bodies are composed  of all the 'simple' bodies. 

9

Since some things are such as to cometobe and passaway, and  since  comingtobe in fact occurs in the

region about the centre, we  must  explain the number and the nature of the 'originative sources' of  all

comingtobe alike: for a grasp of the true theory of any  universal facilitates the understanding of its specific

forms. 

The 'originative sources', then, of the things which cometobe  are equal in number to, and identical in kind

with, those in the  sphere of the eternal and primary things. For there is one in the  sense of 'matter', and a

second in the sense of 'form': and, in  addition, the third 'originative source' must be present as well.  For  the

two first are not sufficient to bring things into being, any  more  than they are adequate to account for the

primary things. 

Now cause, in the sense of material origin, for the things which  are such as to cometobe is 'that which can

beandnotbe': and  this  is identical with'that which can cometobeandpassaway', since  the  latter,

while it is at one time, at another time is not. (For  whereas  some things are of necessity, viz. the eternal

things,  others of  necessity are not. And of these two sets of things, since  they cannot  diverge from the

necessity of their nature, it is  impossible for the  first not to he and impossible for the second to  he. Other

things,  however, can both be and not he.) Hence comingtobe  and passingaway  must occur within the

field of 'that which can beand  notbe'. This,  therefore, is cause in the sense of material origin for  the things

which are such as to cometobe; while cause, in the  sense of their  'end', is their 'figure' or 'form'and that is

the  formula expressing  the essential nature of each of them. 

But the third 'originative source' must be present as wellthe  cause  vaguely dreamed of by all our

predecessors, definitely stated by  none of them. On the contrary (a) some amongst them thought the nature  of

'the Forms' was adequate to account for comingtobe. Thus Socrates  in the Phaedo first blames everybody

else for having given no  explanation; and then lays it down; that 'some things are Forms,  others Participants

in the Forms', and that 'while a thing is said  to  "be" in virtue of the Form, it is said to "cometobe" qua

sharing  in," to "passaway" qua "losing," the 'Form'. Hence he  thinks that  'assuming the truth of these theses,

the Forms must be  causes both of  comingtobe and of passingaway'. On the other hand  (b) there were

others who thought 'the matter' was adequate by  itself to account for  comingtobe, since 'the movement

originates  from the matter'. 

Neither of these theories, however, is sound. For (a) if the Forms  are causes, why is their generating activity

intermittent instead of  perpetual and continuoussince there always are Participants as well  as Forms?

Besides, in some instances we see that the cause is other  than the Form. For it is the doctor who implants

health and the man of  science who implants science, although 'Health itself' and 'Science  itself' are as well as

the Participants: and the same principle  applies to everything else that is produced in accordance with an art.

On the other hand (b) to say that 'matter generates owing to its  movement' would be, no doubt, more

scientific than to make such  statements as are made by the thinkers we have been criticizing. For  what 'alters'

and transfigures plays a greater part in bringing,  things into being; and we are everywhere accustomed, in the

products  of nature and of art alike, to look upon that which can initiate  movement as the producing cause.

Nevertheless this second theory is  not right either. 

For, to begin with, it is characteristic of matter to suffer  action,  i.e. to be moved: but to move, i.e. to act,

belongs to a  different  'power'. This is obvious both in the things that cometobe  by art and  in those that

come tobe by nature. Water does not of  itself produce  out of itself an animal: and it is the art, not the  wood,

that makes a  bed. Nor is this their only error. They make a  second mistake in  omitting the more controlling


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

9 31



Top




Page No 34


cause: for they  eliminate the  essential nature, i.e. the 'form'. And what is more,  since they remove  the formal

cause, they invest the forces they assign  to the 'simple'  bodiesthe forces which enable these bodies to bring

things into  beingwith too instrumental a character. For 'since' (as  they say) 'it  is the nature of the hot to

dissociate, of the cold to  bring together,  and of each remaining contrary either to act or to  suffer action',  it is

out of such materials and by their agency (so  they maintain)  that everything else comestobe and

passesaway. Yet  (a) it is  evident that even Fire is itself moved, i.e. suffers action.  Moreover (b) their

procedure is virtually the same as if one were to  treat the saw (and the various instruments of carpentry) as

'the  cause' of the things that cometobe: for the wood must be divided  if  a man saws, must become smooth

if he planes, and so on with the  remaining tools. Hence, however true it may be that Fire is active,  i.e. sets

things moving, there is a further point they fail to  observeviz. that Fire is inferior to the tools or instruments

in  the  manner in which it sets things moving. 

10

As to our own theorywe have given a general account of the causes  in an earlier work,' we have now

explained and distinguished the  'matter' and the 'form'. Further, since the change which is motion has  been

proved' to be eternal, the continuity of the occurrence of  comingtobe follows necessarily from what we

have established: for  the eternal motion, by causing 'the generator' to approach and retire,  will produce

comingtobe uninterruptedly. At the same time it is  clear that we were right when, in an earlier work,' we

called motion  (not comingtobe) 'the primary form of change'. For it is far more  reasonable that what is

should cause the comingtobe of what is  not,  than that what is not should cause the being of what is. Now

that  which is being moved is, but that which is comingtobe is not: hence,  also, motion is prior to

comingtobe. 

We have assumed, and have proved, that comingtobe and  passingaway  happen to things continuously;

and we assert that motion  causes  comingtobe. That being so, it is evident that, if the motion  be  single, both

processes cannot occur since they are contrary to one  another: for it is a law of nature that the same cause,

provided it  remain in the same condition, always produces the same effect, so  that, from a single motion,

either comingtobe or passingaway will  always result. The movements must, on the contrary, be more

than  one,  and they must be contrasted with one another either by the  sense of  their motion or by its

irregularity: for contrary effects  demand  contraries as their causes. 

This explains why it is not the primary motion that causes  comingtobe and passingaway, but the motion

along the inclined  circle: for this motion not only possesses the necessary continuity,  but includes a duality of

movements as well. For if comingtobe and  passingaway are always to be continuous, there must be some

body  always being moved (in order that these changes may not fail) and  moved with a duality of movements

(in order that both changes, not one  only, may result). Now the continuity of this movement is caused by  the

motion of the whole: but the approaching and retreating of the  moving body are caused by the inclination. For

the consequence of  the  inclination is that the body becomes alternately remote and  near; and  since its distance

is thus unequal, its movement will be  irregular.  Therefore, if it generates by approaching and by its  proximity,

itthis very same bodydestroys by retreating and  becoming remote: and  if it generates by many successive

approaches, it  also destroys by  many successive retirements. For contrary effects  demand contraries as  their

causes; and the natural processes of  passingaway and  comingtobe occupy equal periods of time. Hence,

too, the timesi.e.  the livesof the several kinds of living things  have a number by which  they are

distinguished: for there is an Order  controlling all things,  and every time (i.e. every life) is measured  by a

period. Not all of  them, however, are measured by the same  period, but some by a smaller  and others by a

greater one: for to some  of them the period, which is  their measure, is a year, while to some  it is longer and to

others  shorter. 

And there are facts of observation in manifest agreement with our  theories. Thus we see that comingtobe


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

10 32



Top




Page No 35


occurs as the sun approaches  and decay as it retreats; and we see that the two processes occupy  equal times.

For the durations of the natural processes of  passingaway and comingtobe are equal. Nevertheless it

Often happens  that things passaway in too short a time. This is due to the  'intermingling' by which the things

that cometobe and passaway  are  implicated with one another. For their matter is 'irregular', i.e.  is  not

everywhere the same: hence the processes by which they  cometobe  must be 'irregular' too, i.e. some too

quick and others too  slow.  Consequently the phenomenon in question occurs, because the  'irregular'

comingtobe of these things is the passingaway of  other  things. 

Comingtobe and passingaway will, as we have said, always be  continuous, and will never fail owing to

the cause we stated. And this  continuity has a sufficient reason on our theory. For in all things,  as we affirm,

Nature always strives after 'the better'. Now 'being'  (we have explained elsewhere the exact variety of

meanings we  recognize in this term) is better than 'notbeing': but not all things  can possess 'being', since

they are too far removed from the  'originative source. 'God therefore adopted the remaining alternative,  and

fulfilled the perfection of the universe by making comingtobe  uninterrupted: for the greatest possible

coherence would thus be  secured to existence, because that 'comingtobe should itself  cometobe

perpetually' is the closest approximation to eternal being. 

The cause of this perpetuity of comingtobe, as we have often  said,  is circular motion: for that is the only

motion which is  continuous.  That, too, is why all the other thingsthe things, I mean,  which are  reciprocally

transformed in virtue of their 'passions' and  their  'powers of action' e.g. the 'simple' bodiesimitate circular

motion.  For when Water is transformed into Air, Air into Fire, and the  Fire  back into Water, we say the

comingtobe 'has completed the  circle',  because it reverts again to the beginning. Hence it is by  imitating

circular motion that rectilinear motion too is continuous. 

These considerations serve at the same time to explain what is to  some people a baffling problemviz. why

the 'simple' bodies, since  each them is travelling towards its own place, have not become  dissevered from one

another in the infinite lapse of time. The  reason  is their reciprocal transformation. For, had each of them

persisted in  its own place instead of being transformed by its  neighbour, they  would have got dissevered long

ago. They are  transformed, however,  owing to the motion with its dual character: and  because they are

transformed, none of them is able to persist in any  place allotted to  it by the Order. 

It is clear from what has been said (i) that comingtobe and  passingaway actually occur, (ii) what causes

them, and (iii) what  subject undergoes them. But (a) if there is to be movement (as we have  explained

elsewhere, in an earlier work') there must be something  which initiates it; if there is to be movement always,

there must  always be something which initiates it; if the movement is to be  continuous, what initiates it must

be single, unmoved, ungenerated,  and incapable of 'alteration'; and if the circular movements are  more  than

one, their initiating causes must all of them, in spite of  their  plurality, be in some way subordinated to a

single  'originative  source'. Further (b) since time is continuous, movement  must be  continuous, inasmuch as

there can be no time without movement.  Time,  therefore, is a 'number' of some continuous movementa

'number',  therefore, of the circular movement, as was established in the  discussions at the beginning. But (c)

is movement continuous because  of the continuity of that which is moved, or because that in which the

movement occurs (I mean, e.g. the place or the quality) is continuous?  The answer must clearly be 'because

that which is moved is  continuous'. (For how can the quality be continuous except in virtue  of the continuity

of the thing to which it belongs? But if the  continuity of 'that in which' contributes to make the movement

continuous, this is true only of 'the place in which'; for that has  'magnitude' in a sense.) But (d) amongst

continuous bodies which are  moved, only that which is moved in a circle is 'continuous' in such  a  way that it

preserves its continuity with itself throughout the  movement. The conclusion therefore is that this is what

produces  continuous movement, viz. the body which is being moved in a circle;  and its movement makes

time continuous. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

10 33



Top




Page No 36


11

Wherever there is continuity in any process (comingtobe or  'alteration' or any kind of change whatever) we

observe  consecutiveness', i.e. this comingtobe after that without any  interval. Hence we must investigate

whether, amongst the consecutive  members, there is any whose future being is necessary; or whether,  on  the

contrary, every one of them may fail to cometobe. For that  some  of them may fail to occur, is clear. (a) We

need only appeal to  the  distinction between the statements 'x will be' and 'x is about  to  which depends upon

this fact. For if it be true to say of x that it  'will be', it must at some time be true to say of it that 'it is':

whereas, though it be true to say of x now that 'it is about to  occur', it is quite possible for it not to

cometobethus a man might  not walk, though he is now 'about to' walk. And (b) since (to appeal  to a

general principle) amongst the things which 'are' some are  capable also of 'notbeing', it is clear that the same

ambiguous  character will attach to them no less when they are comingtobe: in  other words, their

comingtobe will not be necessary. 

Then are all the things that cometobe of this contingent  character? Or, on the contrary, is it absolutely

necessary for some of  them to cometobe? Is there, in fact, a distinction in the field of  'comingtobe'

corresponding to the distinction, within the field of  'being', between things that cannot possibly 'notbe' and

things  that  can 'notbe'? For instance, is it necessary that solstices  shall  cometobe, i.e. impossible that they

should fail to be able  to occur? 

Assuming that the antecedent must have cometobe if the  consequent is to be (e.g. that foundations must

have cometobe if  there is to be a house: clay, if there are to be foundations), is  the  converse also true? If

foundations have cometobe, must a house  cometobe? The answer seems to be that the necessary nexus

no  longer  holds, unless it is 'necessary' for the consequent (as well  as for the  antecedent) to

cometobe'necessary' absolutely. If that  be the case,  however, 'a house must come tobe if foundations

have  cometobe', as  well as vice versa. For the antecedent was assumed  to be so related to  the consequent

that, if the latter is to be, the  antecedent must have  cometobe before it. If, therefore, it is  necessary that the

consequent should cometobe, the antecedent also  must have  cometobe: and if the antecedent has

cometobe, then the  consequent  also must cometobenot, however, because of the  antecedent, but

because the future being of the consequent was assumed  as necessary.  Hence, in any sequence, when the

being of the consequent  is necessary,  the nexus is reciprocalin other words, when the  antecedent has

cometobe the consequent must always cometobe too. 

Now (i) if the sequence of occurrences is to proceed ad infinitum  'downwards', the coming tobe of any

determinate 'this' amongst the  later members of the sequence will not be absolutely, but only  conditionally,

necessary. For it will always be necessary that some  other member shall have cometobe before 'this' as the

presupposed  condition of the necessity that 'this' should cometobe:  consequently, since what is 'infinite'

has no 'originative source',  neither will there be in the infinite sequence any 'primary' member  which will

make it 'necessary' for the remaining members to  cometobe. 

Nor again (ii) will it be possible to say with truth, even in  regard  to the members of a limited sequence, that it

is 'absolutely  necessary' for any one of them to cometobe. We cannot truly say,  e.g. that 'it is absolutely

necessary for a house to cometobe when  foundations have been laid': for (unless it is always necessary for

a  house to be comingtobe) we should be faced with the consequence  that, when foundations have been

laid, a thing, which need not  always  be, must always be. No: if its comingtobe is to be  'necessary', it  must

be 'always' in its comingtobe. For what is  'of necessity'  coincides with what is 'always', since that which

'must  be' cannot  possibly 'notbe'. Hence a thing is eternal if its  'being' is  necessary: and if it is eternal, its

'being' is  necessary. And if,  therefore, the 'comingtobe' of a thing is  necessary, its  'comingtobe' is

eternal; and if eternal, necessary. 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

11 34



Top




Page No 37


It follows that the comingtobe of anything, if it is absolutely  necessary, must be cyclicali.e. must return

upon itself. For coming  tobe must either be limited or not limited: and if not limited, it  must be either

rectilinear or cyclical. But the first of these last  two alternatives is impossible if comingtobe is to be

eternal,  because there could not be any 'originative source' whatever in an  infinite rectilinear sequence,

whether its members be taken  'downwards' (as future events) or 'upwards' (as past events). Yet  comingtobe

must have an 'originative source' (if it is to be  necessary and therefore eternal), nor can it be eternal if it is

limited. Consequently it must be cyclical. Hence the nexus must be  reciprocal. By this I mean that the

necessary occurrence of 'this'  involves the necessary occurrence of its antecedent: and conversely  that, given

the antecedent, it is also necessary for the consequent to  cometobe. And this reciprocal nexus will hold

continuously  throughout the sequence: for it makes no difference whether the  reciprocal nexus, of which we

are speaking, is mediated by two, or  by  many, members. 

It is in circular movement, therefore, and in cyclical  comingtobe that the 'absolutely necessary' is to be

found. In  other  words, if the comingtobe of any things is cyclical, it is  'necessary' that each of them is

comingtobe and has cometobe:  and  if the comingtobe of any things is 'necessary', their

comingtobe  is cyclical. 

The result we have reached is logically concordant with the  eternity  of circular motion, i.e. the eternity of the

revolution of  the heavens  (a fact which approved itself on other and independent  evidence),'  since precisely

those movements which belong to, and  depend upon, this  eternal revolution 'cometobe' of necessity, and of

necessity 'will  be'. For since the revolving body is always setting  something else  in motion, the movement of

the things it moves must  also be  circular. Thus, from the being of the 'upper revolution' it  follows  that the sun

revolves in this determinate manner; and since  the sun  revolves thus, the seasons in consequence cometobe

in a  cycle,  i.e. return upon themselves; and since they cometobe  cyclically,  so in their turn do the things

whose comingtobe the  seasons  initiate. 

Then why do some things manifestly come tobe in this cyclical  fashion (as, e.g. showers and air, so that it

must rain if there is to  be a cloud and, conversely, there must be a cloud if it is to rain),  while men and

animals do not 'return upon themselves' so that the same  individual comestobe a second time (for though

your comingtobe  presupposes your father's, his comingtobe does not presuppose  yours)? Why, on the

contrary, does this comingtobe seem to  constitute a rectilinear sequence? 

In discussing this new problem, we must begin by inquiring whether  all things 'return upon themselves' in a

uniform manner; or whether,  on the contrary, though in some sequences what recurs is numerically  the same,

in other sequences it is the same only in species. In  consequence of this distinction, it is evident that those

things,  whose 'substance'that which is undergoing the processis  imperishable, will be numerically, as well

as specifically, the same  in their recurrence: for the character of the process is determined by  the character of

that which undergoes it. Those things, on the other  hand, whose 'substance' is perish, able (not imperishable)

must  'return upon themselves' in the sense that what recurs, though  specifically the same, is not the same

numerically. That why, when  Water comestobe from Air and Air from Water, the Air is the same

'specifically', not 'numerically': and if these too recur  numerically  the same, at any rate this does not happen

with things  whose  'substance' comestobewhose 'substance' is such that it is  essentially capable of

notbeing. 

THE END 


ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION

11 35



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION, page = 4

   3. by Aristotle, page = 4

4.  Book I, page = 4

   5.  1, page = 4

   6.  2, page = 6

   7.  3, page = 9

   8.  4, page = 12

   9.  5, page = 13

   10.  6, page = 16

   11.  7, page = 18

   12.  8, page = 19

   13.  9, page = 22

   14.  10, page = 23

15.  Book II, page = 25

   16.  1, page = 25

   17.  2, page = 26

   18.  3, page = 27

   19.  4, page = 28

   20.  5, page = 29

   21.  6, page = 31

   22.  7, page = 32

   23.  8, page = 33

   24.  9, page = 34

   25.  10, page = 35

   26.  11, page = 37