Title:   Meno

Subject:  

Author:   Plato

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Page No 44

Page No 45

Bookmarks





Page No 1


Meno

Plato



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

Meno .....................................................................................................................................................................1

Plato.........................................................................................................................................................1

INTRODUCTION...................................................................................................................................1

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO..................................................................................................................6

MENO ....................................................................................................................................................12


Meno

i



Top




Page No 3


Meno

Plato

Translated by Benjamin Jowett

INTRODUCTION. 

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 

MENO  

INTRODUCTION.

This Dialogue begins abruptly with a question of Meno, who asks,  'whether  virtue can be taught.'  Socrates

replies that he does not as  yet know what  virtue is, and has never known anyone who did.  'Then he  cannot

have met  Gorgias when he was at Athens.'  Yes, Socrates had met  him, but he has a  bad memory, and has

forgotten what Gorgias said.  Will Meno tell him his  own notion, which is probably not very  different from

that of Gorgias?  'O  yesnothing easier:  there is the  virtue of a man, of a woman, of an old  man, and of a

child; there is a  virtue of every age and state of life, all  of which may be easily  described.' 

Socrates reminds Meno that this is only an enumeration of the  virtues and  not a definition of the notion which

is common to them  all.  In a second  attempt Meno defines virtue to be 'the power of  command.'  But to this,

again, exceptions are taken.  For there must  be a virtue of those who obey,  as well as of those who command;

and  the power of command must be justly or  not unjustly exercised.  Meno  is very ready to admit that justice

is  virtue:  'Would you say virtue  or a virtue, for there are other virtues,  such as courage, temperance,  and the

like; just as round is a figure, and  black and white are  colours, and yet there are other figures and other

colours.  Let Meno  take the examples of figure and colour, and try to  define them.'  Meno  confesses his

inability, and after a process of  interrogation, in  which Socrates explains to him the nature of a 'simile in

multis,'  Socrates himself defines figure as 'the accompaniment of colour.'  But  some one may object that he

does not know the meaning of the word  'colour;' and if he is a candid friend, and not a mere disputant,

Socrates  is willing to furnish him with a simpler and more  philosophical definition,  into which no disputed

word is allowed to  intrude:  'Figure is the limit of  form.'  Meno imperiously insists  that he must still have a

definition of  colour.  Some raillery  follows; and at length Socrates is induced to reply,  'that colour is  the

effluence of form, sensible, and in due proportion to  the sight.'  This definition is exactly suited to the taste of

Meno, who  welcomes  the familiar language of Gorgias and Empedocles.  Socrates is of  opinion that the more

abstract or dialectical definition of figure is  far  better. 

Now that Meno has been made to understand the nature of a general  definition, he answers in the spirit of a

Greek gentleman, and in the  words  of a poet, 'that virtue is to delight in things honourable, and  to have the

power of getting them.'  This is a nearer approximation  than he has yet  made to a complete definition, and,

regarded as a  piece of proverbial or  popular morality, is not far from the truth.  But the objection is urged,  'that

the honourable is the good,' and as  every one equally desires the  good, the point of the definition is  contained

in the words, 'the power of  getting them.'  'And they must  be got justly or with justice.'  The  definition will

Meno 1



Top




Page No 4


then stand thus:  'Virtue is the power of getting good with  justice.'  But justice is a  part of virtue, and therefore

virtue is the  getting of good with a  part of virtue.  The definition repeats the word  defined. 

Meno complains that the conversation of Socrates has the effect of  a  torpedo's shock upon him.  When he

talks with other persons he has  plenty  to say about virtue; in the presence of Socrates, his thoughts  desert

him.  Socrates replies that he is only the cause of perplexity  in others, because  he is himself perplexed.  He

proposes to continue  the enquiry.  But how,  asks Meno, can he enquire either into what he  knows or into what

he does  not know?  This is a sophistical puzzle,  which, as Socrates remarks, saves  a great deal of trouble to

him who  accepts it.  But the puzzle has a real  difficulty latent under it, to  which Socrates will endeavour to

find a  reply.  The difficulty is the  origin of knowledge: 

He has heard from priests and priestesses, and from the poet  Pindar, of an  immortal soul which is born again

and again in  successive periods of  existence, returning into this world when she  has paid the penalty of

ancient crime, and, having wandered over all  places of the upper and under  world, and seen and known all

things at  one time or other, is by  association out of one thing capable of  recovering all.  For nature is of  one

kindred; and every soul has a  seed or germ which may be developed into  all knowledge.  The existence  of this

latent knowledge is further proved by  the interrogation of one  of Meno's slaves, who, in the skilful hands of

Socrates, is made to  acknowledge some elementary relations of geometrical  figures.  The  theorem that the

square of the diagonal is double the square  of the  sidethat famous discovery of primitive mathematics, in

honour of  which the legendary Pythagoras is said to have sacrificed a  hecatombis  elicited from him.  The

first step in the process of  teaching has made him  conscious of his own ignorance.  He has had the  'torpedo's

shock' given  him, and is the better for the operation.  But  whence had the uneducated  man this knowledge?  He

had never learnt  geometry in this world; nor was it  born with him; he must therefore  have had it when he was

not a man.  And as  he always either was or was  not a man, he must have always had it.  (Compare Phaedo.) 

After Socrates has given this specimen of the true nature of  teaching, the  original question of the

teachableness of virtue is  renewed.  Again he  professes a desire to know 'what virtue is' first.  But he is willing

to  argue the question, as mathematicians say, under  an hypothesis.  He will  assume that if virtue is knowledge,

then  virtue can be taught.  (This was  the stage of the argument at which  the Protagoras concluded.) 

Socrates has no difficulty in showing that virtue is a good, and  that  goods, whether of body or mind, must be

under the direction of  knowledge.  Upon the assumption just made, then, virtue is teachable.  But where are  the

teachers?  There are none to be found.  This is  extremely discouraging.  Virtue is no sooner discovered to be

teachable, than the discovery follows  that it is not taught.  Virtue,  therefore, is and is not teachable. 

In this dilemma an appeal is made to Anytus, a respectable and  welltodo  citizen of the old school, and a

family friend of Meno, who  happens to be  present.  He is asked 'whether Meno shall go to the  Sophists and be

taught.'  The suggestion throws him into a rage.  'To  whom, then, shall  Meno go?' asks Socrates.  To any

Athenian  gentlemanto the great Athenian  statesmen of past times.  Socrates  replies here, as elsewhere

(Laches,  Prot.), that Themistocles,  Pericles, and other great men, had sons to whom  they would surely, if  they

could have done so, have imparted their own  political wisdom; but  no one ever heard that these sons of theirs

were  remarkable for  anything except riding and wrestling and similar  accomplishments.  Anytus is angry at

the imputation which is cast on his  favourite  statesmen, and on a class to which he supposes himself to

belong;  he  breaks off with a significant hint.  The mention of another opportunity  of talking with him, and the

suggestion that Meno may do the Athenian  people a service by pacifying him, are evident allusions to the

trial  of  Socrates. 

Socrates returns to the consideration of the question 'whether  virtue is  teachable,' which was denied on the

ground that there are no  teachers of  it:  (for the Sophists are bad teachers, and the rest of  the world do not

profess to teach).  But there is another point which  we failed to observe,  and in which Gorgias has never

instructed Meno,  nor Prodicus Socrates.  This is the nature of right opinion.  For  virtue may be under the


Meno

Meno 2



Top




Page No 5


guidance  of right opinion as well as of  knowledge; and right opinion is for  practical purposes as good as

knowledge, but is incapable of being taught,  and is also liable, like  the images of Daedalus, to 'walk off,'

because not  bound by the tie of  the cause.  This is the sort of instinct which is  possessed by  statesmen, who

are not wise or knowing persons, but only  inspired or  divine.  The higher virtue, which is identical with

knowledge,  is an  ideal only.  If the statesman had this knowledge, and could teach  what  he knew, he would be

like Tiresias in the world below,'he alone has  wisdom, but the rest flit like shadows.' 

This Dialogue is an attempt to answer the question, Can virtue be  taught?  No one would either ask or answer

such a question in modern  times.  But in  the age of Socrates it was only by an effort that the  mind could rise to

a  general notion of virtue as distinct from the  particular virtues of  courage, liberality, and the like.  And when

a  hazy conception of this  ideal was attained, it was only by a further  effort that the question of  the

teachableness of virtue could be  resolved. 

The answer which is given by Plato is paradoxical enough, and seems  rather  intended to stimulate than to

satisfy enquiry.  Virtue is  knowledge, and  therefore virtue can be taught.  But virtue is not  taught, and therefore

in  this higher and ideal sense there is no  virtue and no knowledge.  The  teaching of the Sophists is confessedly

inadequate, and Meno, who is their  pupil, is ignorant of the very  nature of general terms.  He can only  produce

out of their armoury the  sophism, 'that you can neither enquire  into what you know nor into  what you do not

know;' to which Socrates  replies by his theory of  reminiscence. 

To the doctrine that virtue is knowledge, Plato has been constantly  tending  in the previous Dialogues.  But the

new truth is no sooner  found than it  vanishes away.  'If there is knowledge, there must be  teachers; and where

are the teachers?'  There is no knowledge in the  higher sense of  systematic, connected, reasoned knowledge,

such as may  one day be attained,  and such as Plato himself seems to see in some  far off vision of a single

science.  And there are no teachers in the  higher sense of the word; that  is to say, no real teachers who will

arouse the spirit of enquiry in their  pupils, and not merely instruct  them in rhetoric or impart to them ready

made information for a fee  of 'one' or of 'fifty drachms.'  Plato is  desirous of deepening the  notion of

education, and therefore he asserts the  paradox that there  are no educators.  This paradox, though different in

form, is not  really different from the remark which is often made in modern  times  by those who would

depreciate either the methods of education  commonly  employed, or the standard attainedthat 'there is no

true  education  among us.' 

There remains still a possibility which must not be overlooked.  Even if  there be no true knowledge, as is

proved by 'the wretched  state of  education,' there may be right opinion, which is a sort of  guessing or

divination resting on no knowledge of causes, and  incommunicable to others.  This is the gift which our

statesmen have,  as is proved by the circumstance  that they are unable to impart their  knowledge to their sons.

Those who  are possessed of it cannot be said  to be men of science or philosophers,  but they are inspired and

divine. 

There may be some trace of irony in this curious passage, which  forms the  concluding portion of the

Dialogue.  But Plato certainly  does not mean to  intimate that the supernatural or divine is the true  basis of

human life.  To him knowledge, if only attainable in this  world, is of all things the  most divine.  Yet, like other

philosophers, he is willing to admit that  'probability is the guide of  life (Butler's Analogy.);' and he is at the

same time desirous of  contrasting the wisdom which governs the world with a  higher wisdom.  There are

many instincts, judgments, and anticipations of  the human  mind which cannot be reduced to rule, and of

which the grounds  cannot  always be given in words.  A person may have some skill or latent  experience

which he is able to use himself and is yet unable to teach  others, because he has no principles, and is

incapable of collecting  or  arranging his ideas.  He has practice, but not theory; art, but not  science.  This is a

true fact of psychology, which is recognized by  Plato  in this passage.  But he is far from saying, as some have

imagined, that  inspiration or divine grace is to be regarded as higher  than knowledge.  He  would not have

preferred the poet or man of action  to the philosopher, or  the virtue of custom to the virtue based upon  ideas. 


Meno

Meno 3



Top




Page No 6


Also here, as in the Ion and Phaedrus, Plato appears to acknowledge  an  unreasoning element in the higher

nature of man.  The philosopher  only has  knowledge, and yet the statesman and the poet are inspired.  There

may be a  sort of irony in regarding in this way the gifts of  genius.  But there is  no reason to suppose that he is

deriding them,  any more than he is deriding  the phenomena of love or of enthusiasm in  the Symposium, or of

oracles in  the Apology, or of divine intimations  when he is speaking of the daemonium  of Socrates.  He

recognizes the  lower form of right opinion, as well as the  higher one of science, in  the spirit of one who

desires to include in his  philosophy every  aspect of human life; just as he recognizes the existence  of popular

opinion as a fact, and the Sophists as the expression of it. 

This Dialogue contains the first intimation of the doctrine of  reminiscence  and of the immortality of the soul.

The proof is very  slight, even  slighter than in the Phaedo and Republic.  Because men  had abstract ideas  in a

previous state, they must have always had  them, and their souls  therefore must have always existed.  For they

must always have been either  men or not men.  The fallacy of the  latter words is transparent.  And  Socrates

himself appears to be  conscious of their weakness; for he adds  immediately afterwards, 'I  have said some

things of which I am not  altogether confident.'  (Compare Phaedo.)  It may be observed, however,  that the

fanciful  notion of preexistence is combined with a true but  partial view of  the origin and unity of

knowledge, and of the association  of ideas.  Knowledge is prior to any particular knowledge, and exists not  in

the  previous state of the individual, but of the race.  It is potential,  not actual, and can only be appropriated by

strenuous exertion. 

The idealism of Plato is here presented in a less developed form  than in  the Phaedo and Phaedrus.  Nothing is

said of the preexistence  of ideas of  justice, temperance, and the like.  Nor is Socrates  positive of anything  but

the duty of enquiry.  The doctrine of  reminiscence too is explained  more in accordance with fact and

experience as arising out of the  affinities of nature (ate tes thuseos  oles suggenous ouses).  Modern  philosophy

says that all things in  nature are dependent on one another; the  ancient philosopher had the  same truth latent

in his mind when he affirmed  that out of one thing  all the rest may be recovered.  The subjective was

converted by him  into an objective; the mental phenomenon of the  association of ideas  (compare Phaedo)

became a real chain of existences.  The germs of two  valuable principles of education may also be gathered

from  the 'words  of priests and priestesses:'  (1) that true knowledge is a  knowledge  of causes (compare

Aristotle's theory of episteme); and (2) that  the  process of learning consists not in what is brought to the

learner, but  in what is drawn out of him. 

Some lesser points of the dialogue may be noted, such as (1) the  acute  observation that Meno prefers the

familiar definition, which is  embellished  with poetical language, to the better and truer one; or  (2) the shrewd

reflection, which may admit of an application to modern  as well as to  ancient teachers, that the Sophists

having made large  fortunes; this must  surely be a criterion of their powers of teaching,  for that no man could

get a living by shoemaking who was not a good  shoemaker; or (3) the remark  conveyed, almost in a word,

that the  verbal sceptic is saved the labour of  thought and enquiry (ouden dei  to toiouto zeteseos).

Characteristic also  of the temper of the  Socratic enquiry is, (4) the proposal to discuss the  teachableness of

virtue under an hypothesis, after the manner of the  mathematicians;  and (5) the repetition of the favourite

doctrine which  occurs so  frequently in the earlier and more Socratic Dialogues, and gives  a  colour to all of

themthat mankind only desire evil through ignorance;  (6) the experiment of eliciting from the slaveboy

the mathematical  truth  which is latent in him, and (7) the remark that he is all the  better for  knowing his

ignorance. 

The character of Meno, like that of Critias, has no relation to the  actual  circumstances of his life.  Plato is

silent about his treachery  to the ten  thousand Greeks, which Xenophon has recorded, as he is also  silent about

the crimes of Critias.  He is a Thessalian Alcibiades,  rich and luxurious  a spoilt child of fortune, and is

described as  the hereditary friend of the  great king.  Like Alcibiades he is  inspired with an ardent desire of

knowledge, and is equally willing to  learn of Socrates and of the Sophists.  He may be regarded as standing  in

the same relation to Gorgias as  Hippocrates in the Protagoras to  the other great Sophist.  He is the


Meno

Meno 4



Top




Page No 7


sophisticated youth on whom  Socrates tries his crossexamining powers, just  as in the Charmides,  the Lysis,

and the Euthydemus, ingenuous boyhood is  made the subject  of a similar experiment.  He is treated by

Socrates in a  halfplayful  manner suited to his character; at the same time he appears  not quite  to understand

the process to which he is being subjected.  For he  is  exhibited as ignorant of the very elements of dialectics,

in which the  Sophists have failed to instruct their disciple.  His definition of  virtue  as 'the power and desire of

attaining things honourable,' like  the first  definition of justice in the Republic, is taken from a poet.  His

answers  have a sophistical ring, and at the same time show the  sophistical  incapacity to grasp a general

notion. 

Anytus is the type of the narrowminded man of the world, who is  indignant  at innovation, and equally

detests the popular teacher and  the true  philosopher.  He seems, like Aristophanes, to regard the new  opinions,

whether of Socrates or the Sophists, as fatal to Athenian  greatness.  He is  of the same class as Callicles in the

Gorgias, but  of a different variety;  the immoral and sophistical doctrines of  Callicles are not attributed to  him.

The moderation with which he is  described is remarkable, if he be the  accuser of Socrates, as is  apparently

indicated by his parting words.  Perhaps Plato may have been  desirous of showing that the accusation of

Socrates was not to be  attributed to badness or malevolence, but rather to  a tendency in  men's minds.  Or he

may have been regardless of the  historical truth  of the characters of his dialogue, as in the case of Meno  and

Critias.  Like Chaerephon (Apol.) the real Anytus was a democrat, and  had  joined Thrasybulus in the conflict

with the thirty. 

The Protagoras arrived at a sort of hypothetical conclusion, that  if  'virtue is knowledge, it can be taught.'  In

the Euthydemus,  Socrates  himself offered an example of the manner in which the true  teacher may draw  out

the mind of youth; this was in contrast to the  quibbling follies of the  Sophists.  In the Meno the subject is

more  developed; the foundations of  the enquiry are laid deeper, and the  nature of knowledge is more

distinctly  explained.  There is a  progression by antagonism of two opposite aspects of  philosophy.  But  at the

moment when we approach nearest, the truth doubles  upon us and  passes out of our reach.  We seem to find

that the ideal of  knowledge  is irreconcilable with experience.  In human life there is indeed  the  profession of

knowledge, but right opinion is our actual guide.  There  is another sort of progress from the general notions of

Socrates, who  asked  simply, 'what is friendship?' 'what is temperance?' 'what is  courage?' as  in the Lysis,

Charmides, Laches, to the transcendentalism  of Plato, who, in  the second stage of his philosophy, sought to

find  the nature of knowledge  in a prior and future state of existence. 

The difficulty in framing general notions which has appeared in  this and in  all the previous Dialogues recurs

in the Gorgias and  Theaetetus as well as  in the Republic.  In the Gorgias too the  statesmen reappear, but in

stronger opposition to the philosopher.  They are no longer allowed to have  a divine insight, but, though

acknowledged to have been clever men and good  speakers, are denounced  as 'blind leaders of the blind.'  The

doctrine of  the immortality of  the soul is also carried further, being made the  foundation not only  of a theory

of knowledge, but of a doctrine of rewards  and  punishments.  In the Republic the relation of knowledge to

virtue is  described in a manner more consistent with modern distinctions.  The  existence of the virtues without

the possession of knowledge in the  higher  or philosophical sense is admitted to be possible.  Right  opinion is

again  introduced in the Theaetetus as an account of  knowledge, but is rejected on  the ground that it is

irrational (as  here, because it is not bound by the  tie of the cause), and also  because the conception of false

opinion is  given up as hopeless.  The  doctrines of Plato are necessarily different at  different times of his  life,

as new distinctions are realized, or new  stages of thought  attained by him.  We are not therefore justified, in

order to take  away the appearance of inconsistency, in attributing to him  hidden  meanings or remote

allusions. 

There are no external criteria by which we can determine the date  of the  Meno.  There is no reason to suppose

that any of the Dialogues  of Plato  were written before the death of Socrates; the Meno, which  appears to be

one of the earliest of them, is proved to have been of a  later date by the  allusion of Anytus. 


Meno

Meno 5



Top




Page No 8


We cannot argue that Plato was more likely to have written, as he  has done,  of Meno before than after his

miserable death; for we have  already seen, in  the examples of Charmides and Critias, that the  characters in

Plato are  very far from resembling the same characters  in history.  The repulsive  picture which is given of him

in the  Anabasis of Xenophon, where he also  appears as the friend of  Aristippus 'and a fair youth having

lovers,' has  no other trait of  likeness to the Meno of Plato. 

The place of the Meno in the series is doubtfully indicated by  internal  evidence.  The main character of the

Dialogue is Socrates;  but to the  'general definitions' of Socrates is added the Platonic  doctrine of

reminiscence.  The problems of virtue and knowledge have  been discussed in  the Lysis, Laches, Charmides,

and Protagoras; the  puzzle about knowing and  learning has already appeared in the  Euthydemus.  The

doctrines of  immortality and preexistence are  carried further in the Phaedrus and  Phaedo; the distinction

between  opinion and knowledge is more fully  developed in the Theaetetus.  The  lessons of Prodicus, whom he

facetiously  calls his master, are still  running in the mind of Socrates.  Unlike the  later Platonic Dialogues,  the

Meno arrives at no conclusion.  Hence we are  led to place the  Dialogue at some point of time later than the

Protagoras,  and earlier  than the Phaedrus and Gorgias.  The place which is assigned to  it in  this work is due

mainly to the desire to bring together in a single  volume all the Dialogues which contain allusions to the trial

and  death of  Socrates. 

... 

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO.

Plato's doctrine of ideas has attained an imaginary clearness and  definiteness which is not to be found in his

own writings.  The  popular  account of them is partly derived from one or two passages in  his Dialogues

interpreted without regard to their poetical  environment.  It is due also  to the misunderstanding of him by the

Aristotelian school; and the  erroneous notion has been further  narrowed and has become fixed by the  realism

of the schoolmen.  This  popular view of the Platonic ideas may be  summed up in some such  formula as the

following:  'Truth consists not in  particulars, but in  universals, which have a place in the mind of God, or  in

some faroff  heaven.  These were revealed to men in a former state of  existence,  and are recovered by

reminiscence (anamnesis) or association  from  sensible things.  The sensible things are not realities, but

shadows  only, in relation to the truth.'  These unmeaning propositions are  hardly  suspected to be a caricature

of a great theory of knowledge,  which Plato in  various ways and under many figures of speech is  seeking to

unfold.  Poetry  has been converted into dogma; and it is  not remarked that the Platonic  ideas are to be found

only in about a  third of Plato's writings and are not  confined to him.  The forms  which they assume are

numerous, and if taken  literally, inconsistent  with one another.  At one time we are in the clouds  of

mythology, at  another among the abstractions of mathematics or  metaphysics; we pass  imperceptibly from

one to the other.  Reason and fancy  are mingled in  the same passage.  The ideas are sometimes described as

many,  coextensive with the universals of sense and also with the first  principles of ethics; or again they are

absorbed into the single idea  of  good, and subordinated to it.  They are not more certain than  facts, but  they

are equally certain (Phaedo).  They are both personal  and impersonal.  They are abstract terms:  they are also

the causes of  things; and they are  even transformed into the demons or spirits by  whose help God made the

world.  And the idea of good (Republic) may  without violence be converted  into the Supreme Being, who

'because He  was good' created all things  (Tim.). 

It would be a mistake to try and reconcile these differing modes of  thought.  They are not to be regarded

seriously as having a distinct  meaning.  They are parables, prophecies, myths, symbols, revelations,

aspirations after an unknown world.  They derive their origin from a  deep  religious and contemplative feeling,

and also from an observation  of  curious mental phenomena.  They gather up the elements of the  previous

philosophies, which they put together in a new form.  Their  great diversity  shows the tentative character of

early endeavours to  think.  They have not  yet settled down into a single system.  Plato  uses them, though he


Meno

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 6



Top




Page No 9


also  criticises them; he acknowledges that both  he and others are always talking  about them, especially about

the Idea  of Good; and that they are not  peculiar to himself (Phaedo; Republic;  Soph.).  But in his later writings

he seems to have laid aside the old  forms of them.  As he proceeds he makes  for himself new modes of

expression more akin to the Aristotelian logic. 

Yet amid all these varieties and incongruities, there is a common  meaning  or spirit which pervades his

writings, both those in which he  treats of the  ideas and those in which he is silent about them.  This  is the

spirit of  idealism, which in the history of philosophy has had  many names and taken  many forms, and has in a

measure influenced those  who seemed to be most  averse to it.  It has often been charged with  inconsistency

and  fancifulness, and yet has had an elevating effect on  human nature, and has  exercised a wonderful charm

and interest over a  few spirits who have been  lost in the thought of it.  It has been  banished again and again,

but has  always returned.  It has attempted  to leave the earth and soar heavenwards,  but soon has found that

only  in experience could any solid foundation of  knowledge be laid.  It has  degenerated into pantheism, but

has again  emerged.  No other knowledge  has given an equal stimulus to the mind.  It  is the science of  sciences,

which are also ideas, and under either aspect  require to be  defined.  They can only be thought of in due

proportion when  conceived  in relation to one another.  They are the glasses through which  the  kingdoms of

science are seen, but at a distance.  All the greatest  minds, except when living in an age of reaction against

them, have  unconsciously fallen under their power. 

The account of the Platonic ideas in the Meno is the simplest and  clearest,  and we shall best illustrate their

nature by giving this  first and then  comparing the manner in which they are described  elsewhere, e.g. in the

Phaedrus, Phaedo, Republic; to which may be  added the criticism of them in  the Parmenides, the personal

form which  is attributed to them in the  Timaeus, the logical character which they  assume in the Sophist and

Philebus, and the allusion to them in the  Laws.  In the Cratylus they dawn  upon him with the freshness of a

newlydiscovered thought. 

The Meno goes back to a former state of existence, in which men did  and  suffered good and evil, and

received the reward or punishment of  them until  their sin was purged away and they were allowed to return  to

earth.  This  is a tradition of the olden time, to which priests and  poets bear witness.  The souls of men

returning to earth bring back a  latent memory of ideas,  which were known to them in a former state.  The

recollection is awakened  into life and consciousness by the sight  of the things which resemble them  on earth.

The soul evidently  possesses such innate ideas before she has  had time to acquire them.  This is proved by an

experiment tried on one of  Meno's slaves, from  whom Socrates elicits truths of arithmetic and  geometry,

which he had  never learned in this world.  He must therefore have  brought them with  him from another. 

The notion of a previous state of existence is found in the verses  of  Empedocles and in the fragments of

Heracleitus.  It was the natural  answer  to two questions, 'Whence came the soul?  What is the origin of  evil?'

and  prevailed far and wide in the east.  It found its way into  Hellas probably  through the medium of Orphic

and Pythagorean rites and  mysteries.  It was  easier to think of a former than of a future life,  because such a life

has  really existed for the race though not for the  individual, and all men come  into the world, if not 'trailing

clouds  of glory,' at any rate able to  enter into the inheritance of the past.  In the Phaedrus, as well as in the

Meno, it is this former rather  than a future life on which Plato is  disposed to dwell.  There the  Gods, and men

following in their train, go  forth to contemplate the  heavens, and are borne round in the revolutions of  them.

There they  see the divine forms of justice, temperance, and the  like, in their  unchangeable beauty, but not

without an effort more than  human.  The  soul of man is likened to a charioteer and two steeds, one  mortal, the

other immortal.  The charioteer and the mortal steed are in  fierce  conflict; at length the animal principle is

finally overpowered,  though not extinguished, by the combined energies of the passionate  and  rational

elements.  This is one of those passages in Plato which,  partaking  both of a philosophical and poetical

character, is  necessarily indistinct  and inconsistent.  The magnificent figure under  which the nature of the  soul

is described has not much to do with the  popular doctrine of the  ideas.  Yet there is one little trait in the

description which shows that  they are present to Plato's mind, namely,  the remark that the soul, which  had


Meno

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 7



Top




Page No 10


seen truths in the form of the  universal, cannot again return to the  nature of an animal. 

In the Phaedo, as in the Meno, the origin of ideas is sought for in  a  previous state of existence.  There was no

time when they could have  been  acquired in this life, and therefore they must have been  recovered from

another.  The process of recovery is no other than the  ordinary law of  association, by which in daily life the

sight of one  thing or person  recalls another to our minds, and by which in  scientific enquiry from any  part of

knowledge we may be led on to  infer the whole.  It is also argued  that ideas, or rather ideals, must  be derived

from a previous state of  existence because they are more  perfect than the sensible forms of them  which are

given by experience.  But in the Phaedo the doctrine of ideas is  subordinate to the proof  of the immortality of

the soul.  'If the soul  existed in a previous  state, then it will exist in a future state, for a  law of alternation

pervades all things.'  And, 'If the ideas exist, then  the soul exists;  if not, not.'  It is to be observed, both in the

Meno and  the Phaedo,  that Socrates expresses himself with diffidence.  He speaks in  the  Phaedo of the words

with which he has comforted himself and his  friends, and will not be too confident that the description which

he  has  given of the soul and her mansions is exactly true, but he  'ventures to  think that something of the kind

is true.'  And in the  Meno, after dwelling  upon the immortality of the soul, he adds, 'Of  some things which I

have  said I am not altogether confident' (compare  Apology; Gorgias).  From this  class of uncertainties he

exempts the  difference between truth and  appearance, of which he is absolutely  convinced. 

In the Republic the ideas are spoken of in two ways, which though  not  contradictory are different.  In the tenth

book they are  represented as the  genera or general ideas under which individuals  having a common name are

contained.  For example, there is the bed  which the carpenter makes, the  picture of the bed which is drawn by

the painter, the bed existing in  nature of which God is the author.  Of the latter all visible beds are only  the

shadows or reflections.  This and similar illustrations or explanations  are put forth, not for  their own sake, or

as an exposition of Plato's  theory of ideas, but  with a view of showing that poetry and the mimetic  arts are

concerned  with an inferior part of the soul and a lower kind of  knowledge.  On  the other hand, in the 6th and

7th books of the Republic we  reach the  highest and most perfect conception, which Plato is able to  attain, of

the nature of knowledge.  The ideas are now finally seen to be  one as  well as many, causes as well as ideas,

and to have a unity which is  the idea of good and the cause of all the rest.  They seem, however,  to  have lost

their first aspect of universals under which individuals  are  contained, and to have been converted into forms

of another kind,  which are  inconsistently regarded from the one side as images or  ideals of justice,

temperance, holiness and the like; from the other  as hypotheses, or  mathematical truths or principles. 

In the Timaeus, which in the series of Plato's works immediately  follows  the Republic, though probably

written some time afterwards, no  mention  occurs of the doctrine of ideas.  Geometrical forms and  arithmetical

ratios  furnish the laws according to which the world is  created.  But though the  conception of the ideas as

genera or species  is forgotten or laid aside,  the distinction of the visible and  intellectual is as firmly

maintained as  ever.  The IDEA of good  likewise disappears and is superseded by the  conception of a personal

God, who works according to a final cause or  principle of goodness  which he himself is.  No doubt is

expressed by Plato,  either in the  Timaeus or in any other dialogue, of the truths which he  conceives to  be the

first and highest.  It is not the existence of God or  the idea  of good which he approaches in a tentative or

hesitating manner,  but  the investigations of physiology.  These he regards, not seriously, as  a part of

philosophy, but as an innocent recreation (Tim.). 

Passing on to the Parmenides, we find in that dialogue not an  exposition or  defence of the doctrine of ideas,

but an assault upon  them, which is put  into the mouth of the veteran Parmenides, and might  be ascribed to

Aristotle himself, or to one of his disciples.  The  doctrine which is  assailed takes two or three forms, but fails

in any  of them to escape the  dialectical difficulties which are urged against  it.  It is admitted that  there are

ideas of all things, but the manner  in which individuals partake  of them, whether of the whole or of the  part,

and in which they become like  them, or how ideas can be either  within or without the sphere of human

knowledge, or how the human and  divine can have any relation to each other,  is held to be incapable of

explanation.  And yet, if there are no universal  ideas, what becomes  of philosophy?  (Parmenides.)  In the


Meno

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 8



Top




Page No 11


Sophist the  theory of ideas is  spoken of as a doctrine held not by Plato, but by  another sect of  philosophers,

called 'the Friends of Ideas,' probably the  Megarians,  who were very distinct from him, if not opposed to him

(Sophist).  Nor  in what may be termed Plato's abridgement of the history of  philosophy  (Soph.), is any

mention made such as we find in the first book  of  Aristotle's Metaphysics, of the derivation of such a theory

or of any  part of it from the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, the Heracleiteans, or  even  from Socrates.  In the

Philebus, probably one of the latest of  the Platonic  Dialogues, the conception of a personal or semipersonal

deity expressed  under the figure of mind, the king of all, who is also  the cause, is  retained.  The one and many

of the Phaedrus and  Theaetetus is still working  in the mind of Plato, and the correlation  of ideas, not of 'all

with all,'  but of 'some with some,' is asserted  and explained.  But they are spoken of  in a different manner, and

are  not supposed to be recovered from a former  state of existence.  The  metaphysical conception of truth

passes into a  psychological one,  which is continued in the Laws, and is the final form of  the Platonic

philosophy, so far as can be gathered from his own writings  (see  especially Laws).  In the Laws he harps once

more on the old string,  and returns to general notions:these he acknowledges to be many, and  yet  he insists

that they are also one.  The guardian must be made to  recognize  the truth, for which he has contended long

ago in the  Protagoras, that the  virtues are four, but they are also in some sense  one (Laws; compare

Protagoras). 

So various, and if regarded on the surface only, inconsistent, are  the  statements of Plato respecting the

doctrine of ideas.  If we  attempted to  harmonize or to combine them, we should make out of them,  not a

system, but  the caricature of a system.  They are the  evervarying expression of  Plato's Idealism.  The terms

used in them  are in their substance and  general meaning the same, although they  seem to be different.  They

pass  from the subject to the object, from  earth (diesseits) to heaven (jenseits)  without regard to the gulf  which

later theology and philosophy have made  between them.  They are  also intended to supplement or explain

each other.  They relate to a  subject of which Plato himself would have said that 'he  was not  confident of the

precise form of his own statements, but was strong  in  the belief that something of the kind was true.'  It is the

spirit, not  the letter, in which they agreethe spirit which places the divine  above  the human, the spiritual

above the material, the one above the  many, the  mind before the body. 

The stream of ancient philosophy in the Alexandrian and Roman times  widens  into a lake or sea, and then

disappears underground to reappear  after many  ages in a distant land.  It begins to flow again under new

conditions, at  first confined between high and narrow banks, but  finally spreading over  the continent of

Europe.  It is and is not the  same with ancient  philosophy.  There is a great deal in modern  philosophy which is

inspired  by ancient.  There is much in ancient  philosophy which was 'born out of due  time; and before men

were  capable of understanding it.  To the fathers of  modern philosophy,  their own thoughts appeared to be

new and original, but  they carried  with them an echo or shadow of the past, coming back by  recollection  from

an elder world.  Of this the enquirers of the seventeenth  century, who to themselves appeared to be working

out independently  the  enquiry into all truth, were unconscious.  They stood in a new  relation to  theology and

natural philosophy, and for a time maintained  towards both an  attitude of reserve and separation.  Yet the

similarities between modern  and ancient thought are greater far than  the differences.  All philosophy,  even

that part of it which is said  to be based upon experience, is really  ideal; and ideas are not only  derived from

facts, but they are also prior  to them and extend far  beyond them, just as the mind is prior to the  senses. 

Early Greek speculation culminates in the ideas of Plato, or rather  in the  single idea of good.  His followers,

and perhaps he himself,  having arrived  at this elevation, instead of going forwards went  backwards from

philosophy  to psychology, from ideas to numbers.  But  what we perceive to be the real  meaning of them, an

explanation of the  nature and origin of knowledge, will  always continue to be one of the  first problems of

philosophy. 

Plato also left behind him a most potent instrument, the forms of  logic  arms ready for use, but not yet

taken out of their armoury.  They were the  late birth of the early Greek philosophy, and were the  only part of

it  which has had an uninterrupted hold on the mind of  Europe.  Philosophies  come and go; but the detection of


Meno

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 9



Top




Page No 12


fallacies, the  framing of definitions,  the invention of methods still continue to be  the main elements of the

reasoning process. 

Modern philosophy, like ancient, begins with very simple  conceptions.  It  is almost wholly a reflection on

self.  It might be  described as a  quickening into life of old words and notions latent in  the semibarbarous

Latin, and putting a new meaning into them.  Unlike  ancient philosophy, it  has been unaffected by

impressions derived from  outward nature:  it arose  within the limits of the mind itself.  From  the time of

Descartes to Hume  and Kant it has had little or nothing to  do with facts of science.  On the  other hand, the

ancient and  mediaeval logic retained a continuous influence  over it, and a form  like that of mathematics was

easily impressed upon it;  the principle  of ancient philosophy which is most apparent in it is  scepticism; we

must doubt nearly every traditional or received notion, that  we may  hold fast one or two.  The being of God in

a personal or impersonal  form was a mental necessity to the first thinkers of modern times:  from  this alone all

other ideas could be deduced.  There had been an  obscure  presentiment of 'cognito, ergo sum' more than 2000

years  previously.  The  Eleatic notion that being and thought were the same  was revived in a new  form by

Descartes.  But now it gave birth to  consciousness and self  reflection:  it awakened the 'ego' in human  nature.

The mind naked and  abstract has no other certainty but the  conviction of its own existence.  'I think, therefore

I am;' and this  thought is God thinking in me, who has  also communicated to the reason  of man his own

attributes of thought and  extensionthese are truly  imparted to him because God is true (compare  Republic).

It has been  often remarked that Descartes, having begun by  dismissing all  presuppositions, introduces

several:  he passes almost at  once from  scepticism to dogmatism.  It is more important for the  illustration of

Plato to observe that he, like Plato, insists that God is  true and  incapable of deception (Republic)that he

proceeds from general  ideas, that many elements of mathematics may be found in him.  A  certain  influence of

mathematics both on the form and substance of  their philosophy  is discernible in both of them.  After making

the  greatest opposition  between thought and extension, Descartes, like  Plato, supposes them to be  reunited for

a time, not in their own  nature but by a special divine act  (compare Phaedrus), and he also  supposes all the

parts of the human body to  meet in the pineal gland,  that alone affording a principle of unity in the  material

frame of  man.  It is characteristic of the first period of modern  philosophy,  that having begun (like the

Presocratics) with a few general  notions,  Descartes first falls absolutely under their influence, and then

quickly discards them.  At the same time he is less able to observe  facts,  because they are too much magnified

by the glasses through  which they are  seen.  The common logic says 'the greater the  extension, the less the

comprehension,' and we may put the same  thought in another way and say of  abstract or general ideas, that

the  greater the abstraction of them, the  less are they capable of being  applied to particular and concrete

natures. 

Not very different from Descartes in his relation to ancient  philosophy is  his successor Spinoza, who lived in

the following  generation.  The system  of Spinoza is less personal and also less  dualistic than that of Descartes.

In this respect the difference  between them is like that between Xenophanes  and Parmenides.  The  teaching of

Spinoza might be described generally as  the Jewish  religion reduced to an abstraction and taking the form of

the  Eleatic  philosophy.  Like Parmenides, he is overpowered and intoxicated  with  the idea of Being or God.

The greatness of both philosophies consists  in the immensity of a thought which excludes all other thoughts;

their  weakness is the necessary separation of this thought from actual  existence  and from practical life.  In

neither of them is there any  clear opposition  between the inward and outward world.  The substance  of

Spinoza has two  attributes, which alone are cognizable by man,  thought and extension; these  are in extreme

opposition to one another,  and also in inseparable identity.  They may be regarded as the two  aspects or

expressions under which God or  substance is unfolded to  man.  Here a step is made beyond the limits of the

Eleatic philosophy.  The famous theorem of Spinoza, 'Omnis determinatio est  negatio,' is  already contained in

the 'negation is relation' of Plato's  Sophist.  The grand description of the philosopher in Republic VI, as the

spectator of all time and all existence, may be paralleled with  another  famous expression of Spinoza,

'Contemplatio rerum sub specie  eternitatis.'  According to Spinoza finite objects are unreal, for they  are

conditioned by  what is alien to them, and by one another.  Human  beings are included in  the number of them.

Hence there is no reality  in human action and no place  for right and wrong.  Individuality is  accident.  The


Meno

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 10



Top




Page No 13


boasted freedom of  the will is only a consciousness of  necessity.  Truth, he says, is the  direction of the reason

towards the  infinite, in which all things repose;  and herein lies the secret of  man's wellbeing.  In the

exaltation of the  reason or intellect, in  the denial of the voluntariness of evil (Timaeus;  Laws) Spinoza

approaches nearer to Plato than in his conception of an  infinite  substance.  As Socrates said that virtue is

knowledge, so Spinoza  would have maintained that knowledge alone is good, and what  contributes to

knowledge useful.  Both are equally far from any real  experience or  observation of nature.  And the same

difficulty is found  in both when we  seek to apply their ideas to life and practice.  There  is a gulf fixed  between

the infinite substance and finite objects or  individuals of  Spinoza, just as there is between the ideas of Plato

and the world of  sense. 

Removed from Spinoza by less than a generation is the philosopher  Leibnitz,  who after deepening and

intensifying the opposition between  mind and  matter, reunites them by his preconcerted harmony (compare

again Phaedrus).  To him all the particles of matter are living beings  which reflect on one  another, and in the

least of them the whole is  contained.  Here we catch a  reminiscence both of the omoiomere, or  similar

particles of Anaxagoras, and  of the worldanimal of the  Timaeus. 

In Bacon and Locke we have another development in which the mind of  man is  supposed to receive

knowledge by a new method and to work by  observation  and experience.  But we may remark that it is the

idea of  experience,  rather than experience itself, with which the mind is  filled.  It is a  symbol of knowledge

rather than the reality which is  vouchsafed to us.  The  Organon of Bacon is not much nearer to actual  facts

than the Organon of  Aristotle or the Platonic idea of good.  Many of the old rags and ribbons  which defaced

the garment of  philosophy have been stripped off, but some of  them still adhere.  A  crude conception of the

ideas of Plato survives in  the 'forms' of  Bacon.  And on the other hand, there are many passages of  Plato in

which the importance of the investigation of facts is as much  insisted  upon as by Bacon.  Both are almost

equally superior to the  illusions  of language, and are constantly crying out against them, as  against  other

idols. 

Locke cannot be truly regarded as the author of sensationalism any  more  than of idealism.  His system is

based upon experience, but with  him  experience includes reflection as well as sense.  His analysis and

construction of ideas has no foundation in fact; it is only the  dialectic  of the mind 'talking to herself.'  The

philosophy of  Berkeley is but the  transposition of two words.  For objects of sense  he would substitute

sensations.  He imagines himself to have changed  the relation of the human  mind towards God and nature;

they remain the  same as before, though he has  drawn the imaginary line by which they  are divided at a

different point.  He has annihilated the outward  world, but it instantly reappears governed  by the same laws

and  described under the same names. 

A like remark applies to David Hume, of whose philosophy the  central  principle is the denial of the relation

of cause and effect.  He would  deprive men of a familiar term which they can ill afford to  lose; but he  seems

not to have observed that this alteration is merely  verbal and does  not in any degree affect the nature of

things.  Still  less did he remark  that he was arguing from the necessary imperfection  of language against the

most certain facts.  And here, again, we may  find a parallel with the  ancients.  He goes beyond facts in his

scepticism, as they did in their  idealism.  Like the ancient Sophists,  he relegates the more important  principles

of ethics to custom and  probability.  But crude and unmeaning as  this philosophy is, it  exercised a great

influence on his successors, not  unlike that which  Locke exercised upon Berkeley and Berkeley upon Hume

himself.  All  three were both sceptical and ideal in almost equal degrees.  Neither  they nor their predecessors

had any true conception of language or  of  the history of philosophy.  Hume's paradox has been forgotten by

the  world, and did not any more than the scepticism of the ancients  require to  be seriously refuted.  Like some

other philosophical  paradoxes, it would  have been better left to die out.  It certainly  could not be refuted by a

philosophy such as Kant's, in which, no less  than in the previously  mentioned systems, the history of the

human  mind and the nature of language  are almost wholly ignored, and the  certainty of objective knowledge

is  transferred to the subject; while  absolute truth is reduced to a figment,  more abstract and narrow than


Meno

ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. 11



Top




Page No 14


Plato's ideas, of 'thing in itself,' to  which, if we reason strictly,  no predicate can be applied. 

The question which Plato has raised respecting the origin and  nature of  ideas belongs to the infancy of

philosophy; in modern times  it would no  longer be asked.  Their origin is only their history, so  far as we know

it;  there can be no other.  We may trace them in  language, in philosophy, in  mythology, in poetry, but we

cannot argue  a priori about them.  We may  attempt to shake them off, but they are  always returning, and in

every  sphere of science and human action are  tending to go beyond facts.  They  are thought to be innate,

because  they have been familiar to us all our  lives, and we can no longer  dismiss them from our mind.  Many

of them  express relations of terms  to which nothing exactly or nothing at all in  rerum natura  corresponds.  We

are not such free agents in the use of them  as we  sometimes imagine.  Fixed ideas have taken the most

complete  possession of some thinkers who have been most determined to renounce  them,  and have been

vehemently affirmed when they could be least  explained and  were incapable of proof.  The world has often

been led  away by a word to  which no distinct meaning could be attached.  Abstractions such as  'authority,'

'equality,' 'utility,' 'liberty,'  'pleasure,' 'experience,'  'consciousness,' 'chance,' 'substance,'  'matter,' 'atom,' and a

heap of  other metaphysical and theological  terms, are the source of quite as much  error and illusion and have

as  little relation to actual facts as the ideas  of Plato.  Few students  of theology or philosophy have sufficiently

reflected how quickly the  bloom of a philosophy passes away; or how hard it  is for one age to  understand the

writings of another; or how nice a  judgment is required  of those who are seeking to express the philosophy of

one age in the  terms of another.  The 'eternal truths' of which  metaphysicians speak  have hardly ever lasted

more than a generation.  In  our own day  schools or systems of philosophy which have once been famous  have

died  before the founders of them.  We are still, as in Plato's age,  groping  about for a new method more

comprehensive than any of those which  now  prevail; and also more permanent.  And we seem to see at a

distance the  promise of such a method, which can hardly be any other than the  method of  idealized

experience, having roots which strike far down  into the history  of philosophy.  It is a method which does not

divorce  the present from the  past, or the part from the whole, or the abstract  from the concrete, or  theory from

fact, or the divine from the human,  or one science from  another, but labours to connect them.  Along such  a

road we have proceeded  a few steps, sufficient, perhaps, to make us  reflect on the want of method  which

prevails in our own day.  In  another age, all the branches of  knowledge, whether relating to God or  man or

nature, will become the  knowledge of 'the revelation of a  single science' (Symp.), and all things,  like the stars

in heaven,  will shed their light upon one another. 

MENO

PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE:  Meno, Socrates, A Slave of Meno (Boy),  Anytus. 

MENO: Can you tell me, Socrates, whether virtue is acquired  by teaching or  by practice; or if neither by

teaching nor by practice,  then whether it  comes to man by nature, or in what other way? 

SOCRATES: O Meno, there was a time when the Thessalians were  famous among  the other Hellenes only

for their riches and their  riding; but now, if I am  not mistaken, they are equally famous for  their wisdom,

especially at  Larisa, which is the native city of your  friend Aristippus.  And this is  Gorgias' doing; for when he

came  there, the flower of the Aleuadae, among  them your admirer Aristippus,  and the other chiefs of the

Thessalians, fell  in love with his wisdom.  And he has taught you the habit of answering  questions in a grand

and  bold style, which becomes those who know, and is  the style in which he  himself answers all comers; and

any Hellene who likes  may ask him  anything.  How different is our lot! my dear Meno.  Here at  Athens  there

is a dearth of the commodity, and all wisdom seems to have  emigrated from us to you.  I am certain that if you

were to ask any  Athenian whether virtue was natural or acquired, he would laugh in  your  face, and say:

'Stranger, you have far too good an opinion of  me, if you  think that I can answer your question.  For I literally

do  not know what  virtue is, and much less whether it is acquired by  teaching or not.'  And I  myself, Meno,

living as I do in this region  of poverty, am as poor as the  rest of the world; and I confess with  shame that I


Meno

MENO 12



Top




Page No 15


know literally nothing  about virtue; and when I do not  know the 'quid' of anything how can I know  the

'quale'?  How, if I  knew nothing at all of Meno, could I tell if he was  fair, or the  opposite of fair; rich and

noble, or the reverse of rich and  noble?  Do you think that I could? 

MENO: No, indeed.  But are you in earnest, Socrates, in  saying that you do  not know what virtue is?  And am

I to carry back  this report of you to  Thessaly? 

SOCRATES: Not only that, my dear boy, but you may say  further that I have  never known of any one else

who did, in my  judgment. 

MENO: Then you have never met Gorgias when he was at Athens? 

SOCRATES: Yes, I have. 

MENO: And did you not think that he knew? 

SOCRATES: I have not a good memory, Meno, and therefore I  cannot now tell  what I thought of him at the

time.  And I dare say  that he did know, and  that you know what he said:  please, therefore,  to remind me of

what he  said; or, if you would rather, tell me your  own view; for I suspect that  you and he think much alike. 

MENO: Very true. 

SOCRATES: Then as he is not here, never mind him, and do you  tell me:  By  the gods, Meno, be generous,

and tell me what you say  that virtue is; for I  shall be truly delighted to find that I have  been mistaken, and that

you  and Gorgias do really have this knowledge;  although I have been just saying  that I have never found

anybody who  had. 

MENO: There will be no difficulty, Socrates, in answering  your question.  Let us take first the virtue of a

manhe should know  how to administer the  state, and in the administration of it to  benefit his friends and

harm his  enemies; and he must also be careful  not to suffer harm himself.  A woman's  virtue, if you wish to

know  about that, may also be easily described:  her  duty is to order her  house, and keep what is indoors, and

obey her husband.  Every age,  every condition of life, young or old, male or female, bond or  free,  has a

different virtue:  there are virtues numberless, and no lack of  definitions of them; for virtue is relative to the

actions and ages of  each  of us in all that we do.  And the same may be said of vice,  Socrates  (Compare Arist.

Pol.). 

SOCRATES: How fortunate I am, Meno!  When I ask you for one  virtue, you  present me with a swarm of

them (Compare Theaet.), which  are in your  keeping.  Suppose that I carry on the figure of the swarm,  and ask

of you,  What is the nature of the bee? and you answer that  there are many kinds of  bees, and I reply:  But do

bees differ as  bees, because there are many and  different kinds of them; or are they  not rather to be

distinguished by some  other quality, as for example  beauty, size, or shape?  How would you answer  me? 

MENO: I should answer that bees do not differ from one  another, as bees. 

SOCRATES: And if I went on to say:  That is what I desire to  know, Meno;  tell me what is the quality in

which they do not differ,  but are all  alike;would you be able to answer? 

MENO: I should. 

SOCRATES: And so of the virtues, however many and different  they may be,  they have all a common

nature which makes them virtues;  and on this he who  would answer the question, 'What is virtue?' would  do


Meno

MENO 13



Top




Page No 16


well to have his eye  fixed:  Do you understand? 

MENO: I am beginning to understand; but I do not as yet take  hold of the  question as I could wish. 

SOCRATES: When you say, Meno, that there is one virtue of a  man, another  of a woman, another of a child,

and so on, does this  apply only to virtue,  or would you say the same of health, and size,  and strength?  Or is

the  nature of health always the same, whether in  man or woman? 

MENO: I should say that health is the same, both in man and  woman. 

SOCRATES: And is not this true of size and strength?  If a  woman is  strong, she will be strong by reason of

the same form and of  the same  strength subsisting in her which there is in the man.  I mean  to say that

strength, as strength, whether of man or woman, is the  same.  Is there any  difference? 

MENO: I think not. 

SOCRATES: And will not virtue, as virtue, be the same,  whether in a child  or in a grownup person, in a

woman or in a man? 

MENO: I cannot help feeling, Socrates, that this case is  different from  the others. 

SOCRATES: But why?  Were you not saying that the virtue of a  man was to  order a state, and the virtue of a

woman was to order a  house? 

MENO: I did say so. 

SOCRATES: And can either house or state or anything be well  ordered  without temperance and without

justice? 

MENO: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: Then they who order a state or a house temperately  or justly  order them with temperance and

justice? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then both men and women, if they are to be good  men and women,  must have the same

virtues of temperance and justice? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And can either a young man or an elder one be  good, if they are  intemperate and unjust? 

MENO: They cannot. 

SOCRATES: They must be temperate and just? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then all men are good in the same way, and by  participation in  the same virtues? 


Meno

MENO 14



Top




Page No 17


MENO: Such is the inference. 

SOCRATES: And they surely would not have been good in the  same way, unless  their virtue had been the

same? 

MENO: They would not. 

SOCRATES: Then now that the sameness of all virtue has been  proven, try  and remember what you and

Gorgias say that virtue is. 

MENO: Will you have one definition of them all? 

SOCRATES: That is what I am seeking. 

MENO: If you want to have one definition of them all, I know  not what to  say, but that virtue is the power of

governing mankind. 

SOCRATES: And does this definition of virtue include all  virtue?  Is  virtue the same in a child and in a

slave, Meno?  Can the  child govern his  father, or the slave his master; and would he who  governed be any

longer a  slave? 

MENO: I think not, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: No, indeed; there would be small reason in that.  Yet once more,  fair friend; according to you,

virtue is 'the power of  governing;' but do  you not add 'justly and not unjustly'? 

MENO: Yes, Socrates; I agree there; for justice is virtue. 

SOCRATES: Would you say 'virtue,' Meno, or 'a virtue'? 

MENO: What do you mean? 

SOCRATES: I mean as I might say about anything; that a  round, for example,  is 'a figure' and not simply

'figure,' and I  should adopt this mode of  speaking, because there are other figures. 

MENO: Quite right; and that is just what I am saying about  virtuethat  there are other virtues as well as

justice. 

SOCRATES: What are they? tell me the names of them, as I  would tell you  the names of the other figures if

you asked me. 

MENO: Courage and temperance and wisdom and magnanimity are  virtues; and  there are many others. 

SOCRATES: Yes, Meno; and again we are in the same case:  in  searching  after one virtue we have found

many, though not in the same  way as before;  but we have been unable to find the common virtue which  runs

through them  all. 

MENO: Why, Socrates, even now I am not able to follow you in  the attempt  to get at one common notion of

virtue as of other things. 


Meno

MENO 15



Top




Page No 18


SOCRATES: No wonder; but I will try to get nearer if I can,  for you know  that all things have a common

notion.  Suppose now that  some one asked you  the question which I asked before:  Meno, he would  say, what

is figure?  And if you answered 'roundness,' he would reply  to you, in my way of  speaking, by asking whether

you would say that  roundness is 'figure' or 'a  figure;' and you would answer 'a figure.' 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And for this reasonthat there are other figures? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if he proceeded to ask, What other figures are  there? you  would have told him. 

MENO: I should. 

SOCRATES: And if he similarly asked what colour is, and you  answered  whiteness, and the questioner

rejoined, Would you say that  whiteness is  colour or a colour? you would reply, A colour, because  there are

other  colours as well. 

MENO: I should. 

SOCRATES: And if he had said, Tell me what they are?you  would have told  him of other colours which

are colours just as much as  whiteness. 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And suppose that he were to pursue the matter in  my way, he  would say:  Ever and anon we are

landed in particulars, but  this is not  what I want; tell me then, since you call them by a common  name, and

say  that they are all figures, even when opposed to one  another, what is that  common nature which you

designate as  figurewhich contains straight as  well as round, and is no more one  than the otherthat would

be your mode  of speaking? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And in speaking thus, you do not mean to say that  the round is  round any more than straight,

or the straight any more  straight than round? 

MENO: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: You only assert that the round figure is not more  a figure than  the straight, or the straight than

the round? 

MENO: Very true. 

SOCRATES: To what then do we give the name of figure?  Try  and answer.  Suppose that when a person

asked you this question either  about figure or  colour, you were to reply, Man, I do not understand  what you

want, or know  what you are saying; he would look rather  astonished and say:  Do you not  understand that I

am looking for the  'simile in multis'?  And then he might  put the question in another  form:  Meno, he might

say, what is that 'simile  in multis' which you  call figure, and which includes not only round and  straight

figures,  but all?  Could you not answer that question, Meno?  I  wish that you  would try; the attempt will be

good practice with a view to  the answer  about virtue. 


Meno

MENO 16



Top




Page No 19


MENO: I would rather that you should answer, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Shall I indulge you? 

MENO: By all means. 

SOCRATES: And then you will tell me about virtue? 

MENO: I will. 

SOCRATES: Then I must do my best, for there is a prize to be  won. 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Well, I will try and explain to you what figure  is.  What do you  say to this answer?Figure is

the only thing which  always follows colour.  Will you be satisfied with it, as I am sure  that I should be, if you

would  let me have a similar definition of  virtue? 

MENO: But, Socrates, it is such a simple answer. 

SOCRATES: Why simple? 

MENO: Because, according to you, figure is that which always  follows  colour. 

(SOCRATES:  Granted.) 

MENO: But if a person were to say that he does not know what  colour is,  any more than what figure

iswhat sort of answer would you  have given him? 

SOCRATES: I should have told him the truth.  And if he were  a philosopher  of the eristic and antagonistic

sort, I should say to  him:  You have my  answer, and if I am wrong, your business is to take  up the argument

and  refute me.  But if we were friends, and were  talking as you and I are now,  I should reply in a milder strain

and  more in the dialectician's vein; that  is to say, I should not only  speak the truth, but I should make use of

premisses which the person  interrogated would be willing to admit.  And  this is the way in which  I shall

endeavour to approach you.  You will  acknowledge, will you  not, that there is such a thing as an end, or

termination, or  extremity?all which words I use in the same sense,  although I am  aware that Prodicus

might draw distinctions about them:  but  still  you, I am sure, would speak of a thing as ended or

terminatedthat  is  all which I am sayingnot anything very difficult. 

MENO: Yes, I should; and I believe that I understand your  meaning. 

SOCRATES: And you would speak of a surface and also of a  solid, as for  example in geometry. 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Well then, you are now in a condition to  understand my  definition of figure.  I define figure to

be that in  which the solid ends;  or, more concisely, the limit of solid. 

MENO: And now, Socrates, what is colour? 


Meno

MENO 17



Top




Page No 20


SOCRATES: You are outrageous, Meno, in thus plaguing a poor  old man to  give you an answer, when you

will not take the trouble of  remembering what  is Gorgias' definition of virtue. 

MENO: When you have told me what I ask, I will tell you,  Socrates. 

SOCRATES: A man who was blindfolded has only to hear you  talking, and he  would know that you are a

fair creature and have still  many lovers. 

MENO: Why do you think so? 

SOCRATES: Why, because you always speak in imperatives:  like all beauties  when they are in their prime,

you are tyrannical;  and also, as I suspect,  you have found out that I have weakness for  the fair, and therefore

to  humour you I must answer. 

MENO: Please do. 

SOCRATES: Would you like me to answer you after the manner  of Gorgias,  which is familiar to you? 

MENO: I should like nothing better. 

SOCRATES: Do not he and you and Empedocles say that there  are certain  effluences of existence? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And passages into which and through which the  effluences pass? 

MENO: Exactly. 

SOCRATES: And some of the effluences fit into the passages,  and some of  them are too small or too large? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And there is such a thing as sight? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And now, as Pindar says, 'read my  meaning:'colour is an  effluence of form, commensurate

with sight,  and palpable to sense. 

MENO: That, Socrates, appears to me to be an admirable  answer. 

SOCRATES: Why, yes, because it happens to be one which you  have been in  the habit of hearing:  and your

wit will have discovered,  I suspect, that  you may explain in the same way the nature of sound  and smell, and

of many  other similar phenomena. 

MENO: Quite true. 

SOCRATES: The answer, Meno, was in the orthodox solemn vein,  and therefore  was more acceptable to

you than the other answer about  figure. 

MENO: Yes. 


Meno

MENO 18



Top




Page No 21


SOCRATES: And yet, O son of Alexidemus, I cannot help  thinking that the  other was the better; and I am

sure that you would  be of the same opinion,  if you would only stay and be initiated, and  were not compelled,

as you  said yesterday, to go away before the  mysteries. 

MENO: But I will stay, Socrates, if you will give me many  such answers. 

SOCRATES: Well then, for my own sake as well as for yours, I  will do my  very best; but I am afraid that I

shall not be able to give  you very many  as good:  and now, in your turn, you are to fulfil your  promise, and

tell  me what virtue is in the universal; and do not make  a singular into a  plural, as the facetious say of those

who break a  thing, but deliver virtue  to me whole and sound, and not broken into a  number of pieces:  I have

given you the pattern. 

MENO: Well then, Socrates, virtue, as I take it, is when he,  who desires  the honourable, is able to provide it

for himself; so the  poet says, and I  say too 

'Virtue is the desire of things honourable and the power of  attaining  them.' 

SOCRATES: And does he who desires the honourable also desire  the good? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then are there some who desire the evil and others  who desire  the good?  Do not all men, my

dear sir, desire good? 

MENO: I think not. 

SOCRATES: There are some who desire evil? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Do you mean that they think the evils which they  desire, to be  good; or do they know that they

are evil and yet desire  them? 

MENO: Both, I think. 

SOCRATES: And do you really imagine, Meno, that a man knows  evils to be  evils and desires them

notwithstanding? 

MENO: Certainly I do. 

SOCRATES: And desire is of possession? 

MENO: Yes, of possession. 

SOCRATES: And does he think that the evils will do good to  him who  possesses them, or does he know that

they will do him harm? 

MENO: There are some who think that the evils will do them  good, and  others who know that they will do

them harm. 


Meno

MENO 19



Top




Page No 22


SOCRATES: And, in your opinion, do those who think that they  will do them  good know that they are

evils? 

MENO: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: Is it not obvious that those who are ignorant of  their nature do  not desire them; but they desire

what they suppose to  be goods although  they are really evils; and if they are mistaken and  suppose the evils

to be  goods they really desire goods? 

MENO: Yes, in that case. 

SOCRATES: Well, and do those who, as you say, desire evils,  and think that  evils are hurtful to the

possessor of them, know that  they will be hurt by  them? 

MENO: They must know it. 

SOCRATES: And must they not suppose that those who are hurt  are miserable  in proportion to the hurt

which is inflicted upon them? 

MENO: How can it be otherwise? 

SOCRATES: But are not the miserable illfated? 

MENO: Yes, indeed. 

SOCRATES: And does any one desire to be miserable and  illfated? 

MENO: I should say not, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: But if there is no one who desires to be  miserable, there is no  one, Meno, who desires evil; for

what is misery  but the desire and  possession of evil? 

MENO: That appears to be the truth, Socrates, and I admit  that nobody  desires evil. 

SOCRATES: And yet, were you not saying just now that virtue  is the desire  and power of attaining good? 

MENO: Yes, I did say so. 

SOCRATES: But if this be affirmed, then the desire of good  is common to  all, and one man is no better than

another in that  respect? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And if one man is not better than another in  desiring good, he  must be better in the power of

attaining it? 

MENO: Exactly. 

SOCRATES: Then, according to your definition, virtue would  appear to be  the power of attaining good? 

MENO: I entirely approve, Socrates, of the manner in which  you now view  this matter. 


Meno

MENO 20



Top




Page No 23


SOCRATES: Then let us see whether what you say is true from  another point  of view; for very likely you

may be right:You affirm  virtue to be the  power of attaining goods? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the goods which you mean are such as health  and wealth and  the possession of gold and

silver, and having office  and honour in the  statethose are what you would call goods? 

MENO: Yes, I should include all those. 

SOCRATES: Then, according to Meno, who is the hereditary  friend of the  great king, virtue is the power of

getting silver and  gold; and would you  add that they must be gained piously, justly, or  do you deem this to be

of  no consequence?  And is any mode of  acquisition, even if unjust and  dishonest, equally to be deemed

virtue? 

MENO: Not virtue, Socrates, but vice. 

SOCRATES: Then justice or temperance or holiness, or some  other part of  virtue, as would appear, must

accompany the acquisition,  and without them  the mere acquisition of good will not be virtue. 

MENO: Why, how can there be virtue without these? 

SOCRATES: And the nonacquisition of gold and silver in a  dishonest manner  for oneself or another, or in

other words the want of  them, may be equally  virtue? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: Then the acquisition of such goods is no more  virtue than the  nonacquisition and want of

them, but whatever is  accompanied by justice or  honesty is virtue, and whatever is devoid of  justice is vice. 

MENO: It cannot be otherwise, in my judgment. 

SOCRATES: And were we not saying just now that justice,  temperance, and  the like, were each of them a

part of virtue? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And so, Meno, this is the way in which you mock  me. 

MENO: Why do you say that, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: Why, because I asked you to deliver virtue into my  hands whole  and unbroken, and I gave you

a pattern according to which  you were to frame  your answer; and you have forgotten already, and  tell me that

virtue is the  power of attaining good justly, or with  justice; and justice you  acknowledge to be a part of virtue. 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then it follows from your own admissions, that  virtue is doing  what you do with a part of

virtue; for justice and the  like are said by you  to be parts of virtue. 

MENO: What of that? 


Meno

MENO 21



Top




Page No 24


SOCRATES: What of that!  Why, did not I ask you to tell me  the nature of  virtue as a whole?  And you are

very far from telling me  this; but declare  every action to be virtue which is done with a part  of virtue; as

though  you had told me and I must already know the whole  of virtue, and this too  when frittered away into

little pieces.  And,  therefore, my dear Meno, I  fear that I must begin again and repeat the  same question:  What

is virtue?  for otherwise, I can only say, that  every action done with a part of virtue  is virtue; what else is the

meaning of saying that every action done with  justice is virtue?  Ought I not to ask the question over again;

for can any  one who does  not know virtue know a part of virtue? 

MENO: No; I do not say that he can. 

SOCRATES: Do you remember how, in the example of figure, we  rejected any  answer given in terms which

were as yet unexplained or  unadmitted? 

MENO: Yes, Socrates; and we were quite right in doing so. 

SOCRATES: But then, my friend, do not suppose that we can  explain to any  one the nature of virtue as a

whole through some  unexplained portion of  virtue, or anything at all in that fashion; we  should only have to

ask over  again the old question, What is virtue?  Am I not right? 

MENO: I believe that you are. 

SOCRATES: Then begin again, and answer me, What, according  to you and your  friend Gorgias, is the

definition of virtue? 

MENO: O Socrates, I used to be told, before I knew you, that  you were  always doubting yourself and

making others doubt; and now you  are casting  your spells over me, and I am simply getting bewitched and

enchanted, and  am at my wits' end.  And if I may venture to make a  jest upon you, you seem  to me both in

your appearance and in your  power over others to be very like  the flat torpedo fish, who torpifies  those who

come near him and touch him,  as you have now torpified me, I  think.  For my soul and my tongue are  really

torpid, and I do not know  how to answer you; and though I have been  delivered of an infinite  variety of

speeches about virtue before now, and  to many personsand  very good ones they were, as I thoughtat this

moment  I cannot even  say what virtue is.  And I think that you are very wise in  not  voyaging and going away

from home, for if you did in other places as  you do in Athens, you would be cast into prison as a magician. 

SOCRATES: You are a rogue, Meno, and had all but caught me. 

MENO: What do you mean, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: I can tell why you made a simile about me. 

MENO: Why? 

SOCRATES: In order that I might make another simile about  you.  For I know  that all pretty young

gentlemen like to have pretty  similes made about  themas well they maybut I shall not return the

compliment.  As to my  being a torpedo, if the torpedo is torpid as  well as the cause of torpidity  in others, then

indeed I am a torpedo,  but not otherwise; for I perplex  others, not because I am clear, but  because I am utterly

perplexed myself.  And now I know not what virtue  is, and you seem to be in the same case,  although you did

once perhaps  know before you touched me.  However, I have  no objection to join with  you in the enquiry. 

MENO: And how will you enquire, Socrates, into that which  you do not know?  What will you put forth as

the subject of enquiry?  And if you find what  you want, how will you ever know that this is  the thing which


Meno

MENO 22



Top




Page No 25


you did not  know? 

SOCRATES: I know, Meno, what you mean; but just see what a  tiresome  dispute you are introducing.  You

argue that a man cannot  enquire either  about that which he knows, or about that which he does  not know; for

if he  knows, he has no need to enquire; and if not, he  cannot; for he does not  know the very subject about

which he is to  enquire (Compare Aristot. Post.  Anal.). 

MENO: Well, Socrates, and is not the argument sound? 

SOCRATES: I think not. 

MENO: Why not? 

SOCRATES: I will tell you why:  I have heard from certain  wise men and  women who spoke of things

divine that 

MENO: What did they say? 

SOCRATES: They spoke of a glorious truth, as I conceive. 

MENO: What was it? and who were they? 

SOCRATES: Some of them were priests and priestesses, who had  studied how  they might be able to give a

reason of their profession:  there have been  poets also, who spoke of these things by inspiration,  like Pindar,

and many  others who were inspired.  And they saymark,  now, and see whether their  words are truethey

say that the soul of  man is immortal, and at one time  has an end, which is termed dying,  and at another time is

born again, but  is never destroyed.  And the  moral is, that a man ought to live always in  perfect holiness.  'For

in the ninth year Persephone sends the souls of  those from whom she  has received the penalty of ancient

crime back again  from beneath into  the light of the sun above, and these are they who become  noble kings

and mighty men and great in wisdom and are called saintly  heroes in  after ages.'  The soul, then, as being

immortal, and having been  born  again many times, and having seen all things that exist, whether in  this world

or in the world below, has knowledge of them all; and it is  no  wonder that she should be able to call to

remembrance all that she  ever  knew about virtue, and about everything; for as all nature is  akin, and the  soul

has learned all things; there is no difficulty in  her eliciting or as  men say learning, out of a single recollection

all  the rest, if a man is  strenuous and does not faint; for all enquiry  and all learning is but  recollection.  And

therefore we ought not to  listen to this sophistical  argument about the impossibility of  enquiry:  for it will

make us idle; and  is sweet only to the sluggard;  but the other saying will make us active and  inquisitive.  In

that  confiding, I will gladly enquire with you into the  nature of virtue. 

MENO: Yes, Socrates; but what do you mean by saying that we  do not learn,  and that what we call learning

is only a process of  recollection?  Can you  teach me how this is? 

SOCRATES: I told you, Meno, just now that you were a rogue,  and now you  ask whether I can teach you,

when I am saying that there  is no teaching,  but only recollection; and thus you imagine that you  will involve

me in a  contradiction. 

MENO: Indeed, Socrates, I protest that I had no such  intention.  I only  asked the question from habit; but if

you can prove  to me that what you say  is true, I wish that you would. 

SOCRATES: It will be no easy matter, but I will try to  please you to the  utmost of my power.  Suppose that

you call one of  your numerous attendants,  that I may demonstrate on him. 


Meno

MENO 23



Top




Page No 26


MENO: Certainly.  Come hither, boy. 

SOCRATES: He is Greek, and speaks Greek, does he not? 

MENO: Yes, indeed; he was born in the house. 

SOCRATES: Attend now to the questions which I ask him, and  observe whether  he learns of me or only

remembers. 

MENO: I will. 

SOCRATES: Tell me, boy, do you know that a figure like this  is a square? 

BOY: I do. 

SOCRATES: And you know that a square figure has these four  lines equal? 

BOY: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And these lines which I have drawn through the  middle of the  square are also equal? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: A square may be of any size? 

BOY: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And if one side of the figure be of two feet, and  the other side  be of two feet, how much will

the whole be?  Let me  explain:  if in one  direction the space was of two feet, and in the  other direction of one

foot, the whole would be of two feet taken  once? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But since this side is also of two feet, there are  twice two  feet? 

BOY: There are. 

SOCRATES: Then the square is of twice two feet? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And how many are twice two feet? count and tell  me. 

BOY: Four, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: And might there not be another square twice as  large as this,  and having like this the lines

equal? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And of how many feet will that be? 


Meno

MENO 24



Top




Page No 27


BOY: Of eight feet. 

SOCRATES: And now try and tell me the length of the line  which forms the  side of that double square:  this

is two feetwhat  will that be? 

BOY: Clearly, Socrates, it will be double. 

SOCRATES: Do you observe, Meno, that I am not teaching the  boy anything,  but only asking him

questions; and now he fancies that  he knows how long a  line is necessary in order to produce a figure of  eight

square feet; does  he not? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And does he really know? 

MENO: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: He only guesses that because the square is double,  the line is  double. 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: Observe him while he recalls the steps in regular  order.  (To  the Boy:)  Tell me, boy, do you

assert that a double space  comes from a  double line?  Remember that I am not speaking of an  oblong, but of a

figure  equal every way, and twice the size of  thisthat is to say of eight feet;  and I want to know whether

you  still say that a double square comes from  double line? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But does not this line become doubled if we add  another such  line here? 

BOY: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And four such lines will make a space containing  eight feet? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Let us describe such a figure:  Would you not say  that this is  the figure of eight feet? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And are there not these four divisions in the  figure, each of  which is equal to the figure of four

feet? 

BOY: True. 

SOCRATES: And is not that four times four? 

BOY: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And four times is not double? 


Meno

MENO 25



Top




Page No 28


BOY: No, indeed. 

SOCRATES: But how much? 

BOY: Four times as much. 

SOCRATES: Therefore the double line, boy, has given a space,  not twice,  but four times as much. 

BOY: True. 

SOCRATES: Four times four are sixteenare they not? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: What line would give you a space of eight feet, as  this gives  one of sixteen feet;do you see? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the space of four feet is made from this half  line? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Good; and is not a space of eight feet twice the  size of this,  and half the size of the other? 

BOY: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Such a space, then, will be made out of a line  greater than this  one, and less than that one? 

BOY: Yes; I think so. 

SOCRATES: Very good; I like to hear you say what you think.  And now tell  me, is not this a line of two

feet and that of four? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then the line which forms the side of eight feet  ought to be  more than this line of two feet, and

less than the other  of four feet? 

BOY: It ought. 

SOCRATES: Try and see if you can tell me how much it will  be. 

BOY: Three feet. 

SOCRATES: Then if we add a half to this line of two, that  will be the line  of three.  Here are two and there is

one; and on the  other side, here are  two also and there is one:  and that makes the  figure of which you speak? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But if there are three feet this way and three  feet that way,  the whole space will be three times

three feet? 


Meno

MENO 26



Top




Page No 29


BOY: That is evident. 

SOCRATES: And how much are three times three feet? 

BOY: Nine. 

SOCRATES: And how much is the double of four? 

BOY: Eight. 

SOCRATES: Then the figure of eight is not made out of a line  of three? 

BOY: No. 

SOCRATES: But from what line?tell me exactly; and if you  would rather  not reckon, try and show me

the line. 

BOY: Indeed, Socrates, I do not know. 

SOCRATES: Do you see, Meno, what advances he has made in his  power of  recollection?  He did not know

at first, and he does not know  now, what is  the side of a figure of eight feet:  but then he thought  that he knew,

and  answered confidently as if he knew, and had no  difficulty; now he has a  difficulty, and neither knows nor

fancies  that he knows. 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: Is he not better off in knowing his ignorance? 

MENO: I think that he is. 

SOCRATES: If we have made him doubt, and given him the  'torpedo's shock,'  have we done him any harm? 

MENO: I think not. 

SOCRATES: We have certainly, as would seem, assisted him in  some degree to  the discovery of the truth;

and now he will wish to  remedy his ignorance,  but then he would have been ready to tell all  the world again

and again  that the double space should have a double  side. 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: But do you suppose that he would ever have  enquired into or  learned what he fancied that he

knew, though he was  really ignorant of it,  until he had fallen into perplexity under the  idea that he did not

know,  and had desired to know? 

MENO: I think not, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Then he was the better for the torpedo's touch? 

MENO: I think so. 


Meno

MENO 27



Top




Page No 30


SOCRATES: Mark now the farther development.  I shall only  ask him, and not  teach him, and he shall share

the enquiry with me:  and do you watch and  see if you find me telling or explaining  anything to him, instead

of  eliciting his opinion.  Tell me, boy, is  not this a square of four feet  which I have drawn? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And now I add another square equal to the former  one? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And a third, which is equal to either of them? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Suppose that we fill up the vacant corner? 

BOY: Very good. 

SOCRATES: Here, then, there are four equal spaces? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And how many times larger is this space than this  other? 

BOY: Four times. 

SOCRATES: But it ought to have been twice only, as you will  remember. 

BOY: True. 

SOCRATES: And does not this line, reaching from corner to  corner, bisect  each of these spaces? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And are there not here four equal lines which  contain this  space? 

BOY: There are. 

SOCRATES: Look and see how much this space is. 

BOY: I do not understand. 

SOCRATES: Has not each interior line cut off half of the  four spaces? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And how many spaces are there in this section? 

BOY: Four. 

SOCRATES: And how many in this? 


Meno

MENO 28



Top




Page No 31


BOY: Two. 

SOCRATES: And four is how many times two? 

BOY: Twice. 

SOCRATES: And this space is of how many feet? 

BOY: Of eight feet. 

SOCRATES: And from what line do you get this figure? 

BOY: From this. 

SOCRATES: That is, from the line which extends from corner  to corner of  the figure of four feet? 

BOY: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And that is the line which the learned call the  diagonal.  And  if this is the proper name, then

you, Meno's slave, are  prepared to affirm  that the double space is the square of the  diagonal? 

BOY: Certainly, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: What do you say of him, Meno?  Were not all these  answers given  out of his own head? 

MENO: Yes, they were all his own. 

SOCRATES: And yet, as we were just now saying, he did not  know? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: But still he had in him those notions of hishad  he not? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then he who does not know may still have true  notions of that  which he does not know? 

MENO: He has. 

SOCRATES: And at present these notions have just been  stirred up in him,  as in a dream; but if he were

frequently asked the  same questions, in  different forms, he would know as well as any one  at last? 

MENO: I dare say. 

SOCRATES: Without any one teaching him he will recover his  knowledge for  himself, if he is only asked

questions? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And this spontaneous recovery of knowledge in him  is  recollection? 


Meno

MENO 29



Top




Page No 32


MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And this knowledge which he now has must he not  either have  acquired or always possessed? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But if he always possessed this knowledge he would  always have  known; or if he has acquired

the knowledge he could not  have acquired it in  this life, unless he has been taught geometry; for  he may be

made to do the  same with all geometry and every other branch  of knowledge.  Now, has any  one ever taught

him all this?  You must  know about him, if, as you say, he  was born and bred in your house. 

MENO: And I am certain that no one ever did teach him. 

SOCRATES: And yet he has the knowledge? 

MENO: The fact, Socrates, is undeniable. 

SOCRATES: But if he did not acquire the knowledge in this  life, then he  must have had and learned it at

some other time? 

MENO: Clearly he must. 

SOCRATES: Which must have been the time when he was not a  man? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if there have been always true thoughts in  him, both at the  time when he was and was not

a man, which only need  to be awakened into  knowledge by putting questions to him, his soul  must have

always possessed  this knowledge, for he always either was or  was not a man? 

MENO: Obviously. 

SOCRATES: And if the truth of all things always existed in  the soul, then  the soul is immortal.  Wherefore

be of good cheer, and  try to recollect  what you do not know, or rather what you do not  remember. 

MENO: I feel, somehow, that I like what you are saying. 

SOCRATES: And I, Meno, like what I am saying.  Some things I  have said of  which I am not altogether

confident.  But that we shall  be better and  braver and less helpless if we think that we ought to  enquire, than

we  should have been if we indulged in the idle fancy  that there was no knowing  and no use in seeking to

know what we do not  know;that is a theme upon  which I am ready to fight, in word and  deed, to the

utmost of my power. 

MENO: There again, Socrates, your words seem to me  excellent. 

SOCRATES: Then, as we are agreed that a man should enquire  about that  which he does not know, shall

you and I make an effort to  enquire together  into the nature of virtue? 

MENO: By all means, Socrates.  And yet I would much rather  return to my  original question, Whether in

seeking to acquire virtue  we should regard it  as a thing to be taught, or as a gift of nature,  or as coming to

men in  some other way? 


Meno

MENO 30



Top




Page No 33


SOCRATES: Had I the command of you as well as of myself,  Meno, I would not  have enquired whether

virtue is given by instruction  or not, until we had  first ascertained 'what it is.'  But as you think  only of

controlling me  who am your slave, and never of controlling  yourself,such being your  notion of freedom, I

must yield to you, for  you are irresistible.  And  therefore I have now to enquire into the  qualities of a thing of

which I do  not as yet know the nature.  At any  rate, will you condescend a little, and  allow the question

'Whether  virtue is given by instruction, or in any other  way,' to be argued  upon hypothesis?  As the

geometrician, when he is asked  whether a  certain triangle is capable being inscribed in a certain circle  (Or,

whether a certain area is capable of being inscribed as a triangle in  a certain circle.), will reply:  'I cannot tell

you as yet; but I will  offer a hypothesis which may assist us in forming a conclusion:  If  the  figure be such that

when you have produced a given side of it (Or,  when you  apply it to the given line, i.e. the diameter of the

circle  (autou).), the  given area of the triangle falls short by an area  corresponding to the part  produced (Or,

similar to the area so  applied.), then one consequence  follows, and if this is impossible  then some other; and

therefore I wish to  assume a hypothesis before I  tell you whether this triangle is capable of  being inscribed in

the  circle':that is a geometrical hypothesis.  And we  too, as we know  not the nature and qualities of virtue,

must ask, whether  virtue is or  is not taught, under a hypothesis:  as thus, if virtue is of  such a  class of mental

goods, will it be taught or not?  Let the first  hypothesis be that virtue is or is not knowledge,in that case will

it be  taught or not? or, as we were just now saying, 'remembered'?  For there is  no use in disputing about the

name.  But is virtue  taught or not? or  rather, does not every one see that knowledge alone  is taught? 

MENO: I agree. 

SOCRATES: Then if virtue is knowledge, virtue will be  taught? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then now we have made a quick end of this  question:  if virtue  is of such a nature, it will be

taught; and if  not, not? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: The next question is, whether virtue is knowledge  or of another  species? 

MENO: Yes, that appears to be the question which comes next  in order. 

SOCRATES: Do we not say that virtue is a good?This is a  hypothesis which  is not set aside. 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Now, if there be any sort of good which is  distinct from  knowledge, virtue may be that good;

but if knowledge  embraces all good,  then we shall be right in thinking that virtue is  knowledge? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And virtue makes us good? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if we are good, then we are profitable; for  all good things  are profitable? 

MENO: Yes. 


Meno

MENO 31



Top




Page No 34


SOCRATES: Then virtue is profitable? 

MENO: That is the only inference. 

SOCRATES: Then now let us see what are the things which  severally profit  us.  Health and strength, and

beauty and  wealththese, and the like of  these, we call profitable? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And yet these things may also sometimes do us  harm:  would you  not think so? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And what is the guiding principle which makes them  profitable or  the reverse?  Are they not

profitable when they are  rightly used, and  hurtful when they are not rightly used? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Next, let us consider the goods of the soul:  they  are  temperance, justice, courage, quickness of

apprehension, memory,  magnanimity, and the like? 

MENO: Surely. 

SOCRATES: And such of these as are not knowledge, but of  another sort, are  sometimes profitable and

sometimes hurtful; as, for  example, courage  wanting prudence, which is only a sort of confidence?  When a

man has no  sense he is harmed by courage, but when he has  sense he is profited? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And the same may be said of temperance and  quickness of  apprehension; whatever things are

learned or done with  sense are  profitable, but when done without sense they are hurtful? 

MENO: Very true. 

SOCRATES: And in general, all that the soul attempts or  endures, when  under the guidance of wisdom, ends

in happiness; but  when she is under the  guidance of folly, in the opposite? 

MENO: That appears to be true. 

SOCRATES: If then virtue is a quality of the soul, and is  admitted to be  profitable, it must be wisdom or

prudence, since none  of the things of the  soul are either profitable or hurtful in  themselves, but they are all

made  profitable or hurtful by the  addition of wisdom or of folly; and therefore  if virtue is profitable,  virtue

must be a sort of wisdom or prudence? 

MENO: I quite agree. 

SOCRATES: And the other goods, such as wealth and the like,  of which we  were just now saying that they

are sometimes good and  sometimes evil, do  not they also become profitable or hurtful,  accordingly as the

soul guides  and uses them rightly or wrongly; just  as the things of the soul herself  are benefited when under

the  guidance of wisdom and harmed by folly? 


Meno

MENO 32



Top




Page No 35


MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And the wise soul guides them rightly, and the  foolish soul  wrongly. 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And is not this universally true of human nature?  All other  things hang upon the soul, and the

things of the soul  herself hang upon  wisdom, if they are to be good; and so wisdom is  inferred to be that

which  profitsand virtue, as we say, is  profitable? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And thus we arrive at the conclusion that virtue  is either  wholly or partly wisdom? 

MENO: I think that what you are saying, Socrates, is very  true. 

SOCRATES: But if this is true, then the good are not by  nature good? 

MENO: I think not. 

SOCRATES: If they had been, there would assuredly have been  discerners of  characters among us who

would have known our future  great men; and on their  showing we should have adopted them, and when  we

had got them, we should  have kept them in the citadel out of the  way of harm, and set a stamp upon  them far

rather than upon a piece of  gold, in order that no one might  tamper with them; and when they grew  up they

would have been useful to the  state? 

MENO: Yes, Socrates, that would have been the right way. 

SOCRATES: But if the good are not by nature good, are they  made good by  instruction? 

MENO: There appears to be no other alternative, Socrates.  On the  supposition that virtue is knowledge, there

can be no doubt  that virtue is  taught. 

SOCRATES: Yes, indeed; but what if the supposition is  erroneous? 

MENO: I certainly thought just now that we were right. 

SOCRATES: Yes, Meno; but a principle which has any soundness  should stand  firm not only just now, but

always. 

MENO: Well; and why are you so slow of heart to believe that  knowledge is  virtue? 

SOCRATES: I will try and tell you why, Meno.  I do not  retract the  assertion that if virtue is knowledge it

may be taught;  but I fear that I  have some reason in doubting whether virtue is  knowledge:  for consider now

and say whether virtue, and not only  virtue but anything that is taught,  must not have teachers and  disciples? 

MENO: Surely. 

SOCRATES: And conversely, may not the art of which neither  teachers nor  disciples exist be assumed to be

incapable of being  taught? 


Meno

MENO 33



Top




Page No 36


MENO: True; but do you think that there are no teachers of  virtue? 

SOCRATES: I have certainly often enquired whether there were  any, and  taken great pains to find them, and

have never succeeded; and  many have  assisted me in the search, and they were the persons whom I  thought

the  most likely to know.  Here at the moment when he is wanted  we fortunately  have sitting by us Anytus, the

very person of whom we  should make enquiry;  to him then let us repair.  In the first place,  he is the son of a

wealthy  and wise father, Anthemion, who acquired  his wealth, not by accident or  gift, like Ismenias the

Theban (who has  recently made himself as rich as  Polycrates), but by his own skill and  industry, and who is a

well  conditioned, modest man, not insolent, or  overbearing, or annoying;  moreover, this son of his has

received a  good education, as the Athenian  people certainly appear to think, for  they choose him to fill the

highest  offices.  And these are the sort  of men from whom you are likely to learn  whether there are any

teachers of virtue, and who they are.  Please,  Anytus, to help me and  your friend Meno in answering our

question, Who are  the teachers?  Consider the matter thus:  If we wanted Meno to be a good  physician,  to

whom should we send him?  Should we not send him to the  physicians? 

ANYTUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Or if we wanted him to be a good cobbler, should  we not send him  to the cobblers? 

ANYTUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And so forth? 

ANYTUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Let me trouble you with one more question.  When  we say that we  should be right in sending

him to the physicians if we  wanted him to be a  physician, do we mean that we should be right in  sending him

to those who  profess the art, rather than to those who do  not, and to those who demand  payment for teaching

the art, and profess  to teach it to any one who will  come and learn?  And if these were our  reasons, should we

not be right in  sending him? 

ANYTUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And might not the same be said of fluteplaying,  and of the  other arts?  Would a man who

wanted to make another a  fluteplayer refuse  to send him to those who profess to teach the art  for money,

and be  plaguing other persons to give him instruction, who  are not professed  teachers and who never had a

single disciple in that  branch of knowledge  which he wishes him to acquirewould not such  conduct be the

height of  folly? 

ANYTUS: Yes, by Zeus, and of ignorance too. 

SOCRATES: Very good.  And now you are in a position to  advise with me  about my friend Meno.  He has

been telling me, Anytus,  that he desires to  attain that kind of wisdom and virtue by which men  order the state

or the  house, and honour their parents, and know when  to receive and when to send  away citizens and

strangers, as a good man  should.  Now, to whom should he  go in order that he may learn this  virtue?  Does not

the previous argument  imply clearly that we should  send him to those who profess and avouch that  they are

the common  teachers of all Hellas, and are ready to impart  instruction to any one  who likes, at a fixed price? 

ANYTUS: Whom do you mean, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: You surely know, do you not, Anytus, that these  are the people  whom mankind call Sophists? 


Meno

MENO 34



Top




Page No 37


ANYTUS: By Heracles, Socrates, forbear!  I only hope that no  friend or  kinsman or acquaintance of mine,

whether citizen or  stranger, will ever be  so mad as to allow himself to be corrupted by  them; for they are a

manifest  pest and corrupting influence to those  who have to do with them. 

SOCRATES: What, Anytus?  Of all the people who profess that  they know how  to do men good, do you

mean to say that these are the  only ones who not  only do them no good, but positively corrupt those  who are

entrusted to  them, and in return for this disservice have the  face to demand money?  Indeed, I cannot believe

you; for I know of a  single man, Protagoras, who  made more out of his craft than the  illustrious Pheidias,

who created such  noble works, or any ten other  statuaries.  How could that be?  A mender of  old shoes, or

patcher up  of clothes, who made the shoes or clothes worse  than he received them,  could not have remained

thirty days undetected, and  would very soon  have starved; whereas during more than forty years,  Protagoras

was  corrupting all Hellas, and sending his disciples from him  worse than  he received them, and he was never

found out.  For, if I am not  mistaken, he was about seventy years old at his death, forty of which  were  spent in

the practice of his profession; and during all that time  he had a  good reputation, which to this day he retains:

and not only  Protagoras,  but many others are well spoken of; some who lived before  him, and others  who are

still living.  Now, when you say that they  deceived and corrupted  the youth, are they to be supposed to have

corrupted them consciously or  unconsciously?  Can those who were  deemed by many to be the wisest men of

Hellas have been out of their  minds? 

ANYTUS: Out of their minds!  No, Socrates; the young men who  gave their  money to them were out of their

minds, and their relations  and guardians  who entrusted their youth to the care of these men were  still more

out of  their minds, and most of all, the cities who allowed  them to come in, and  did not drive them out,

citizen and stranger  alike. 

SOCRATES: Has any of the Sophists wronged you, Anytus?  What  makes you so  angry with them? 

ANYTUS: No, indeed, neither I nor any of my belongings has  ever had, nor  would I suffer them to have,

anything to do with them. 

SOCRATES: Then you are entirely unacquainted with them? 

ANYTUS: And I have no wish to be acquainted. 

SOCRATES: Then, my dear friend, how can you know whether a  thing is good  or bad of which you are

wholly ignorant? 

ANYTUS: Quite well; I am sure that I know what manner of men  these are,  whether I am acquainted with

them or not. 

SOCRATES: You must be a diviner, Anytus, for I really cannot  make out,  judging from your own words,

how, if you are not acquainted  with them, you  know about them.  But I am not enquiring of you who are  the

teachers who  will corrupt Meno (let them be, if you please, the  Sophists); I only ask  you to tell him who there

is in this great city  who will teach him how to  become eminent in the virtues which I was  just now

describing.  He is the  friend of your family, and you will  oblige him. 

ANYTUS: Why do you not tell him yourself? 

SOCRATES: I have told him whom I supposed to be the teachers  of these  things; but I learn from you that I

am utterly at fault, and  I dare say  that you are right.  And now I wish that you, on your part,  would tell me  to

whom among the Athenians he should go.  Whom would  you name? 


Meno

MENO 35



Top




Page No 38


ANYTUS: Why single out individuals?  Any Athenian gentleman,  taken at  random, if he will mind him, will

do far more good to him  than the  Sophists. 

SOCRATES: And did those gentlemen grow of themselves; and  without having  been taught by any one,

were they nevertheless able to  teach others that  which they had never learned themselves? 

ANYTUS: I imagine that they learned of the previous  generation of  gentlemen.  Have there not been many

good men in this  city? 

SOCRATES: Yes, certainly, Anytus; and many good statesmen  also there  always have been and there are

still, in the city of  Athens.  But the  question is whether they were also good teachers of  their own virtue;not

whether there are, or have been, good men in  this part of the world, but  whether virtue can be taught, is the

question which we have been  discussing.  Now, do we mean to say that  the good men of our own and of  other

times knew how to impart to  others that virtue which they had  themselves; or is virtue a thing  incapable of

being communicated or  imparted by one man to another?  That is the question which I and Meno have  been

arguing.  Look at the  matter in your own way:  Would you not admit  that Themistocles was a  good man? 

ANYTUS: Certainly; no man better. 

SOCRATES: And must not he then have been a good teacher, if  any man ever  was a good teacher, of his

own virtue? 

ANYTUS: Yes certainly,if he wanted to be so. 

SOCRATES: But would he not have wanted?  He would, at any  rate, have  desired to make his own son a

good man and a gentleman; he  could not have  been jealous of him, or have intentionally abstained  from

imparting to him  his own virtue.  Did you never hear that he made  his son Cleophantus a  famous horseman;

and had him taught to stand  upright on horseback and hurl  a javelin, and to do many other  marvellous things;

and in anything which  could be learned from a  master he was well trained?  Have you not heard  from our

elders of  him? 

ANYTUS: I have. 

SOCRATES: Then no one could say that his son showed any want  of capacity? 

ANYTUS: Very likely not. 

SOCRATES: But did any one, old or young, ever say in your  hearing that  Cleophantus, son of Themistocles,

was a wise or good man,  as his father  was? 

ANYTUS: I have certainly never heard any one say so. 

SOCRATES: And if virtue could have been taught, would his  father  Themistocles have sought to train him

in these minor  accomplishments, and  allowed him who, as you must remember, was his  own son, to be no

better  than his neighbours in those qualities in  which he himself excelled? 

ANYTUS: Indeed, indeed, I think not. 

SOCRATES: Here was a teacher of virtue whom you admit to be  among the best  men of the past.  Let us

take another,Aristides, the  son of Lysimachus:  would you not acknowledge that he was a good man? 


Meno

MENO 36



Top




Page No 39


ANYTUS: To be sure I should. 

SOCRATES: And did not he train his son Lysimachus better  than any other  Athenian in all that could be

done for him by the help  of masters?  But  what has been the result?  Is he a bit better than  any other mortal?

He is  an acquaintance of yours, and you see what he  is like.  There is Pericles,  again, magnificent in his

wisdom; and he,  as you are aware, had two sons,  Paralus and Xanthippus. 

ANYTUS: I know. 

SOCRATES: And you know, also, that he taught them to be  unrivalled  horsemen, and had them trained in

music and gymnastics and  all sorts of  artsin these respects they were on a level with the  bestand had he

no  wish to make good men of them?  Nay, he must have  wished it.  But virtue,  as I suspect, could not be

taught.  And that  you may not suppose the  incompetent teachers to be only the meaner  sort of Athenians and

few in  number, remember again that Thucydides  had two sons, Melesias and  Stephanus, whom, besides

giving them a good  education in other things, he  trained in wrestling, and they were the  best wrestlers in

Athens:  one of  them he committed to the care of  Xanthias, and the other of Eudorus, who  had the reputation

of being  the most celebrated wrestlers of that day.  Do  you remember them? 

ANYTUS: I have heard of them. 

SOCRATES: Now, can there be a doubt that Thucydides, whose  children were  taught things for which he

had to spend money, would  have taught them to be  good men, which would have cost him nothing, if  virtue

could have been  taught?  Will you reply that he was a mean man,  and had not many friends  among the

Athenians and allies?  Nay, but he  was of a great family, and a  man of influence at Athens and in all  Hellas,

and, if virtue could have  been taught, he would have found out  some Athenian or foreigner who would  have

made good men of his sons,  if he could not himself spare the time from  cares of state.  Once  more, I suspect,

friend Anytus, that virtue is not a  thing which can  be taught? 

ANYTUS: Socrates, I think that you are too ready to speak  evil of men:  and, if you will take my advice, I

would recommend you to  be careful.  Perhaps there is no city in which it is not easier to do  men harm than to

do them good, and this is certainly the case at  Athens, as I believe that  you know. 

SOCRATES: O Meno, think that Anytus is in a rage.  And he  may well be in a  rage, for he thinks, in the first

place, that I am  defaming these  gentlemen; and in the second place, he is of opinion  that he is one of them

himself.  But some day he will know what is the  meaning of defamation, and  if he ever does, he will forgive

me.  Meanwhile I will return to you, Meno;  for I suppose that there are  gentlemen in your region too? 

MENO: Certainly there are. 

SOCRATES: And are they willing to teach the young? and do  they profess to  be teachers? and do they agree

that virtue is taught? 

MENO: No indeed, Socrates, they are anything but agreed; you  may hear them  saying at one time that virtue

can be taught, and then  again the reverse. 

SOCRATES: Can we call those teachers who do not acknowledge  the  possibility of their own vocation? 

MENO: I think not, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: And what do you think of these Sophists, who are  the only  professors?  Do they seem to you to

be teachers of virtue? 


Meno

MENO 37



Top




Page No 40


MENO: I often wonder, Socrates, that Gorgias is never heard  promising to  teach virtue:  and when he hears

others promising he only  laughs at them;  but he thinks that men should be taught to speak. 

SOCRATES: Then do you not think that the Sophists are  teachers? 

MENO: I cannot tell you, Socrates; like the rest of the  world, I am in  doubt, and sometimes I think that they

are teachers and  sometimes not. 

SOCRATES: And are you aware that not you only and other  politicians have  doubts whether virtue can be

taught or not, but that  Theognis the poet says  the very same thing? 

MENO: Where does he say so? 

SOCRATES: In these elegiac verses (Theog.): 

'Eat and drink and sit with the mighty, and make yourself agreeable  to  them; for from the good you will learn

what is good, but if you mix  with  the bad you will lose the intelligence which you already have.' 

Do you observe that here he seems to imply that virtue can be  taught? 

MENO: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: But in some other verses he shifts about and says  (Theog.): 

'If understanding could be created and put into a man, then they'  (who were  able to perform this feat) 'would

have obtained great  rewards.' 

And again: 

'Never would a bad son have sprung from a good sire, for he would  have  heard the voice of instruction; but

not by teaching will you ever  make a  bad man into a good one.' 

And this, as you may remark, is a contradiction of the other. 

MENO: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: And is there anything else of which the professors  are affirmed  not only not to be teachers of

others, but to be ignorant  themselves, and  bad at the knowledge of that which they are professing  to teach? or

is  there anything about which even the acknowledged  'gentlemen' are sometimes  saying that 'this thing can be

taught,' and  sometimes the opposite?  Can  you say that they are teachers in any  true sense whose ideas are in

such  confusion? 

MENO: I should say, certainly not. 

SOCRATES: But if neither the Sophists nor the gentlemen are  teachers,  clearly there can be no other

teachers? 

MENO: No. 

SOCRATES: And if there are no teachers, neither are there  disciples? 


Meno

MENO 38



Top




Page No 41


MENO: Agreed. 

SOCRATES: And we have admitted that a thing cannot be taught  of which  there are neither teachers nor

disciples? 

MENO: We have. 

SOCRATES: And there are no teachers of virtue to be found  anywhere? 

MENO: There are not. 

SOCRATES: And if there are no teachers, neither are there  scholars? 

MENO: That, I think, is true. 

SOCRATES: Then virtue cannot be taught? 

MENO: Not if we are right in our view.  But I cannot  believe, Socrates,  that there are no good men:  And if

there are, how  did they come into  existence? 

SOCRATES: I am afraid, Meno, that you and I are not good for  much, and  that Gorgias has been as poor an

educator of you as Prodicus  has been of  me.  Certainly we shall have to look to ourselves, and try  to find some

one  who will help in some way or other to improve us.  This I say, because I  observe that in the previous

discussion none of  us remarked that right and  good action is possible to man under other  guidance than that

of knowledge  (episteme);and indeed if this be  denied, there is no seeing how there can  be any good men at

all. 

MENO: How do you mean, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: I mean that good men are necessarily useful or  profitable.  Were  we not right in admitting this?

It must be so. 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And in supposing that they will be useful only if  they are true  guides to us of actionthere we

were also right? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But when we said that a man cannot be a good guide  unless he  have knowledge (phrhonesis),

this we were wrong. 

MENO: What do you mean by the word 'right'? 

SOCRATES: I will explain.  If a man knew the way to Larisa,  or anywhere  else, and went to the place and

led others thither, would  he not be a right  and good guide? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And a person who had a right opinion about the  way, but had  never been and did not know,

might be a good guide also,  might he not? 


Meno

MENO 39



Top




Page No 42


MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And while he has true opinion about that which the  other knows,  he will be just as good a

guide if he thinks the truth,  as he who knows the  truth? 

MENO: Exactly. 

SOCRATES: Then true opinion is as good a guide to correct  action as  knowledge; and that was the point

which we omitted in our  speculation about  the nature of virtue, when we said that knowledge  only is the

guide of  right action; whereas there is also right  opinion. 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: Then right opinion is not less useful than  knowledge? 

MENO: The difference, Socrates, is only that he who has  knowledge will  always be right; but he who has

right opinion will  sometimes be right, and  sometimes not. 

SOCRATES: What do you mean?  Can he be wrong who has right  opinion, so  long as he has right opinion? 

MENO: I admit the cogency of your argument, and therefore,  Socrates, I  wonder that knowledge should be

preferred to right  opinionor why they  should ever differ. 

SOCRATES: And shall I explain this wonder to you? 

MENO: Do tell me. 

SOCRATES: You would not wonder if you had ever observed the  images of  Daedalus (Compare

Euthyphro); but perhaps you have not got  them in your  country? 

MENO: What have they to do with the question? 

SOCRATES: Because they require to be fastened in order to  keep them, and  if they are not fastened they

will play truant and run  away. 

MENO: Well, what of that? 

SOCRATES: I mean to say that they are not very valuable  possessions if  they are at liberty, for they will

walk off like  runaway slaves; but when  fastened, they are of great value, for they  are really beautiful works of

art.  Now this is an illustration of the  nature of true opinions:  while  they abide with us they are beautiful  and

fruitful, but they run away out  of the human soul, and do not  remain long, and therefore they are not of  much

value until they are  fastened by the tie of the cause; and this  fastening of them, friend  Meno, is recollection,

as you and I have agreed  to call it.  But when  they are bound, in the first place, they have the  nature of

knowledge;  and, in the second place, they are abiding.  And this  is why knowledge  is more honourable and

excellent than true opinion,  because fastened  by a chain. 

MENO: What you are saying, Socrates, seems to be very like  the truth. 

SOCRATES: I too speak rather in ignorance; I only  conjecture.  And yet  that knowledge differs from true

opinion is no  matter of conjecture with  me.  There are not many things which I  profess to know, but this is

most  certainly one of them. 


Meno

MENO 40



Top




Page No 43


MENO: Yes, Socrates; and you are quite right in saying so. 

SOCRATES: And am I not also right in saying that true  opinion leading the  way perfects action quite as

well as knowledge? 

MENO: There again, Socrates, I think you are right. 

SOCRATES: Then right opinion is not a whit inferior to  knowledge, or less  useful in action; nor is the man

who has right  opinion inferior to him who  has knowledge? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: And surely the good man has been acknowledged by  us to be  useful? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Seeing then that men become good and useful to  states, not only  because they have

knowledge, but because they have  right opinion, and that  neither knowledge nor right opinion is given  to man

by nature or acquired  by him(do you imagine either of them to  be given by nature? 

MENO: Not I.) 

SOCRATES: Then if they are not given by nature, neither are  the good by  nature good? 

MENO: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: And nature being excluded, then came the question  whether virtue  is acquired by teaching? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: If virtue was wisdom (or knowledge), then, as we  thought, it was  taught? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if it was taught it was wisdom? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And if there were teachers, it might be taught;  and if there  were no teachers, not? 

MENO: True. 

SOCRATES: But surely we acknowledged that there were no  teachers of  virtue? 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then we acknowledged that it was not taught, and  was not wisdom? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And yet we admitted that it was a good? 


Meno

MENO 41



Top




Page No 44


MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the right guide is useful and good? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And the only right guides are knowledge and true  opinionthese  are the guides of man; for

things which happen by  chance are not under the  guidance of man:  but the guides of man are  true opinion and

knowledge. 

MENO: I think so too. 

SOCRATES: But if virtue is not taught, neither is virtue  knowledge. 

MENO: Clearly not. 

SOCRATES: Then of two good and useful things, one, which is  knowledge, has  been set aside, and cannot

be supposed to be our guide  in political life. 

MENO: I think not. 

SOCRATES: And therefore not by any wisdom, and not because  they were wise,  did Themistocles and those

others of whom Anytus spoke  govern states.  This  was the reason why they were unable to make  others like

themselvesbecause  their virtue was not grounded on  knowledge. 

MENO: That is probably true, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: But if not by knowledge, the only alternative  which remains is  that statesmen must have

guided states by right  opinion, which is in  politics what divination is in religion; for  diviners and also

prophets say  many things truly, but they know not  what they say. 

MENO: So I believe. 

SOCRATES: And may we not, Meno, truly call those men  'divine' who, having  no understanding, yet

succeed in many a grand  deed and word? 

MENO: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then we shall also be right in calling divine  those whom we were  just now speaking of as

diviners and prophets,  including the whole tribe of  poets.  Yes, and statesmen above all may  be said to be

divine and  illumined, being inspired and possessed of  God, in which condition they say  many grand things,

not knowing what  they say. 

MENO: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the women too, Meno, call good men divinedo  they not? and  the Spartans, when they

praise a good man, say 'that he  is a divine man.' 

MENO: And I think, Socrates, that they are right; although  very likely our  friend Anytus may take offence at

the word. 


Meno

MENO 42



Top




Page No 45


SOCRATES: I do not care; as for Anytus, there will be  another opportunity  of talking with him.  To sum up

our enquirythe  result seems to be, if we  are at all right in our view, that virtue is  neither natural nor

acquired,  but an instinct given by God to the  virtuous.  Nor is the instinct  accompanied by reason, unless there

may  be supposed to be among statesmen  some one who is capable of educating  statesmen.  And if there be

such an  one, he may be said to be among  the living what Homer says that Tiresias  was among the dead, 'he

alone  has understanding; but the rest are flitting  shades'; and he and his  virtue in like manner will be a reality

among  shadows. 

MENO: That is excellent, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Then, Meno, the conclusion is that virtue comes to  the virtuous  by the gift of God.  But we

shall never know the certain  truth until,  before asking how virtue is given, we enquire into the  actual nature of

virtue.  I fear that I must go away, but do you, now  that you are persuaded  yourself, persuade our friend

Anytus.  And do  not let him be so  exasperated; if you can conciliate him, you will  have done good service to

the Athenian people. 


Meno

MENO 43



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. Meno, page = 4

   3. Plato, page = 4

   4. INTRODUCTION., page = 4

   5. ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO., page = 9

   6. MENO, page = 15